Preface
We have already published treatises on the One God, the Triune God, the
Creator, and the Holy Eucharist. These have been presented in the form of a
commentary on the teaching of St. Thomas in his Theological Summa. It is the
purpose of the present treatise on Christ the Savior to explain, in accordance
with the more common interpretation of the Thomists, the teaching of St. Thomas
on the motive of the Incarnation, the hypostatic union, and its effects. We have
discussed at length the more difficult problems, such as the reconciliation of
freedom with absolute impeccability in Christ, the intrinsically infinite value
of His merits and satisfaction, His predestination with reference to ours,
inasmuch as He is the first of the predestined, and the reconciliation, during
the Passion, of the presence of extreme sorrow with supreme happiness
experienced by our Lord in the summit of His soul.
In all these problems our wish has been to manifest the unity of Christ
inasmuch as He is one personal Being, although He has two really distinct and
infinitely different natures. Hence the Person of Christ constitutes the one and
only principle of all His theandric operations.
In all these questions St. Thomas, according to his custom, wonderfully
preserved the principle of economy[1] by reducing all things to the same
principles and in the ultimate analysis to the one and only fundamental
principle. Similarly, with reference to the Passion everything is reduced to the
principle of the plenitude of grace. This plenitude, on the one hand, was the
cause in the summit of our Lord's soul of the beatific vision and, on the other
hand, it was the cause of His most ardent love as priest and victim, so that He
willed to be overwhelmed with grief, and die on the cross a most perfect
holocaust.
At the end of this treatise we have given merely a compendium on Mariology,
since a more complete commentary on this subject has recently been published by
us in the French language.
May the reading of these pages be a source of knowledge as well as of
spiritual benefit to all students of theology.
THE THIRD PART OF ST THOMAS' THEOLOGICAL SUMMA
Prologue
In this prologue St. Thomas shows the place assigned to this treatise in his
Theological Summa, according to the division made by him at the beginning of
this work, in which he had said: "Because the chief aim of sacred doctrine
is to teach the knowledge of God, not only as He is in Himself, but also as He
is in the beginning of things and their last end, and especially of rational
creatures... we shall treat:
(1) "Of God (one in nature and triune in persons, and inasmuch as He is
the principle of creatures); (2) of the rational advance of creatures toward God
(or of God as He is the end of the rational creature); (3) of Christ, who as man
is our way to God."[2]
In the present treatise he says: "Because our Savior the Lord Jesus
Christ in order to save His people from their sins, as the angel announced,
showed unto us in His own person the way of truth, whereby we may attain to the
bliss of eternal life by rising again, it is necessary... that, after
consideration of the last end of human life, and the virtues and vices, there
should follow a consideration of the Savior of all and of the benefits bestowed
by Him on the human race."[3]
Some theologians prefer another division to that made by St Thomas, in which
the distinction between dogmatic theology and moral theology is more in
evidence, so that moral theology is not placed between the treatises on the One
God and the Word incarnate. Furthermore, they remark that the treatise on the
Word incarnate because of its dignity justly comes immediately after the
treatise on the one and triune God.
To this the Thomists reply that, according to St. Thomas, dogmatic theology
and moral theology are not two distinct sciences, but two parts of the same
science, similar to the science of God of which it is a participation.[4] The
unity of this science results from the unity of its formal object both quod and
quo.[5] Its formal object quod, or the subject of this science, is God Himself
considered in Himself, or as He is the principle and end of creatures. The
formal object quo is virtual revelation by the light of which are deduced both
in dogmatic theology and moral theology the conclusions that are virtually
contained in the revealed principles. Therefore dogmatic and moral theology are
not two sciences, but two parts of the same science.
They also remark that, although this treatise on the Savior, because of its
dignity, precedes the moral part of theology, nevertheless, in the orderly
arrangement of knowledge, it is justly placed after the other parts of theology,
and this especially for three reasons: (1) because the simpler things come
before the composite. In the preceding parts of the Summa, however, what
pertains to God and to man are discussed separately, whereas the present
treatise is concerned with Him who is both God and man.[6] (2) The work of
redemption presupposes also that man lived for a long period of time under the
law of the Old Testament, as well as it presupposes acts of faith and other
virtues necessary in the various states of life. Hence St. Thomas appropriately
places this treatise on the Savior at the end of his Summa. (3) Moreover, it
must be noticed that what is necessary precedes what is contingent. But in the
two preceding parts of the Theological Summa, what forms the subject of special
discussion is the nature of God, and the nature of both angels and man with
reference to God; whereas the Third Part of the Summa considers the great
contingent fact which did not have to be realized, namely, that the Word was
made flesh. This fact, although it is the greatest of all historical facts in
the universe, is a contingent fact; for it is not something absolutely
necessary, such as the divine nature for God and also the human nature for man.
For this reason, certain philosophers, even certain mystics, desired to reach
union with God, not by way of Christ the universal mediator, although He had
said: "I am the way and the truth and the life."[7] These persons did
not grasp the practical import of the statement that Christ, or the Word of God
incarnate, is the exemplar and source of all virtues, without whom nobody can
acquire salvation and sanctity.
This deviation from the common method of approach to God is in itself
manifestly in opposition to the great truth, namely, that these persons somehow
overlooked the fact of the Incarnation, inasmuch as it is not an absolutely
necessary fact, and they failed to see that precisely because it is contingent,
it becomes, in some aspect, a fact of the greatest importance, inasmuch as it is
a transcendent manifestation of God's most free and absolutely gratuitous love
for the human race. St. John testifies that: "God so loved the world as to
give His only-begotten Son."[8] He also says: "He hath first loved us,
and sent His Son to be a propitiation for our sins."[9] In fact, these
texts express the fundamental truth of Christianity, which is that God, by a
most free act of His love, sent His divine Son to us. Hence the entire third
part of the Theological Summa of St. Thomas is a detailed narrative of God's
gratuitous love for us confirmed by the text: "God so loved the world, as
to give His only-begotten Son."[10] It is truly a complete description of
this gratuitous love as being the motive of God's mercy, and of the efficacy of
this love. It is a canticle of God's gratuitous love for the human race. Thus
the contingency of this most prominent fact in the history of the human race
does not lessen its importance, but it manifests, on the contrary, the supreme
gratuitousness of God's most free love for us.
Indeed, this manifestation of love is of such excellence that, in these days,
even the more obnoxious enemies of the Church, such as several idealists,
disciples of Hegel and Renan, who deny the existence of a true God really and
essentially distinct from the world, say that Christ was the noblest of all men
and that nobody was a better type of the evolution of the human race. So wrote
Renan.[11] In fact, several communists in these days say the same, and they
furthermore remark that this evolution of the human race predicted by Christ can
be realized only by communism. Thus, presenting Christ in an entirely false
light, whether they wish it or not, they confess that the greatest event in the
history of the human race was the coming of Christ. But before this statement
about Christ can be understood, one must have a correct notion of both God and
man. Hence this treatise on the Incarnation is logically placed in the third
part of the Theological Summa.
From the prologue we see that St. Thomas divides the third part of his Summa
by considering: (1) the Savior Himself; (2) the sacraments by which we attain to
our salvation; (3) the end of immortal life to which we attain by the
resurrection.
Thus it is evident that the third part of the Summa is a treatise on the
Savior, and the benefits He bestowed on us by instituting the sacraments and
enabling us to get to heaven, which is our last end.
The treatise on the Savior is divided into two parts.
Part I discusses the mystery itself of the Incarnation (q. 1-26).
Part II discusses the actions and sufferings of our Savior or the mysteries
of the life of Christ (q. 27-59).
The first part is often called, in our days, Christology, and the second part
is known as soteriology. The mystery of the Incarnation is the principal topic
of discussion in the first part, and in the second part St. Thomas considers the
mystery of Redemption, in which he discusses especially the passion of Christ
(q. 46-52).
The first part of the mystery of the Incarnation contains three sections:
1) The fitness of the Incarnation, in which it is discussed as a historical
fact (q. 1).
2) The mode of union of the Word incarnate is considered (q. 2-15). The union
itself (q. 2), the union in its relation to the person assuming (q. 3), and then
on the part of the nature assumed and its perfections, the grace, knowledge, and
powers of Christ are discussed (q. 4-15).
3) The consequences of the union with reference to what belongs to Christ are
here discussed: (1) in themselves (q. 16-19); (2) in their relation to the
Father, in which the predestination of Christ is considered; (3) with reference
to us, in which our adoration of Christ and His office of Mediator are discussed
(q. 25-26).
The second part is concerned with the mysteries of the life of Christ, and is
divided into four sections: (1) the coming of Christ into the world, which
includes Mariology; (2) His life on earth in its gradual development; (3) the
end of His life, or His passion and death; (4) His exaltation, or His
resurrection and ascension.
This second part which is entitled, The Mystery of Redemption, will be a
brief treatise on the Passion, as it is the cause of our salvation, the
vicarious satisfaction of Christ, its infinite value, Christ's victory, and also
Christ as king, judge, and head of the blessed. Finally there will be a
compendium on Mariology.
It must be noticed that among the commentators of the Summa John of St.
Thomas discusses the satisfaction of Christ at the beginning of His commentary,
by considering the fittingness of the Incarnation, inasmuch as the Son of God
came down from heaven for our salvation, namely, to redeem the human race. This
arrangement is, indeed, appropriate for a complete understanding of the thesis
on the motive of the Incarnation. However, in the doctrinal order, so far as
operation follows being, St. Thomas is justified in discussing the Incarnation
before the Redemption, or before the theandric act of the love of Christ
suffering for us. Probably the reason why John of St. Thomas discussed at length
the satisfaction of Christ at the beginning of his commentary, is that it ends
with the twenty-fourth question in the Summa of St. Thomas.
Billuart, however, developed his thesis on the satisfaction of Christ in
connection with the merit of Christ, which is question nineteen in the Summa of
St. Thomas, at the same time discussing the infinite value of the merits of
Christ.
Following the arrangement of questions as given by St. Thomas, we shall
consider: (1) the mystery of the Incarnation; (2) the mystery of Redemption.
This is the method commonly adopted by theologians.
CHAPTER I: THE MYSTERY AND FACT OF THE INCARNATION
Preliminary Remarks
Before we come to explain the article of St. Thomas, we must set forth what
positive theology teaches on the fundamentals of this treatise. Speculative
theology, of course, begins with the articles of faith as defined by the Church,
and concerning these its method of procedure is twofold. In the first place it
gives a philosophical analysis of the terminology employed in these articles of
faith. Thus it shows the fittingness of the mysteries, the possibility of which
can neither be proved nor disproved. As the Vatican Council says: "Reason
enlightened by faith, when it seeks earnestly, piously, and calmly, attains by a
gift from God some, and that a very fruitful, understanding of mysteries; partly
from the analogy of those things which it naturally knows, partly from the
relations which the mysteries bear to one another and to the last end of
man."[12]
In the second place, speculative theology deduces from the principles of
faith conclusions that are virtually contained in the principles. In this way a
body of theological doctrine is established in which there is due subordination
of notions and truths, some of these being simply revealed, whereas others are
simply deduced from revealed principles. These latter truths do not properly
belong to the faith, but to theology as a science.
So does St. Thomas proceed, presupposing in the first article of this third
part of his Summa the dogma of the divinity of Christ as solemnly defined by the
Church. The positive theology of St. Thomas is found especially in his
commentaries on the Gospels and on the Epistles of St. Paul.
It is necessary, however, to begin with a chapter on positive theology, in
order to show that the definitions of the Church express what is already
contained more or less explicitly in the deposit of revelation, namely, in
Sacred Scripture and tradition.
On this point it must be carefully noted, as regards the method, that
positive theology, being a part of sacred theology, differs from mere history,
inasmuch as per se or essentially it presupposes infused faith concerning divine
revelation, as contained in Sacred Scripture and tradition, and faithfully and
infallibly preserved and explained by the Church.
Thus positive theology differs from the history of dogmas, for this latter
views them solely according to the rational exigencies of the historical method.
Positive theology, under the positive and intrinsic direction of the faith,
makes use of history, just as speculative theology makes use of philosophy, but
in each case as a subsidiary science.
This means that positive theology, in studying the documents of Scripture and
tradition, presupposes not only rational criticism and exegesis, as Father
Zapletal ably points out,[13] but also Christian criticism and exegesis, which
acknowledges the dogma of inspiration. It presupposes, too, Catholic
interpretation of Scripture and tradition, which admits not only the dogma of
inspiration, but also the authority of the Church in determining the true sense
of Sacred Scripture and tradition, as also the authority of the Fathers and the
analogy of faith, as Leo XIII explains in his encyclical Providentissimus Deus.
In this encyclical he writes: "In the other passages, the analogy of faith
should be followed, and Catholic doctrine, as authoritatively proposed by the
Church, should be held as the supreme law.... Hence it is apparent that all
interpretation is foolish and false which either makes the sacred writers
disagree with one another, or is opposed to the doctrine of the
Church."[14] In accordance with the analogy of faith, an obscure text in
Sacred Scripture is to be explained by other texts that are clearer or more
explicit.
This method appears to be most reasonable, since even in human affairs, if we
wish to put a correct interpretation on the historical documents of any nation
or family, their traditions must be considered, for these are always a living
quasi-commentary of these documents, so that an interpretation of these
documents which results in their being contradictory to the living tradition of
the people should be rejected as false.
Thus not only rational but also Christian and Catholic exegesis must admit
the canon of the books of Sacred Scripture, together with the text, which have
been approved by the Church, and also the documents of tradition preserved in
her archives.
Thus Catholic exegesis considers the books of Scripture not only as
historical works written by certain authors, such as the Gospel written by St.
Matthew, or that by St. Mark, but it also considers them as divine books that
have God as their author, the preservation of which pertains to the Church; and
it reads these books not only by the light of natural reason but also by the
supernatural light of infused faith. Catholic exegesis, of course, makes use of
the natural branches of knowledge, languages, for instance, but it subordinates
these to a higher light and to the principles of faith.
Hence the Vatican Council, in recalling the decree of the Council of Trent,
says: "In matters of faith and morals... that is to be held as the true
sense of Holy Scripture, which our holy Mother the Church has held and
holds."[15]
Finally, as Father Zapletal remarks,[16] the sacred authors sometimes did not
fully understand the meaning which the Holy Spirit intended to convey by the
words, that is, they did not always completely grasp the literal and objective
sense of the words, as can be concluded from what St. Peter says about the
prophets.[17]
In fact, St. Thomas says: "Sometimes he who is prompted to write
something does not understand the meaning the Holy Spirit intends to convey by
what he writes, as is evident in the case of Caiphas, who said: 'It is expedient
for you that one man should die for the people.’ Then it is a case more of
prophetic instinct than of prophecy."[18]
This observation may prove useful in connection with the question of the
divinity of Christ as literally expressed in the Synoptic Gospels. Having
completed these preliminary remarks, let us pass on to consider the testimony of
Christ Himself as contained in the Gospels.
First Article: Christ's Testimony Of Himself And Primarily Of His Messianic
Dignity
State Of The Question.
In our days what claims first attention is the opinion that Modernists and a
number of liberal Protestants have about Christ. What they think is known from
the propositions condemned in the decree Lamentabili.[19] Some of these read:
"The divinity of Jesus Christ is not proved from the Gospels, but it is a
dogma deduced by the Christian conscience from the notion of the Messias"
(prop. 27). "In all the Gospel texts the expression 'Son of God' is
equivalent merely to the name 'Messias'; it does not at all, however, signify
that Christ is the true and natural Son of God" (prop. 30). "The
doctrine of the sacrificial death of Christ is not evangelical, but originated
with St. Paul" (prop. 38).
A number of rationalists, such as Renan, B. Weiss, H. Wendt, Harnack,
recognize some divine sonship in Christ that is superior to His Messiahship, but
they deny that Jesus, in virtue of this sonship, was truly God.[20]
Among conservative Protestants, however, several, such as F. Godet in
Switzerland, Stevens and Sanday in England, defended in recent times the
divinity of Christ, not only from the Fourth Gospel and the Epistles of St.
Paul, but even from the Synoptic Gospels.[21]
Let us first briefly review what the Gospels say about the Messiahship of
Christ; a fuller account will be given afterward of His divinity as recorded in
the New Testament.
It has already been shown in apologetics by the historical method, that is by
considering the Gospels as historical narratives, though not in this connection,
as being inspired, that Christ very plainly affirmed Himself to be the Messias
announced by the prophets. A few rationalists, such as Wellhausen, deny that
Christ said He was the Messias; but very many rationalists, such as Harnack and
O. Holzmann, acknowledge that Jesus affirmed His Messiahship, and Loisy admits
that Jesus, not at the beginning of His public life but toward its end, taught
that He was the Messias.[22] The Gospel texts in which the Messiahship is
affirmed are quoted in all works on apologetics.[23] The principal texts are
given below.
From the beginning of His ministry, Jesus testified that He was the
ambassador of God, and later on much more explicitly He asserted that He was the
Messias and the Savior.
This He affirmed both publicly and privately.
Publicly (1) He declared His mission as teacher and Messias, when the
Evangelist says of Him: "He began preaching the Gospel of the kingdom of
God. And saying: The time is accomplished, and the kingdom of God is at hand;
repent, and believe the Gospel."[24] In choosing His apostles, He said:
"Come ye after Me and I will make you to be fishers of men."[25]
"And Jesus went about all Galilee, teaching in their synagogues, and
preaching the Gospel of the kingdom, and healing all manner of sickness and
every infirmity among the people."[26]
In the Sermon on the Mount, Jesus perfects the Mosaic law in His own name,
asserting many times: "It was said to them of old.... But I say to
you."[27] At the end of this Sermon, we read: "For He was teaching
them as one having power, and not as the scribes and Pharisees."[28]
2) Jesus replied to the scribes and Pharisees that He is the "Lord of
the sabbath,"[29] "greater than Jonas and Solomon,"[30] greater
than David.[31]
3) Likewise, in the synagogue at Nazareth, after Jesus had read the words of
Isaias concerning the future Messias: "The spirit of the Lord is upon me.
Wherefore He hath anointed me to preach the gospel to the poor, to heal the
contrite of heart," we read farther on that "He began to say to them:
This day is fulfilled this Scripture in your ears."[32] When the people did
not believe, and said: "Is not this the Son of Joseph?" Jesus replied:
"Amen I say to you that no prophet is accepted in his own
country."[33]
4) Jesus declared His Messiahship even in plain words, after He cured the
paralytic in a certain house at Capharnaum, on the Sabbath. The Jews accused Him
of blasphemy, and He replied: "But that you may know that the Son of man
hath power on earth to forgive sins, then He said to the man sick of the palsy:
Arise, take up thy bed and go into thy house. And he arose and went into his
house."[34] Christ claimed for Himself all rights pertaining to the
Messiahship, such as the power of doing what His Father does, raising the dead
to life, judging all men, and bringing those faithful to Him to eternal
life.[35]
Privately. Jesus preferred to make known His Messiahship when speaking more
intimately to His apostles.
1) In the beginning, after John the Baptist had given his testimony, and
Jesus had spoken to others for the first time, Andrew says to his brother:
"We have found the Messias."[36] Philip and Nathanael had similar
experiences.[37]
2) Jesus said to His twelve apostles: "And going, preach, saying: The
kingdom of heaven is at hand. Heal the sick, raise the dead.... He that
receiveth you receiveth Me, and he that receiveth Me receiveth Him that sent
Me."[38] "He that despiseth Me despiseth Him that sent Me."[39]
3) To the disciples of John the Baptist asking: "Art Thou He that art to
come, or look we for another?" Jesus replied: "Go and relate to John
what you have heard and seen. The blind see, the lame walk, the lepers are
cleansed, the deaf hear, the dead rise again, the poor have the gospel preached
to them."[40] This text, however, is manifestly the fulfillment of the
prophecy by Isaias, which the Jews understood as referring to the Messias.[41]
4) The first time that Jesus came to Jerusalem, He conversed with Nicodemus,
one of the rulers of the Jews, and declared to him: "No man hath ascended
into heaven, but He that descended from heaven, the Son of man who is in
heaven.... For God so loved the world, as to give His only-begotten Son; that
whosoever believeth in Him, may not perish, but may have life
everlasting."[42] It is most evident from this answer that Jesus teaches
His Messiahship, in fact, His divine sonship.
5) Jesus spoke similarly to the Samaritan woman, who says to Him: "I
know that the Messias cometh (who is called Christ) "; Jesus says to her:
"I am He who am speaking with thee."[43] After the Samaritans had
heard Jesus, they said: "We ourselves have heard Him, and know that this is
indeed the Savior of the world."[44]
All the preceding testimony, however, belongs to the beginning of Jesus'
ministry; but toward the end of His life He speaks more explicitly not only to
His apostles but also to the people.
The Last Year Of His Life
1) As Jesus was approaching the city of Caesarea Philippi, He asks a
question, and receives from Peter this answer: "Thou art Christ the Son of
the living God."[45] These words at least signify that Jesus is truly the
Messias, and they are approved by Christ as being inspired by His heavenly
Father.
2) On the festival day of the Jews, Jesus says to them: "My doctrine is
not Mine, but His that sent Me."[46] The next day Jesus says to the Jews:
"I am the light of the world.... I give testimony of Myself... and the
Father that sent Me giveth testimony of Me."[47]
3) On the occasion of Jesus' triumphal entry into Jerusalem, as the crowd was
shouting: "Blessed is He that cometh in the name of the Lord.... Hosannah
in the highest,"[48] Jesus said to the Pharisees: "If these shall hold
their peace, the stones will cry out."[49]
4) During the Passion, Jesus affirms before the Sanhedrim that He is the
Christ, the Son of God. Thus at least He declared His Messiahship.[50]
5) After the Resurrection, Jesus said to the disciples on their way to
Emmaus: "Ought not Christ to have suffered all these things, and so to
enter into His glory?"[51] Similarly, Jesus said to the eleven apostles:
"As the Father hath sent Me, I also send you."[52]
Conclusion. All this testimony, as Harnack[53] acknowledges against
Wellhausen, is so interconnected with the entire Gospel narrative. that without
it there would be almost nothing left that is historical in the life of Jesus,
and His death could by no means be explained. There was also no time for a
gradual idealization of Jesus' life, for the apostles already from the day of
Pentecost taught that Jesus is the Messias and the Author of life.[54]
It must be noted that, theologically speaking, it is hard to determine in the
Gospel texts when the expression of complete Messianic dignity ceases, and that
of the divine sonship of Christ begins. The reason is that Jesus is called the
Messias, or Christ, because He is the anointed of God. But the principal source
of His anointing comes from the grace of union, by which His humanity is
personally united to the Word, and by which He is therefore the Son of God.
Hence, among the prophets and apostles, those who were more illuminated
concerning the sublimity of the Messianic dignity already had a confused
knowledge of the dignity of divine sonship.
Second Article: Testimony Of Christ And The Apostles Concerning The Divine
Sonship
State of the question. Several rationalists, such as Renan, B. Weiss, H.
Wendt, and Harnack, recognize some divine sonship in Christ that is superior to
His Messiahship, but they deny that Jesus, in virtue of His sonship, is truly
God.[55]
Several conservative Protestants, such as F. Godet, and in England, Stevens,
Gore, Ottley, and Sanday, recently defended the divinity of Christ not only from
the Fourth Gospel and the Epistles of St. Paul, but even from the Synoptic
Gospels.[56]
Moreover, the Church declared against the Modernists, that the divinity of
Christ is proved from the Gospels. Thus several of their propositions were
condemned in the decree Lamentabili.[57]
Let us see what the Synoptic Gospels, the Gospel of St. John, and the
Epistles of St. Paul say about the mystery of the Incarnation.[58]
For the state of the question it must be observed that Jesus is called the
Son of God fifty times. The question is: In what sense is this expression to be
understood?
In the Scripture, "son" is predicated in two ways. In the strict
and literal sense it signifies a living being that proceeds from a living
principle in conformity with the laws of nature. In the broad and metaphorical
sense it denotes a disciple or an adopted heir. The term, with reference to God,
also has two meanings. In the broad sense it is predicated of men who
participate in the spirit and life of God, so that Christians are called
"sons of God";[59] in the strict and proper sense, it is predicated of
the Second Person of the Trinity, as in the text: "the only-begotten Son
who is in the bosom of the Father."[60]
This expression "Son of God" sometimes perhaps in the Gospel means
no more that Messias, when it is predicated of Jesus, for instance, by those who
do not yet seem to know that He is by nature divine.[61] But from the Synoptic
Gospels it is certain that Jesus said He was the Son of God in the proper,
strict and most sublime sense of the term, inasmuch as He possesses the divine
nature and is not merely a participator or partaker of this nature by grace.[62]
Christ Testifies To His Divinity In The Synoptic Gospels[63]
There are two ways by which Jesus in the Synoptic Gospels gradually declares
His divine nature. (1) He claims rights or privileges that belong only to God.
(2) He affirms that He is the Son of God. This gradual development is seen also
as regards His Messiahship, which on several occasions is more affirmed as it is
more denied or disbelieved by the Pharisees. The divine affirmation of these
rights for the salvation of souls is intensified in proportion as the Pharisees
increasingly resist these claims.
Moreover, we get a clearer insight into the sublime meaning of these words of
Christ in proportion as the gift of infused faith increases within us, just as
the validity of the first principles of reason and of being is more fully
realized in proportion as the ability of metaphysical argumentation or the power
of intellectual penetration increases within us. The scriptural texts that we
shall now quote are considered by students of apologetics as it were from
without, but in theology they are considered as it were from within, just as
there are two ways of viewing the paintings on the windows of churches, either
from the outside; or from within the church and thus in their true light, and
then they are seen with better effect, and there is a realization of their
value.
A. Christ attributed to Himself divine rights. The seven principal ones are
these.
1) Jesus testified of Himself that He is greater than any creature. He is
greater than Jonas and Solomon,[64] greater than David who called Him Lord,[65]
greater than Moses and Elias who were present with Him on the day of the
Transfiguration.[66] He is greater than John the Baptist, greater than the
angels, because "the angels ministered to Him"[67] after His
temptation in the desert, and they are His angels, for we read: "The Son of
man shall send His angels and they shall gather together His elect."[68]
2) He speaks as the supreme Legislator, absolutely equal in authority to the
divine author of the Old Law, which He completes and perfects, purging it of the
false rabbinical interpretations, repeatedly saying: "It was said to them
of old... but I say to you."[69] He forbids divorce to the Jews, which
Moses permitted because of the hardness of their heart.[70] He says that He is
the Lord of the Sabbath.[71]
3) He claims the right of forgiving sins, which the Jews considered a divine
privilege. This is evident from the answer Jesus gave to the Jews when He
miraculously cured the paralytic, saying: "But that you may know that the
Son of man hath on earth to forgive sins, then He said to the man sick of the
palsy: 'Arise, take up thy bed, and go into thy house. "[72] He even claims
the right of communicating to others this power of forgiving sins, saying:
"Whatsoever you shall bind upon earth, shall be bound also in
heaven."[73]
4) He performs miracles in His own name, commanding the paralytic and the
dead, saving: "Arise."[74] On the occasion of the storm at sea, He
said: "Peace, be still. And the wind ceased."[75] On the contrary,
others perform miracles in the name of Jesus, saying: "We have done many
miracles in Thy name."[76]
5) He demands that all believe in, obey, and love Him in preference to all
other affections, even at the cost of their life. "He that loveth father or
mother more than Me is not worthy of Me; and he that loveth son or daughter more
than Me, is not worthy of Me."[77] These words would express odious and
intolerable pride if Jesus were not God. The prophets never spoke in this
manner. There are similar texts in the Gospels.[78]
6) He assigns to Himself the power of judging the living and the dead.
"You shall see the Son of man sitting on the right hand of the power of God
and coming with the clouds of heaven."[79] "And He shall send His
angels with a trumpet, and a great voice, and they shall gather together His
elect from the four winds, from the farthest parts of the heavens to the utmost
bounds of them."[80]
7) He promises to send the Holy Ghost. "And I send the promise of My
Father upon you."[81] Lastly, He accepts adoration from others; whereas, on
the contrary, Peter, Paul, Barnabas, and the angels reject this adoration as
being unworthy of it.[82]
B. In the Synoptic Gospels, Jesus affirms several times that He is the Son of
God in the proper and strict sense of the term.[83] There are six principal
texts, which shall be set forth in chronological order.
1) "All things are delivered to Me by My Father. And no one knoweth the
Son, but the Father; neither cloth anyone know the Father, but the Son, and he
to whom it shall please the Son to reveal Him."[84]
The authenticity of this text is admitted by the majority of Protestant
critics, and it is most ably defended by Catholic authors.[85] This text
declares the equality of the Father and the Son both in knowledge and
knowability. But this equality implies consubstantiality, as St. Thomas remarks,
saying: "The substance of the Father transcends all understanding, since
the essence of the Father is said to be unknowable as the substance of the Son
is."[86] The Son is known only by the Father; therefore, like the Father,
He exceeds all created knowledge, and hence is God. The above-mentioned
scriptural text is substantially the same in meaning as when it is said:
"No man hath seen God at any time; the only-begotten Son who is in the
bosom of the Father, He hath declared Him."[87] These two texts are equally
profound and identical in meaning, as several critics admit.
2) Christ's answer to Peter's confession. Peter said: "Thou art Christ,
the Son of the living God." Jesus answering, said to him: "Blessed art
thou, Simon Bar-Jona, because flesh and blood hath not revealed it to thee, but
My Father who is in heaven."[88]
Some say that it cannot be historically proved from this confession that
Peter affirmed anything more than Christ's Messiahship, since elsewhere he is
quoted as saying merely: "Thou art the Christ,"[89] "Thou art the
Christ of God."[90] Nevertheless, something more than this is clearly
enough evident from Jesus' answer. For He says that Peter could not have known
His sonship unless it had been revealed to him. The mere knowledge of Christ's
Messiahship did not require so great a revelation, for the signs of Messiahship
were already made manifest to the apostles from the beginning of Jesus'
ministry, and several of them acknowledged it.[91]
3) Parable of the wicked husbandmen. The authenticity of this parable is
admitted by most of the critics, even by very many rationalists. The parable
says that the lord of the vineyard sent a servant to the husbandmen at the time
of the harvest, then another, and many more, some of whom they beat, and others
they killed. "Having yet one son, most dear to him, he also sent him unto
them last of all, saying: They will reverence my son. But the husbandmen said to
one another: This is the heir; come, let us kill him, and the inheritance shall
be ours. And laying hold on him, they killed him and cast him out of the
vineyard. What therefore will the lord of the vineyard do? He will come and
destroy those husbandmen and will give the vineyard to others. And have you not
read this scripture: The stone which the builders rejected, the same is made the
head of the corner? By the Lord has this been done, and it is wonderful in our
eyes. And they sought to lay hands on Him, but they feared the people. For they
knew that He spoke this parable to them. And leaving Him they went their
way."[92]
The application of this parable was manifest. The servants sent by the Lord
of the vineyard were the prophets, and Jesus stated this more clearly to the
Pharisees later on.[93] If, therefore, the servants of the Lord's vineyard are
the prophets, His beloved Son is not only more than a prophet, but is truly His
Son. Therefore this parable expresses absolutely the same truth as when St. Paul
says: "God, who at sundry times and in divers manners spoke in times past
to the fathers by the prophets, last of all in these days hath spoken to us by
His Son... by whom also He made the world."[94]
4) Jesus questions the Jews about Christ the son of David. "And the
Pharisees being gathered together, Jesus asked them, saying: 'What think you of
Christ, whose Son is He.’ They say to Him, 'David's.’ He saith to them: 'How
then doth David call Him Lord, how is He his Son?' And no man was able to answer
Him a word."[95]
The authenticity of this text is admitted by the prominent liberal critics.
But in the Messianic psalm just quoted, David, in calling the Messias "my
Lord," acknowledges that this Lord is superior to him and equal to the
first Lord, namely, to God the Father.
5) Jesus answers Caiphas. When Christ appeared before the Sanhedrim,
"the high priest said to Him: 'I adjure Thee by the living God, that Thou
tell us if Thou be the Christ the Son of God.’ Jesus saith to him: 'Thou hast
said it. Nevertheless, I say to you, hereafter you shall see the Son of man
sitting on the right hand of the power of God, and coming in the clouds of
heaven.’ Then the high priest rent his garments, saying: 'He hath blasphemed;
what further need have we of witnesses? Behold now you have heard the blasphemy.’"[96]
From this answer we see that Jesus is more than the Messias, for divine sonship,
sitting at the right hand of the Father, the exercise of supreme power, do not
belong to the simple dignity of Messiahship. That is why Caiphas rent his
garments, saying: "He hath blasphemed." These texts of the Synoptic
Gospels receive further clarification in the Fourth Gospel, in which we read
that, after Jesus had cured the paralytic at the Probatic pool, "the Jews
sought the more to kill Him, because He did not only break the Sabbath, but also
said God was His Father, making Himself equal to God."[97] Similarly, in
the history of the Passion we read: "The Jews answered Him: 'We have a law
and according to the law He ought to die, because He made Himself the Son of
God.’"[98] Hence the question put by Caiphas to Jesus was to get an
answer rendering Him guilty of death.[99]
6) The baptismal formula. After the Resurrection, we read in the Gospel:
"Jesus coming, spoke to them[His apostles], saying: 'All power is given to
Me in heaven and in earth. Going therefore teach ye all nations, baptizing them
in the name of the Father and of the Son and of the Holy Ghost. Teaching them to
observe all things whatsoever I have commanded you. And behold I am with you all
days, even to the consummation of the world.’"[100]
Even all liberal Protestants admit this formula,[101] and it was universally
accepted in the various Churches at the beginning of the second century. In this
baptismal formula the Son is declared equal to the Father and the Holy Spirit.
Conclusion. It must therefore be said, in refutation of the Modernists, that
the declarations of Jesus concerning His eminent dignity as recorded by the
Synoptics transcend simple Messiahship and express divine sonship that belongs
most properly to Christ. Moreover, this divine sonship is not only superior to
simple Messiahship, which is conceded, as has been said by several rationalists
of our times, such as Harnack, but it establishes Christ above all creatures as
equal to, and one in nature with God, the Second Person of the Trinity.
Testimony Of The Acts Of The Apostles Concerning The Divinity Of Christ
The more conservative Catholic and Protestant historians consider it more
probable that the Acts of the Apostles was written about A. D. 64 or, at least,
before the year 70.[102] The rationalists of the Tubingen school set the date at
A. D. 150. But, in our days, historical evidence made the rationalist Harnack
assign the date of this work to the years 78-83, or perhaps even to 60-70.[103]
From this it is evident that the above mentioned declarations of the Synoptic
Gospels were not the result of a certain process of idealization, gradually
evolved after Christ's death and ascribed to Him. The time required for this
idealization was too short, for it is certain that from the day of Pentecost the
apostles taught not only that Jesus was the Messias but also God.
The discourses of St. Peter are recorded in the Acts of the Apostles, in
which we read: "The God of Abraham and the God of Isaac and the God of
Jacob, the God of our fathers, hath glorified His Son Jesus, whom you indeed
delivered up.... But the Author of life you killed, whom God hath raised from
the dead, of which we are witnesses. And the faith which is by Him, hath given
this perfect soundness [the lame man who sat at the gate of the Temple] in the
sight of you all."[104]
The Author of life, however, is none other than God Himself. Likewise St.
Peter says: "This is the stone which was rejected by you the builders,
which is become the head of the corner. Neither is there salvation in any
other."[105] "God hath exalted Him [Jesus] with His right hand to be
Prince and Savior, to give repentance to Israel, and remission of sins.
"[106] But only God is the Savior of souls, forgiving persons their sins.
Similarly St. Peter says: "By the grace of the Lord Jesus Christ, we
believe to be saved."[107] Jesus is called by St. Peter
"Lord,"[108] "Lord to all,"[109] "He who was appointed
by God to be judge of the living and of the dead."[110] Finally, the
apostles work miracles in the name of Jesus, confer baptism; and the deacon St.
Stephen says, when dying: "Lord Jesus, receive my spirit."[111]
It is no matter of surprise, therefore, that when the Ebionites, who were the
first heretics, denied the divinity of Christ, they were immediately condemned
by the Church, as is evident from the writings of the Apostolic Fathers.
Testimony Of St. Paul On The Divinity Of Christ
The principal epistles of St. Paul[112] were written about A. D. 48-59 or
50-64, as several rationalists admit, among whom are Harnack and Julicher. In
these epistles, however, St. Paul, in affirming the divinity of Christ, does not
announce it to the Churches as an unheard-of innovation, but he speaks of it as
an already accepted dogmatic truth.
It will suffice if we give the principal references of St. Paul to the
divinity of Christ.
1) According to St. Paul, Jesus is the Son of God in the strict sense of the
term. He says of Him: "Who was predestinated the Son of God in power,
according to the spirit of sanctification."[113] And again he writes:
"God sending His own Son in the likeness of sinful flesh, ... spared not
even His own Son, but delivered Him up for us all."[114] Elsewhere he says:
"But when the fullness of the time was come, God sent His Son, made of a
woman, made under the law, that He might redeem them who were under the law;
that we might receive the adoption of sons."[115]
2) St. Paul affirms that the Son of God existed from all eternity before He
became incarnate, and he also states plainly that the Son of God is the Creator.
He speaks of "the light of the gospel of the glory of Christ, who is the
image of God."[116] He says of Christ: "Who is the image of the
invisible God, the first-born of every creature. For in Him were all things
created in heaven and on earth, visible and invisible, whether thrones or
dominations or principalities or powers; all things were created by Him, and in
Him. And He is before all, and by Him all things consist. And He is the head of
the body, the Church, who is the beginning, the first-born from the dead; that
in all things He may hold the primacy. Because in Him it hath well pleased the
Father that all fullness should dwell."[117] In this text the Son of God is
clearly declared the Creator, just as elsewhere St. Paul says of God that:
"of Him and by Him and in Him are all things."[118] Likewise it is the
common belief among Catholics, and even very many non-Catholic critics admit
that: "the fullness of the Godhead here signifies "all that is
required to constitute Christ as God."[119]
3) St. Paul teaches that Jesus is God and equal to the Father. He says:
"But we preach Christ crucified, unto the Jews indeed a stumbling block,
and unto the Gentiles foolishness. But unto them that are called, both Jews and
Greeks, Christ the power of God and the wisdom of God."[120] And again of
Christ he says: "For in Him dwelleth all the fullness of the Godhead
corporally. And you are filled in Him who is the head of all principality and
power."[121] In another epistle he writes: "For let this mind be in
you, which was also in Christ Jesus: who being in the form of God thought it not
robbery to be equal with God; but emptied Himself, taking the form of a servant,
being made in the likeness of men, and in habit found as a man."[122] There
cannot be a clearer affirmation of the divinity of Christ than in this text.
Farther on in this epistle, he writes: "God hath given Him a name which
is above all names, that in the name of Jesus every knee should bow"[123]
Likewise he says: "I wished myself to be an anathema from Christ, for my
brethren, ... of whom is Christ, according to the flesh, who is over all things,
God blessed forever. Amen."[124] But there is a difficulty concerning the
punctuation of this text. Very many even of the liberal critics place merely a
comma before the words, "who is over all things, God"; whereas,
Tischendorf and Gebhardt put a period, thus making this expression to be only an
invocation addressed to God. All the Fathers of the Church and Catholic exegetes
saw in this text an affirmation of the divinity of Christ.
Finally, in another epistle, we read: "In these days [God] hath spoken
to us by His Son, whom He hath appointed heir of all things, by whom also He
made the world. Who being the brightness of His glory, and the figure of His
substance, and upholding all things by the word of His power, making purgation
of sins, sitteth on the right hand of the majesty on high."[125] According
to this teaching, the Son is the Creator, for it is by the Son that God produced
all things. With the Jews, however, creation is an act that applies solely to
God. The Son is also the preserver of all things, upholding all things by the
word of His power. Likewise in this same epistle the angels are called the
ministers of Christ, and adore Him.[126] They are therefore inferior to Him.
The preceding texts clearly prove that St. Paul taught the divinity of
Christ; and so speaking, he intended to affirm no new doctrine, but to state
what was already the universal belief among the early Christians, even among the
converted Jews, who adhered most firmly to monotheism.
St. John's Testimony To The Divinity Of Christ
1) In the prologue to the Fourth Gospel, we read:: "In the beginning was
the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God."[127] Three
assertions are made: 1. The eternal pre-existence of the Word; 2. The Word is
distinct from God the Father; 3. The Word is divine and therefore consubstantial
with the Father. Then it is affirmed that all things were made by the Word.[128]
Therefore the Word is the Creator, and He is consequently God. That Word or
divine person assumed our human flesh, or nature, and lived among men. He is
called "the only-begotten Son, who is in the bosom of the
Father."[129] Therefore St. John most clearly teaches the divinity of
Christ in this prologue, which is a quasi-synthesis of revelation.
2) In the Fourth Gospel we find Christ reported as using words by which He
declares Himself to be the Son of God and Lord, although He frequently calls
Himself the Son of man, thereby showing the humble subjection of Himself as man
to His Father.
He says: "Father, the hour is come. Glorify Thy Son... that He may give
eternal life to all whom Thou hast given Him.... And all things are Thine, and
Thine are Mine."[130] Again, we read: "The Jews sought the more to
kill Him, because He did not only break the Sabbath, but also said God was His
Father, making Himself equal to God. Then Jesus answered, and said to them:
'What things soever the Father cloth, these the Son also cloth in like manner...
and He giveth life to whom He will.... The Father hath given all judgment to the
Son, that all men may honor the Son, as they honor the Father.... For as the
Father hath life in Himself, so He hath given to the Son also to have life in
Himself.’"[131] Christ also says: "From God I proceeded and
came."[132] And again: "I came forth from the Father and am come into
the world.... And yet I am not alone, because the Father is with Me."[133]
It is eternal sonship in the strict sense to which Jesus refers, for He says:
"Amen, amen, I say to you, before Abraham was made, I am."[134] And
again: "Glorify Thou Me, O Father, with Thyself, with the glory which I had
before the world was, with Thee."[135]
Moreover, Jesus says: "As the Father knoweth Me and I know the
Father."[136] "All things whatsoever the Father hath, are Mine.
Therefore I said, that He, the Spirit of truth, shall receive of Mine, and show
it to you."[137] Jesus even says: "I and the Father are One.[138] The
Jews understood these words in the sense that Jesus was equal in dignity to the
Father, for they at once took up stones to stone Him. Similarly He said: "I
am the way and the truth and the life";[139] but only God, who is essential
Being, is truth and life; a mere man may have even infallible truth, but is not
truth itself, just as he is not self-subsisting being. In this respect there is
an immeasurable difference between the two verbs, "to be" and "to
have." Hence this last utterance of Jesus would of itself suffice to
constitute an explicit expression of His divinity, which is so clearly affirmed
in the prologue of St. John's Gospel.
3) In St. John's First Epistle we read: "That which was from the
beginning, which we have heard... and our hands have handled of the Word of
life... we declare unto you."[140] Farther on he says: "And we know
that the Son of God is come, and He hath given us understanding that we may know
the true God, and may be in His true Son."[141] These concluding words of
St. John's First Epistle most clearly show that the author's intention was to
affirm the divinity of Christ just as this was his intention in writing his
prologue to the Fourth Gospel.
4) In the Apocalypse, that Christ is divine and the Son of God, is clearly
evident from the titles assigned to Him; for He is the First and the Last,[142]
the beginning of the Creation,[143] the Lord of lords and the King of
kings.[144] The divinity of Jesus is also equally manifested from the
prerogatives attributed to Him, for He is called the Lord of life and death for
all men,[145] the searcher of hearts.[146] He has power to open the book, which
no man is able to open,[147] ruling over all things celestial and
terrestrial,[148] being omnipotent as God Himself is.[149] The divinity of
Christ is also clearly set forth in this book; because of the honors that are
rendered to Him from men, the faithful are called servants of Jesus,[150] the
faithful both of Jesus and of God.[151] There is reference in these texts to the
priests of God and of Christ.[152] The Lamb of God who takes away the sin of the
world is adored as God,[153] and adoration is permitted to be given only to
God.[154]
From what has been said, it is most clearly apparent that Jesus is God and a
divine person distinct from God the Father. This will be more fully explained
when we come to discuss the infinite value of the merits and satisfaction of
Christ[155] and consider the texts of the New Testament concerning the mystery
of Redemption.
Among the principal texts of the Old Testament about the divinity of the
Messias, the following must be quoted: "A child is born to us and a son is
given to us, and the government is upon his shoulder, and his name shall be
called Wonderful, Counselor, God the Mighty, the Father of the world to come,
the Prince of Peace."[156] This text forms part of the Introit of the
second Mass in honor of the birth of our Lord. The Church sees in this text an
affirmation of the divinity of Jesus.
Concerning this text, the Rev. F. Ceuppens, O. P., remarks: "The true
meaning of this expression 'God the Mighty,’ is very much disputed among
Catholics. Following the opinion of such distinguished authors as A. Condamin,
E. Tobac, F. Feldmann, and M. J. Lagrange, we think the expression must be
accepted in the literal and proper sense, and the reason we give for this is
that, in other texts of the Old Testament, the same expression occurs, and it is
always predicated of Yahweh. This being the case, the future Messias is foretold
as being truly God, and truly divine by nature. But it is another question
whether the Jews, imbued with monotheistic concepts, perfectly understood all
these things, and whether the prophet himself fully grasped this doctrine and
saw it in all its applications."[157]
Third Article: Testimony Of Tradition And The Principal Definitions Of The
Church
A more detailed account of tradition and the definition of the Church is
given in the history of dogmas and in patrology. In this treatise we shall give
a brief summary of what everyone is expected to know about these matters.[158]
We notice that considerable progress has been made in the development of dogma
in the course of combating the various heresies.
1) In the first three centuries, the Fathers affirm that Christ is both God
and man, because He came to save and redeem us, which He could not have done
unless He had been both God, the author of grace, and also man.[159] Hence they
reject the errors of the Docetae, who said that Christ's body was imaginary and
fantastic, and of the Dualists, who declared that the divine and human natures
in Christ were united accidentally.[160] We find Tertullian, in his days,
asserting that the union of the two natures in Christ was effected "in one
person."[161]
2) In the fourth century, whereas the Apollinarists denied a rational soul to
Christ, meaning to say that the Word took the place of the mind in Christ, the
Fathers clearly affirm that Christ is both perfect God and perfect man; and they
also assert that what was not assumed was not healed. If, therefore, the Word
did not assume a rational soul, the soul was not healed; and besides, Christ
could not have merited and been obedient.[162]
3) Finally, in the fifth century, the Nestorians declared that the union of
the two natures in Christ was only accidental, and the Eutychians asserted that
there was only one nature in Christ. Against these heresies the Catholic concept
of one person in Christ and of the hypostatic union is explicitly affirmed, and
these points must be fully explained farther on.[163]
Following are the principal definitions of the Church concerning the divinity
of Christ.[164]
1) Christ is truly God, He is rightly called the Word, and Son of the Father,
consubstantial with the Father, equal to Him, God of God, begotten not made, the
only-begotten of the Father by natural and not by adoptive sonship.
2) "I believe in Jesus Christ, our Savior...," which is the most
ancient formula.[165]
3) "I believe in Jesus Christ, His only Son [of the Father] our
Lord,"[166] which is the more ancient formula in the Western Church.
4) The Creed of St. Epiphanius proposed to the catechumens of the Eastern
Church: "We believe in one God... and in one Lord Jesus Christ the Son of
God, begotten of God the Father, the only-begotten, that is, of the substance of
the Father, God of God, light of light, true God of true God, begotten not made,
consubstantial with the Father by whom all things were made... who for us men
and for our salvation came down from heaven and was incarnate."[167]
5) The First Council of Nicaea (325) defines, against the Arians: "We
believe in one God the Father almighty, Maker of all things visible and
invisible. And in our one Lord Jesus Christ, the Son of God, the only-begotten
of the Father, that is, of the substance of the Father, God of God, light of
light, true God of true God, begotten not made, one in substance with the
Father, by whom all things were made, both in heaven and on earth, who for our
salvation came down, was incarnate, and was made man, suffered and rose again
the third day, ascended into heaven, and will come to judge the living and the
dead."[168] All these words of the Nicene Council must be seriously
considered farther on, when we explain the articles of St. Thomas. The preceding
testimony and definitions suffice for establishing the fact of the Incarnation.
CHAPTER II: PRELIMINARY QUESTION THE POSSIBILITY OF THE
INCARNATION
Let us now turn to speculative theology, which, as stated, has two tasks to
perform.
1) It must give a philosophical analysis of the terms used in revealed dogma,
so that their meaning may be better known, for, as the Vatican Council says in
the text already quoted: "Reason enlightened by faith, when it seeks
earnestly, piously, and calmly, attains by a gift from God, some, and that a
very fruitful, understanding of the mysteries; partly from the analogy of those
things which it naturally knows, partly from the relation which the mysteries
bear to one another and the last end of man."[169] Thus the mystery of man
must be illustrated from analysis of the notions of divine nature, human nature,
person, as well as from the connection of this mystery with the mysteries of
Redemption and of eternal life. In this part of speculative theology the
discussions are either explicative, or subjectively illative.[170]
2) Speculative theology must deduce from revealed truths by a discursive
process that is properly and objectively illative, other truths, namely,
conclusions that are only virtually contained in the revealed truths. An example
would be the following: Christ already had, when on earth, infused knowledge,
which was inferior to the beatific vision.
We must begin by discussing the possibility and fittingness of the
Incarnation.
St. Thomas starts abruptly by considering the fittingness of the Incarnation,
whereas many theologians of later times first speak of its possibility; and this
is what St. Thomas had done in the work preceding his Summa.[171] The reason why
the holy Doctor omitted this question of the possibility is probably because he
wishes to examine this question afterward, when he discusses the mode of the
union (q. 2-15), which is concerned with the principal difficulties against the
possibility of this mystery. Moreover, it is not absolutely necessary to begin
by treating about the possibility of this mystery, because for the faithful this
possibility follows from the fact of the Incarnation, which is of faith. From
actuality to possibility, this follows as a logical consequence.
For the general benefit of the doctrine, however, theologians begin by asking
whether the possibility of the Incarnation can be proved or known by the natural
light of reason. This question has its advantages as regards method.
Incarnation corresponds to the Latin term "inhumanatio," which
signifies the act of becoming man, and it is the union or unition of the human
nature with the divine in the one person of the Word. This is evident from the
traditional explanation of the words of St. John: "The Word was made
flesh,"[172] in which "flesh" as frequently in Sacred Scripture
is concerned with living and human flesh, which is not living and human unless
united with a human soul. And it also says that this Word was made flesh to
commend the humility of our Savior, who also willed to become man for our
salvation.
But can the Incarnation be proved? In the first question of this treatise it
will be shown, indeed, that there is no apparent contradiction in the
Incarnation, and that it cannot be proved impossible. But the question now is,
as posited above, whether this possibility can be proved by reason alone. There
does not seem to be any apparent contradiction in the affirmation of a divine
quaternity, and yet there lurks a contradiction in this affirmation. There
cannot be four persons in God, nor merely two, but three. Is it therefore
possible to prove the Incarnation? This question is commonly answered in the
negatives.[173]
Authoritative proof. St. Paul calls the Incarnation, "the mystery which
hath been hidden in God."[174] The Eleventh Council of Toledo says:
"If the Incarnation could be shown possible by reason, then it would not be
an object of admiration; if it were an example, then would not be
unique."[175]
Similarly, against the semi-rationalists, who wish to prove the revealed
mysteries, especially against Froschammer, Pius IX wrote: "The author
teaches that reason, also in the most secret matters pertaining to God's wisdom
and goodness, even too in the mysteries that are dependent on His free will,
although granted that they have been revealed, can by itself, not relying on the
already established principle of divine authority, but on its own natural
principles and powers, acquire a certainty of knowledge. Everyone who has a
slight knowledge of the rudiments of Christian doctrine immediately sees and
likewise fully realizes how altogether false and erroneous is the author's
teaching."[176]
It is true, indeed, that Froschammer wished to prove not only the possibility
but also the very fact of the Incarnation. If, however, the possibility of the
Incarnation could be apodictically and positively proved, as the possibility of
any miracle, for instance, of the Resurrection, then the Incarnation would be
only a miracle that is supernatural as regards the mode of its production, but
it would not be a mystery in the strict sense, that it is essentially
supernatural.
In the condemnation of semi-rationalism, it is stated: "And assuredly,
since these dogmas are above nature, therefore they are beyond the scope of
reason and natural principles."[177]
The Vatican Council also says: "If anyone shall say that in divine
revelation there are no mysteries, truly and properly so called, but that all
the doctrines of faith can be understood and demonstrated from natural
principles by properly cultivated reason, let him be anathema."[178]
Theological proof.[179] What is essentially supernatural is supernatural as
regards its knowability, even for the angels.
But the intrinsic possibility of the Incarnation is the intrinsic possibility
of something essentially supernatural, which has no necessary and evident
connection with things of the natural order.
Therefore this possibility is supernatural as regards its knowability, even
for the angel. Hence it cannot be demonstrated, but only persuasive arguments of
fitness can be advanced, and it can be defended against those who deny it.
The major is evident, for truth and being are convertible.
Minor. The Incarnation is not only a miracle that is supernatural as regards
the mode of its production, such as the resurrection of the dead, but it is also
an essentially supernatural mystery, for it is the intimate union of the human
nature with the divine nature as it is in itself, in the person of the Word. But
the divine nature as it is in itself, and the person of the Word are essentially
supernatural; on the contrary, God as the author of nature has a necessary and
evident connection with things of the natural order.
Reason, however, can solve the objections against the possibility of this
mystery, by showing them to be either false or unnecessary.[180] Moreover,
reason can urge the fitness of this mystery by arguments that are not apodictic
but congruent. These arguments are truly profound; in fact, they can always be
the result of keen penetration by either the human or angelic intellect, but
this penetration can never reach the degree required for demonstration.
Objection. To prove that anything is not contradictory is to prove it
possible.
But it is proved that the Incarnation is not contradictory.
Therefore the Incarnation is proved possible.
I distinguish the major. To prove that anything is not contradictory,
positively and evidently, this I concede; that it is not so negatively and
probably, this I deny. So writes Billuart.[181]
In this kind of argument we do not proceed from some a priori or a posterior)
reasoning that is positively demonstrative of this possibility, but our
reasoning rests on probable and apparent grounds. Thus it is shown that the
possibility of the Incarnation is never disproved; the objections are not
impossible of solution, for they can be shown to be either false or at least not
cogent.
Another objection. But God is in Himself essentially supernatural, and yet
reason alone apodictically proves His existence. Therefore, although the mystery
of the Incarnation is essentially supernatural, reason alone apodictically
proves at least the possibility, if not the fact of the Incarnation.
Reply. I distinguish the antecedent. That God is in Himself as regards His
Deity or intimate life essentially supernatural, this I concede. Nevertheless,
as the Author of nature, He has a necessary and evident connection with created
effects of the natural order, and so in this inferior aspect the truth of this
proposition, God exists, is demonstrated cum fundamento in re,[182] although we
have not a positive and natural knowledge of God's essence or of His act of
essence. On this point St. Thomas says: "To be can mean either of two
things. It may mean the act of essence or it may mean the composition of a
proposition effected by the mind in joining a predicate to a subject. Taking 'to
be' in the first sense, we cannot understand God's existence or His essence; but
only in the second sense. We know that this proposition which we form about God
when we say 'God is,’ is true; and this we know from His effects."[183]
But there is nothing similar to this in the Incarnation of the Word, because
this mystery, just as the intimate life of the Trinity, has no necessary and
evident connection with natural effects; hence neither the fact nor the
possibility of this mystery can be demonstrated from natural principles, for
this possibility transcends demonstration. These arguments of congruence may
always be made more profound, but they will never reach the degree required for
an apodictic argument, just as the sides of a polygon inscribed in a circle may
be increased indefinitely, yet they will never be identified with the
circumference of the circle, because the sides will never be diminished so as to
become a point.
But I insist. It is apodictically proved that there is in God a supernatural
order of truth and of life.
Reply. We are not positively but only negatively assured of this order by
such a proof, which is the case with any order whose mysteries cannot be known
in a natural way.
Still Gregory of Valentia insists that at least the angelic intellect can
perhaps prove this possibility, because the angel intuitively sees the human
nature as distinct from its subsistence or personality, and therefore as
assumable by the divine subsistence.
Reply. The angelic intellect cannot know in a natural way whether the divine
subsistence, which is essentially supernatural, can, without implying
imperfection, take the place of human subsistence.
Corollary. A fortiori the angelic intellect cannot know by its natural powers
the fact of the Incarnation.
Gregory of Valentia remarks that the angel, since He sees intuitively that
the human nature of Christ is without its own personality, must immediately
conclude that this human nature is personally united to some divine person.
Reply. This conclusion is not established, for the angel could conclude: the
human personality of this man is hidden from me, because of motives known to God
alone. Thus it is certain that the created intellect by its own natural powers
cannot know that the Incarnation is possible, much less that it is a fact.
The objections that can be raised, however, against the possibility of the
Incarnation are solved in the course of this treatise.[184] It will suffice here
at the beginning to take note of the principal objection, by way of a statement
of the question. It is one proposed by St. Thomas,[185] and may be stated as
follows:
God cannot be subject to any intrinsic change, or be intrinsically otherwise
than He is.
But by the Incarnation God would be intrinsically otherwise than He is.
Therefore the Incarnation is impossible.
Reply. I distinguish the minor. That God would undergo a change, if by reason
of passive potency He were to receive some distinct perfection, this I concede;
that God only terminates the human nature, and undergoes a change, this I deny.
God in the Incarnation neither loses nor acquires anything, but merely makes
creatures partakers in His perfection. Therefore, as St. Thomas says: "When
it is said, 'God was made man,’ we understand no change on the part of God,
but only on the part of the human nature."[186] Similarly, if we see the
sun, it undergoes no change, but is only the object of our vision.
As St. Thomas says: "To be man belongs to God by reason of the union,
which is a relation.... But whatever is predicated relatively can be newly
predicated of anything without its change, as a man may be made to be on the
right side without being changed, and merely by the change of him who was on his
left side."[187] Likewise, anything at first not seen is seen afterward
without any change in itself, but inasmuch as it is actually the termination of
our vision. It is the visual faculty that is changed, inasmuch as it passes from
potentiality to act.
Similarly, as we shall see in the case of the Incarnation, the change is
entirely on the part of the nature that is assumed, which is deprived of its own
subsistence and acquires the divine. The Word by no means acquires a new and
real relation, but the relation is logical; for the real relation is only on the
part of the human nature toward the Word, just as the visual faculty is in real
relation to the object seen, and not the reverse of this. Hence St. Thomas says:
"God is said to be united not by any change in Himself, but in that which
is united to Him; similarly, when it is said that He is unitable, this statement
does not mean that the union is effected by reason of any passive potency
existing in God, but because there is such a potency existing in the creature so
as to make this union possible."[188] So also God is said to be visible and
in the next life He is seen by the blessed, not because of any change in
Himself, but the change is in the blessed, since He terminates their vision as
object seen. Thus a point that already terminates one line, can terminate a
second and third line as in the case of the point of a pyramid, and yet the
point undergoes no change in itself.
Objection. The Word is the subject of the human nature, and not merely the
terminus; for the Word has this human nature, which is truly attributed to Him,
as to the subject. Therefore the Word is the recipient of the human nature.
Reply. I distinguish the antecedent. That the Word possesses the human nature
in a receptive sense, this I deny; in a terminative sense, this I concede. To
possess a form in a receptive sense is to be the subject of this form, just as
matter receives its form, or as a substance receives accidental forms; but such
is not the case when a subject has some form in a personal or terminative sense.
The Word, however, possesses the human nature not in a receptive sense, because
He is not in passive potency to receive it; but He possesses it personally and
terminatively, in so far as He is its intrinsic terminus, intrinsically
completing it and terminating it, just as the point terminates the line, or the
object seen terminates the visual faculty. The difficulty raised by this
objection makes it apparent that the possibility of the Incarnation cannot be
strictly proved.
Again I insist. What is extrinsic to another cannot become intrinsic to it
unless it is received by the other. But the human nature in itself is extrinsic
to the Word. Therefore the Word can become intrinsic to the human nature only by
becoming the recipient of it.
Reply. I deny the major. For something can become intrinsic to another by the
sole fact of being joined to that which receives it by way of intrinsic
termination, as a point becomes intrinsic to a line, and so what is received is
not received by way of informing act, as if the recipient were in some passive
potentiality to be perfected by it. Thus it is shown that the objection is
either false or at least unnecessary, and hence of no force.
This point will be made clearer in the course of this treatise, in which it
will be shown that God cannot take the place of a created subsistence as
informing, but as terminating what is received. The informing form is related to
the whole to which it is ordered as the less perfect part, just as the soul is
less perfect than the complete man. On the contrary, the terminating perfection
is not ordered to the more complete whole, but rather draws the other to
Himself. Hence, instead of involving any imperfection, God imparts His
perfection to what is assumed. Thus, for example God's essence without involving
any imperfection terminates the vision of the blessed, and the divine essence is
not more perfect in being seen by the blessed than if it were not seen by them.
Similarly, a beautiful statue is not made more perfect by the fact that it is
the object of my admiration, nor is the doctrine of St. Thomas made more perfect
by the fact that it is understood by the disciple, but it is the disciple who is
made more perfect by the doctrine. Rome is not made more perfect by the fact
that any pilgrim, however distinguished, visits it.
Final objection. One substantial being cannot result from the union of
several complete beings. But the human and divine natures are complete beings.
Therefore one substantial being, such as Christ would be, cannot result from the
union of the two natures.
Reply. I distinguish the major. From several beings complete in their natures
there cannot result one substantial unity of nature, this I concede; that there
cannot result a substantial unity of suppositum or person, this I deny.
Explanation. From two acts there cannot result something essentially one in
nature, and therefore prime matter must be pure potency, so that the human
nature is essentially and not accidentally one. But the human nature as such is
not complete in the sense that it is a suppositum or person, and thus it is
drawn to unity of being with the Word, in the sense that there is one
suppositum, which will be more fully explained farther on.[189] Thus in the
resurrection the body is united with the soul and constitutes with it one
supposital being.
More briefly, these various objections are solved by saying that the Word is
not related to Christ's humanity as recipient subject, for in such case the Word
would be in passive potency for His humanity; nor is He related to it as
informing form that is received, for in this case He would be less perfect than
the whole, which is the complete Christ; but He is related to it as terminating
perfection, just as the pre-existing point that already terminates one line
again terminates another; or just as the object that terminates the vision of
one man, may again terminate the vision of another man. Thus the professor
teaches his various students not in a receptive but in a terminative sense.
Expressed more briefly, we may say that the Pure Act is unreceived and
unreceivable. If He were received in any potency, He would be subjected to
participation and limitation; if, however, He were to receive, then He would be
in potency for a further act.
"To have terminatively" does not mean to be actuated or to be
perfected; rather it means to perfect. Thus the Father, the Son, and the Holy
Ghost do not have the Deity receptively, but terminatively. Thus the Son of God
has His humanity terminatively, but not receptively. Thus God has His external
glory, inasmuch as He is known and praised.
"To have receptively" is to be actuated and perfected. Thus matter
receives the form. The created substance receives accidental forms.
"The form terminating" is not a part and involves no imperfection,
but perfects and bestows its perfection upon what it terminates. Such is the
case with the person of the Word, who unites with Himself and terminates
Christ's humanity. So also the doctrine of St. Thomas unites with himself and
terminates the intelligence of a number of students.
"The form informing" is less perfect than the whole, as the soul in
man.
The difficulty raised by the foregoing objections against the intrinsic
possibility of the Incarnation confirms the thesis, namely, that this
possibility cannot be apodictically proved from reason alone, but solely that
persuasive reasons can be adduced in defense of this possibility, by showing
that the objections of those attacking it are either evidently false or at least
unnecessary, and of no force.
We must now treat of the fitness of the Incarnation. Fitness means something
more than mere possibility, and it will at once be seen that we are persuaded of
this fitness by congruent arguments drawn from reason alone; but the revelation
of original sin being presupposed, the Incarnation is proved necessary so that
adequate reparation be made to God, if He demands such reparation.
CHAPTER III: QUESTION 1—THE FITNESS OF THE INCARNATION
This question contains six articles that gradually develop the doctrine of
the fitness of the Incarnation. St. Thomas begins by discussing:
(1) the fitness of the incarnation;
(2) its necessity for the reparation of the human race;
(3) its proximate motive, whether, if there had been no sin, God would have
become incarnate;
(4) whether God became incarnate for the removal of original sin more chiefly
than for actual sin;
(5) why it was not more fitting that God should become incarnate in the
beginning of the human race;
(6) why it is not more fitting that the Incarnation should take place at the
end of the world.
First Article: Whether It Was Fitting That God Should Become Incarnate?[190]
State of the question. In this article we are concerned with the mere
fitness, not as yet with the proximate motive of the Incarnation. In other
words, was the Incarnation not only possible, but was it expedient and fitting,
that is, was it in agreement with God's wisdom and goodness? Taken in this
sense, the question is whether it was fitting that God should become man; on the
other hand, it does not seem fitting that God should become a lion, although
this may perhaps be possible. But was it more fitting that the Son of God,
rather than the Father or the Holy Ghost, should become incarnate?[191]
Likewise, was it more fitting that the Word should assume the human nature
rather than the angelic nature?[192]
This state of the question will be made clearer from the solution of the
difficulties posited at the beginning of this article. They constitute, as it
were, the nucleus of the difficulties to be solved.
The difficulties are the following.
(1) From all eternity God was separated from human nature. Therefore it was
not fitting that He should be united to it.
(2) It is not fitting for those things to be united that are infinitely
distant from each other. This seems to be against the principle of continuity,
which states that the highest of the lowest order should reach the lowest of the
highest, but not that the very lowest should reach the very highest. Hence it
seems to be more fitting that God should have taken the nature of the highest
angel, which is perhaps what Lucifer thought.
(3) It was not fitting that the supreme uncreated Spirit should assume a
body, as indeed He would be assuming what is evil. This objection was raised by
the Manichaeans, who held that matter is evil.
(4) It is unfitting that the infinite God, the Ruler of the universe, should
remain hidden in the tiny body of an infant. So say Volusianus and many
philosophers of modern times, who do not see anything unbecoming, however, in
pantheism so that the divine nature be confused with the nature even of a stone.
Several rationalists of our times say that the Incarnation would be the lapse or
descent of the metaphysical absolute into the phenomenal relative, or the lapse
of immutable eternity into mutable time. In like manner some go further and say
that the Incarnation might perhaps be admitted by those who thought that the
earth is the center of the universe, but not by those who hold that the earth is
but like an atom among the millions of stars. They also say that the Incarnation
is not only derogatory to God's supreme majesty, but also to His mercy, which is
more strikingly manifested by simply forgiving the sin without demanding
reparation.
Finally, if it were said to be fitting for God to become incarnate, we should
also have to conclude that it was unfitting for God not to become incarnate. But
this conclusion is false, because God could have willed not to become incarnate,
without this being derogatory to Him.[193] All other objections even of modern
philosophers are easily reduced to the above-mentioned objections.[194]
Yet the answer is that it was fitting for God to become incarnate.
Authoritative proof. St. Paul and St. Damascene say that it appears to be
most fitting that the invisible things of God be made known by the visible
things He has created. Thus God created the world in manifestation of His
goodness and perfections. But, as Damascene says, the Incarnation shows the
goodness, wisdom, justice, and omnipotence of God.
The goodness which Damascene speaks of includes mercy, and already Plato had
defined divine goodness as diffusive of itself, it being the love of supreme
opulence or perfection for extreme poverty. In a loftier strain, the Evangelist
says: "For God so loved the world as to give His only-begotten
Son."[195] This thought is developed below.
Theological proof. It starts from a consideration of God's goodness, on which
the fitness of the Incarnation has its special foundation, and is a commentary
on the words of St. John: "For God so loved the world as to give His
only-begotten Son."[196] God's goodness is seen conspicuously in this
supreme and most liberal gift, although His wisdom, justice, or omnipotence is
also evident.
The argument may be reduced to the following syllogism.
It belongs to the idea of good to communicate itself to others, for good is
self-diffusive.[197] But God's nature is essential goodness, or plenitude of
being. Therefore it is fitting for God to communicate Himself to others in the
highest degree, which finds its complete realization in the Incarnation.
The major is quoted from Dionysius,[198] and is explained by St. Thomas in
various places. It contains three principles: Good is self-diffusive, primarily
as the end that attracts and perfects. Secondly, inasmuch as the end attracts
the agent to act at least immanently. Thirdly, inasmuch as the perfect agent
acts to communicate its goodness externally.
Nevertheless, good does not consist essentially in the actual communication
of itself, for this would result in pantheistic emanation; but good essentially
implies an aptitude or propensity to communicate itself. This means that good is
aptitudinally self-diffusive, not of necessity diffusing itself, and, when it
does so, this diffusion is sometimes most free and entirely gratuitous; but
sometimes this diffusion is a necessary act, if the agent is determined to act
in only one way, as the primary purpose of the sun is to give light.
These truths have been explained by St. Thomas in various parts of his works.
Thus he says: "Goodness is described as self-diffusive, in the sense that
an end is said to move,"[199] namely, by attracting to itself, as to that
which is perfect and perfective. Thus good is more of the nature of a final
cause than of an efficient cause. But as stated in the argumentative part of
this article just quoted, the end moves the efficient cause to act. Hence St.
Thomas says: "The very nature of good is that something flows from it but
not that it flows from something else.... But, since the First Good diffuses
itself according to the intellect, to which it is proper to flow forth into its
effects according to a certain fixed form, it follows that there is a certain
measure from which all other goods share the power of diffusion."[200]
Thus, this law is verified, namely, that good is self-diffusive throughout
the universe, as St. Thomas shows in illustrating the mystery of the Trinity. He
says: "The nobler a nature is, the more that which flows from it is more
intimate to it."[201] In other words, good is self-diffusive, and the
nobler it is, the more fully and more intimately it is self-diffusive. For
instance, the sun illumines and heats, or fire generates fire, the plant
produces a plant, the grown-up animal or perfect animal generates an animal like
itself. Similarly, a celebrated artist or a famous musician conceives and
produces wonderful works of art; a prominent scientist or celebrated astronomer
discovers and formulates the laws of nature, for instance, the courses of the
planets. Great teachers, such as St. Augustine, impart not only their knowledge
but also their spirit to their disciples; a virtuous man incites others to lead
a virtuous life; great apostles, such as St. Paul, communicate to others their
love for God. Hence good is self-diffusive, and the nobler it is, the more fully
and intimately it is self-diffusive. We now see how this principle illustrates
the mystery of the Trinity, inasmuch as the Father, generating the Son,
communicates to Him not only a participation in His nature, His intellect, and
His love, but His complete and indivisible nature, so that the Son of God is
Light of Light, God of God, true God of true God. Likewise the Holy Spirit is
true God proceeding from the mutual love between the Father and the Son.
There is, however, a difficulty. It is that the principle, good is
self-diffusive, proves either too much or not enough. It proves, indeed, too
much if we infer from it the moral necessity and a fortiori the physical
necessity of the Incarnation. But it does not prove enough if the Incarnation is
a most free decree, because then, whether God became incarnate or not seems to
be equally fitting.
As a matter of fact, there were extreme views both for and against this
principle. Some pantheists, such as the Neoplatonists, in accordance with their
emanatory theory, exaggerated this principle, saying that good is essentially
and actually self-diffusive and also actually diffusing itself. But God is the
highest good. Therefore He is essentially and actually diffusive externally by a
process of necessary emanation. This teaching is contrary to the dogma of a free
creation, which was explicitly defined by the Vatican Council in these words:
"God created both the spiritual and corporeal creature with absolute
freedom of counsel,"[202] and not from eternity.
Absolute optimists, such as Leibnitz and Malebranche, likewise erred.[203]
Hence the principle that good is self-diffusive must be understood in the sense
we already noted with the Thomists, as meaning that good does not consist
essentially in the actual communication of itself, but that there is essentially
in good an aptitude and tendency to be self-diffusive, first as the end
proposed, and then as moving the agent to act. But actual diffusion of good is
sometimes necessary if the agent is determined in one way, as the sun is to
illumine; sometimes this diffusion is a most free and absolutely gratuitous
act,[204] because God is not determined in one way in His eternal acts. He is
already infinitely good and blessed in Himself, and created good does not
increase His perfection; He is not more being after His action.
Thus creation and the Incarnation are absolutely free acts. The freedom of
both is confirmed by the revelation of the mystery of the Trinity; for if there
had been neither creation nor Incarnation, the principle that good is
self-diffusive would be verified in the case of the internal divine processions.
This sufficiently explains the major of our syllogism, namely, that good is
self-diffusive.
Minor. God's nature is essential goodness, for He is the self-subsisting
Being and is therefore the very plenitude of being, which means that He is the
essential, supreme, and infinite goodness.[205]
Therefore it is fitting for God to communicate Himself to others in the
highest degree, and this is, indeed, most effectively accomplished by means of
the Incarnation. For by this means God communicates to the creature not only a
participation of being, as in the creation of stones, not only a participation
in life, as in the creation of plants and animals, not only a participation in
the intellectual and moral life of justice and holiness, as in the creation of
Adam, the first man, but He communicates Himself in person. St. Thomas quotes
St. Augustine in saying: "He so joined created nature to Himself that one
person is made up of these three, the Word, a soul, and flesh."[206] Hence
it is manifest that it was fitting for God to become incarnate.
This same principle (good is self-diffusive) illustrates the mystery of
Redemption, the sacrifice of the Cross, and the institution of the Eucharist.
There is still another difficulty, namely, that this argument does not
sufficiently prove. It is that if, in virtue of the principle that good is
self-diffusive, the Incarnation is not even morally necessary but absolutely
free and gratuitous, then it is equally fitting whether God become incarnate or
not. This leaves the question either indifferent or undecided. Therefore, as the
nominalist-q say, it is useless for theology to speak of the fitness of the
mysteries that have been accomplished by God's liberality.
Reply. Billuart says: "The incarnation was fitting, not in the sense of
its being necessary, but of its being a free act."[207] We say, for in
stance, the motive for choosing this particular thing is fitting, not as
necessitating the will, but it is fitting that this particular thing be a matter
of free choice, and not because of any necessity. Thus it is fitting to preserve
one's virginity, yet it is equally fitting to make use of matrimony, because
each is a free decision. And so incarnation or no incarnation, each was equally
fitting. As Cajetan says: "To communicate Himself to others does not denote
a new perfection in God but in the creature to whom this perfection is
communicated."[208]
Hence theology does not have recourse to useless speculations about the
fittingness of the Incarnation, as several nominalists said, and certain
philosophers and theologians who wrote that the Incarnation is said to be
fitting because it was accomplished; but it would have been likewise and equally
fitting for God not to have become incarnate if He had so willed. Therefore the
arguments of fitness have no foundation.
This statement would be true if it were not more fitting for God to have
chosen to become incarnate than for Him not to have chosen. In the opinion of
St. Thomas, before the foreknowledge of merits it is not more fitting for God to
choose Peter in preference to Judas; for this choice "depends on the will
of God; as from the simple will of the artificer it depends that this stone is
in this part of the wall, and that in another; although the plan requires that
some stones should be in this place and some in that place."[209] The
election of the predestined depends purely on the divine benevolence, which is
the culmination of divine liberty.
In the matter we are discussing, it is a certain motive in the divine
strategy or in divine providence that makes the Incarnation more fitting than no
incarnation,[210] just as creation is preferable to no creation, and just as
virginity consecrated to God is better than matrimony. But this reason of
fitness does not even morally necessitate the divine will, which is independent
of all created good, inasmuch as from all eternity God's goodness is infinite,
and is not in need of any created good. Therefore the argument of fitness does
not make it necessary for God to become incarnate, but it is advanced as showing
the wisdom of such choice.
Difficulty. God would have communicated Himself still more if He had united
all created natures with Himself.
Reply. The union is not an absolute impossibility, and it would not have been
pantheism, because it would have been accomplished without confusion of the
created nature with the uncreated; but then all men and angels would have been
impeccable, as Christ is. It is also fitting that the Word be united with the
human nature, which is the microcosm, the compendium of the universe, inasmuch
as it includes corporeity, as also vegetative, sensitive and intellective lives.
It is even more perfect for the Word to be united only with the human nature
of Christ, and not with others. The reason is that the whole world demands
subordination of beings, and it is fitting that the created nature personally
united with the Word be the highest in the order of created beings, as the
efficient and final cause of those beings beneath it, as St. Paul says:
"For all are yours. And you are Christ's, and Christ is God's."[211]
Concerning this article, Medina asks whether there can be anything more
excellent than the humanity of Christ. He replies that there can, indeed, be
something more excellent than the humanity of Christ, but not anything more
excellent than Christ.
1) God could not make anything that is better than Christ our I Lord, because
Christ is truly God.
2) God could not elevate human nature to anything better than the hypostatic
union.
3) God could have made something more excellent than the humanity of Christ,
such as more perfect angels. In fact, as we shall state farther on, God, by His
absolute power, could have given to the soul of Christ a higher degree of the
light of glory, or one of greater intensity, because the highest possible degree
of the created light of glory is inconceivable; for God can produce something
still more perfect than anything He has produced. Thus the swiftest possible
motion is inconceivable, because such swiftest motion would reach its terminus
before it had left its starting point, and would no longer be motion, but
immobility.
St. Thomas says: "God can make always something better than each
individual thing."[212] Hence in created beings, there is no highest
possible, and in this sense there is no highest creatable angel; but nothing can
be higher than the hypostatic union of some created nature with some divine
person.
What has just been said is the answer to the absolute optimism of Leibnitz
and Malebranche.
Reply to first objection. "God was not changed by the Incarnation... but
He united Himself to the creature in a new way, or rather united Himself to
it," St. Thomas says; "or rather He united it to Himself,"
because there is a real relation of union of Christ's humanity to the Word, but
not of the Word to the assumed humanity. It was fitting for Christ's humanity
thus to be assumed.
Reply to the second objection. "To be united to God was not fitting for
human flesh according to its natural endowments, but it was fitting by reason of
God's infinite goodness that He should unite it for man's salvation."
This distinction is of greatest validity in showing the fitness of the
elevation of our nature to the supernatural order, so as to solve the following
objection, which is similar to the one raised by Baius: What is eminently
fitting must be unconditional, and is opposed to what is gratuitous. But the
beatific vision is for us eminently fitting, so that its privation is abject
misery. Therefore the beatific vision is unconditionally fitting to our nature,
and is not gratuitous.
Reply. I distinguish the major, in accordance with the distinction given in
this article. What is eminently fitting according to our natural endowments must
be unconditional, this I concede; what is according to God's infinite goodness,
this I deny; and I contradistinguish the minor.
Reply to the third objection. It could be fitting for God to assume flesh but
not evil, because flesh is from God the author of nature and is ordered to good,
whereas evil is not.
Reply to fourth objection. St. Augustine replies to Volusianus that God by
the Incarnation at Bethlehem did not lose the government of the world, just as
He did not lose His divine nature, but united the human nature to it.
"Hence (in the infant) Jesus the greatness of divine power feels no straits
in narrow surroundings." God's immensity is not measured by space or by
quantity, but it is greatness of power, supporting or preserving all things in
being. If a word Uttered by a human being in some point of space can be heard by
others also even far away, and its meaning has a moral influence upon the whole
world, why could not the Word of God, present in the frail body of the child
Jesus, still preserve in being and govern all things created?[213]
Finally, what must be said in reply to the objection of modern scientists,
who say that the Incarnation perhaps could be admitted if the earth were the
center of the universe, which it is not, for it is a planet among countless
millions of heavenly bodies that are greater, namely, the stars and the nebulae?
Reply.
It may be said: 1. Just as the a priori reason why the Savior was sent was
not so that the Jewish race be chosen in preference to some other nation, or,
among the women of this race, that Mary be chosen as the Mother of our Lord in
preference to some other woman, or among the just of this race, there was no a
priori reason that Joseph be chosen as the foster father of our Lord; so there
is no a priori reason that the earth be chosen in preference to some other
heavenly body that may possibly be inhabited, such as Sirius.
We may also say: 2. We do not know whether there are any other heavenly
bodies suitable for human habitation, which are inhabited.
On this point both the positive sciences and theology can offer only
hypotheses. Therefore it is not on conjectural grounds that the testimony about
the Incarnation must be rejected; namely, the testimony of Christ, of the
apostles, of so many martyrs, of the Catholic Church must be rejected concerning
the Incarnation. This testimony is confirmed, indeed, by miracles and the
wonderful life of the Church, which is fruitful both morally and spiritually in
all good works.
If some of the other heavenly bodies are inhabited by human beings, God has
not deemed it opportune to reveal this fact to us. Some say, if perhaps there
are others inhabited, then these human beings are either in the purely natural
state, or there was no case of original sin among them, or if there was, then
they were regenerated in some other way than by the Incarnation. There is
nothing intrinsically repugnant in all these views. It is difficult to say,
however, whether these opinions can be reconciled with the free decree of the
Incarnation in its relation to the human race. For revelation speaks of the
human race as it exists on this earth.
Whatever is the fact about these gratuitous hypotheses, Christ, as the
incarnate Word of God, is the culmination of the whole of creation, and, just as
He is the head of the angels, at least as regards accidental grace, so He could
be such with reference to human beings who might be living on some of the other
heavenly bodies. Concerning these things and many others, we have no knowledge,
and there is no need for us to stop and discuss them. Some men seem to be of the
opinion that on other heavenly bodies perhaps there are rational animals of
another species than man. But this seems to be false, for the term
"rational animal" seems to be not a genus but the ultimate species,
according to the principle of continuity; for the highest in the lowest order,
for instance, the sensitive life, touches the lowest in the highest order,
namely, the intellective life. Hence there is no conjunction of the highest in
the sensitive life with the lowest in the intellective life, except in one
species, and this is not susceptible to either increase or decrease.
Finally, it must be noted that even if the world were the mathematical center
of the universe, this would be no reason why God should choose it for the
Incarnation. Thus Christ was not born in Jerusalem, but in Bethlehem. So also
St. Augustine was the greatest theologian of his time, and yet he came into the
world and taught not at Rome, which was the center of the world, but in Africa.
He was only bishop of Hippo.
The mathematical position of a body is a matter of less importance with
reference to a supernatural mystery, which infinitely transcends the spatial
order.
What has been said suffices concerning the fitness of the Incarnation.
Second Article: Whether It Was Necessary For The Restoration Of The Human
Race That The Word Of God Should Become Incarnate?
State of the question.
(1) We assume that the Incarnation was not absolutely necessary, as Wyclif
contended, arguing from the false principle that "all things happen because
of absolute necessity."[214] Presupposing the fact of creation, the
Incarnation was not necessary, whatever absolute optimists, such as Leibnitz and
Malebranche, said to the contrary; although the Incarnation may have increased
the accidental glory of God, He is absolutely sufficient unto Himself, and is
not at all in need of this accidental glory.
2) We assume that after original sin, it was in God's power not to will the
reparation of the human race, and in this there would have been no injustice, as
St. Augustine says.[215] Therefore we must thank God for having mercifully
willed to free the human race from sin.
As a matter of fact, indeed, God did not reinstate the fallen angels; and why
He permitted their fall was for a greater good, which must be the manifestation
of infinite justice. St. Thomas considers the reparation of the human race to be
most fitting, for the sin was not in itself irreparable, whereas he considers
the devil's sin, which was committed with full knowledge, to be in itself
irreparable, just as the sin of final impenitence is for man. He says: "So
it is customary to say that man's free will is flexible to the opposite both
before and after the choice; but the angel, s free will is flexible to either
opposite before the choice but not after. So therefore the good angels who
adhered to justice were confirmed therein; whereas the wicked ones, sinning, are
obstinate in sin,"[216] because the angel immediately and intuitively sees
whatever must be considered before the choice, with nothing to be considered
after the choice.
The question of this article is posited on the understanding that God wills
to restore the human race, so far as it is capable of restoration.
A thing is said to be necessary for the end in two ways:
a) simply, when the end cannot be attained in any other way. Thus food is
necessary for the preservation of life;
b) in a qualified manner, when the end is attained more conveniently, as a
horse is necessary for a journey.
Some thought that St. Anselm in his treatise on the Incarnation[217] taught
its absolute necessity after the fall of the human race; but St. Bonaventure and
Scotus interpret his statements in a benign sense; in fact, St. Anselm does so
himself farther on.[218] Tournely holds that the Incarnation is absolutely
necessary after the fall of the human race, if God wills to free the human race
from sin.
On the contrary, it is the common teaching among theologians that the
Incarnation is not absolutely necessary even after the fall of the human race,
even if it is granted that God willed to free the human race from sin, because
there were other means of liberation; but it was necessary secundum quid. Suarez
thinks that it would be rash to deny this common opinion of the theologians; so
does Lugo. In fact, Valentia says that the conclusion is most certain, which
means that it is a theological conclusion commonly admitted by the theologians,
one which is supported by many testimonies of the Fathers of the Church.[219]
St. Thomas, who firmly holds this conclusion, begins by positing difficulties
that are against even the secundum quid necessity of the Incarnation. He argues
that the Incarnation does not seem to be necessary even secundum quid because:
(1) for the reparation of the human race, the non-incarnate Word can do whatever
the incarnate Word can do; therefore the Incarnation is not absolutely
necessary. (2) God must not demand from man greater satisfaction than man can
give. (3) It is better if there had been no Incarnation, because the more men
consider God as raised above all creatures and removed from sense perception,
the more they reverence Him. But God's dignity seems to be lowered by assuming
human flesh.
Yet the answer is:
1) The Incarnation is not indeed absolutely necessary for the reparation of
the human race. (2) But it was necessary secundum quid, namely, as a better and
more convenient means.
First Part:
Authoritative proof. A. Billuart holds[220] that this second opinion is the
unanimous teaching of the Fathers; he mentions SS. Athanasius, Gregory
Nazianzen, Theodoret, Cyril of Alexandria, Gregory the Great, and John
Damascene. Likewise St. Augustine in one of his works says: "Foolish people
say that the only way by which God in His wisdom could liberate mankind was by
becoming man, and by suffering all He did from sinners. To these persons we say
that such was absolutely possible for God, but if He had done otherwise, this
likewise would have been displeasing to your stupidity."[221]
B. Proof from reason. Concerning this first part of the thesis, St. Thomas
says: "God of His omnipotent power could have restored human nature in many
other ways."[222] What ways were these?
In the first place, God could have pardoned the offense committed against Him
by sin. Tournely denies the possibility of this way by God's ordinary power,
because the preservation of justice requires punishment of the offense.
We reply to this objection, according to the mind of St. Thomas,[223] by
saying that the supreme judge and legislator can do so, since He is above other
judges, and therefore enjoys the prerogative of being able to pardon offenders
even without demanding reparation, just as sometimes kings bestow a favor upon
or are merciful to those condemned to death.
Or again, God could have accepted some sort of satisfaction from man, or as
it pleased Him to accept it; for there is no contradiction implied in these ways
of pardoning by Him, and God is absolutely free in His operations ad extra.
Or, as we said in the statement of the question, God could even have willed
not to restore the human race, although it is extremely fitting for Him to do
so.
Proof of thesis (second part). This part states that the Incarnation was
secundum quid necessary for the reparation of the human race, as being the
better way.
First of all, there is the authority of St. Augustine, who holds that the
Incarnation was more fitting than any other way for the reparation of the human
race.
St. Thomas offers a fine theological proof, in which he shows the fitness of
the Incarnation on the part of man, just as in the first article of this
question he showed its fitness on the part of God, who, being the supreme good,
is in the highest degree self-diffusive. His argument may be reduced to the
following syllogism.
That way is better for the reparation of the human race, by which man is
better and more easily urged to good and withdrawn from evil. But each of these
results is obtained by the Incarnation. Therefore the Incarnation is the better
way for the reparation of the human race. The major is evident.
The minor is proved, as regards our furtherance in good, by a consideration
of the theological virtues, which are higher than all the other virtues, for God
is their immediate object and the ultimate end to whom the sinner must be
converted.
Faith is made more certain by the Incarnation, for the very reason that by it
we believe God Himself who is speaking.
For the formal motive of faith is the authority of God revealing; but God,
who is most exalted, remains hidden from us, even though He speaks to us through
the prophets, whose preaching is confirmed by miracles. How much more we are
confirmed in the faith, if God Himself comes to us, and speaks to us as a human
being, not as the scribes did, but as one having authority, saying: "Amen,
amen, I say unto you: he that believeth in Me, hath everlasting life."[224]
This argument seems paradoxical to those who say, as the liberal Protestants
do, that Christianity is the most exalted type of religion, provided that the
dogma of Christ's divinity be eliminated from it. They say this, since they are
imbued with the spirit of rationalism that seeks to judge all things by human
reason, and not as God sees them.
On the contrary, if we consider this matter in the spirit of faith, this
argument is seen to be most fitting and also most exalted, and not one made up
by St. Augustine, who is quoted in this article, but as contained already in the
very preaching of Christ and His apostles. Jesus Himself says: "I am one
that give testimony of Myself, and the Father that sent Me giveth testimony of
Me."[225] No prophet spoke words like these, for only Christ can say such
words, because He alone, as He Himself said, "is the truth and the
life."[226] He is the First Truth, who gives testimony of Himself, and so
He is the formal motive of faith, namely, the authority of God actually
revealing, and this authority is confirmed by miracles evident to the senses.
Similarly Jesus says: "The words which Thou gayest Me I have given to them.
And they have received them and have known in very deed that I came out from
Thee; and they have believed that Thou didst send Me."[227] Hence the
Evangelist writes: "The Samaritans said to the woman: We now believe not
for thy saying, for we ourselves have heard Him, and we know that this is indeed
the Savior of the world."[228]
Likewise St. John says in his prologue: "And of His fullness we have all
received.... No man hath seen God at any time; the only-begotten Son who is in
the bosom of the Father, He hath declared Him."[229]
Similarly St. John says: "That which was from the beginning, which we
have heard, which we have seen with our eyes, which we have looked upon, and our
hands have handled of the World of life. For the life was manifested, and we
have seen and do bear witness and declare unto you the life eternal, which was
with the Father, and hath appeared to us."[230] This means that you can
believe because what we announce to you we have heard from the Word incarnate,
whom we saw by our sense of sight, whom we looked upon, and whom we touched with
our hands.
Likewise St. Paul writes: "God who at sundry times and in divers manners
spoke in times past to the fathers by the prophets, last of all in these days
hath spoken to us by His Son, whom He hath appointed heir of all things, by whom
also He hath made the world."[231] And again he says: "For if the
word, spoken by angels, became stead fast... how shall we escape... what has
been declared by the Lord, ... God also bearing them witness by signs and
wonders."[232] This means that Christ is a more exalted witness than the
angels.
These texts serve to illustrate the argument of St. Thomas, who says that by
the Incarnation our faith is reassured since we believe God Himself speaking to
us, that is, speaking to us as man in His assumed nature. As St. Augustine says:
"In order that man might journey more trustfully toward the truth, the
Truth itself, the Son of God, having assumed human nature, established and
founded faith."[233]
Certainly in this life we see Christ's divinity neither by the sense of sight
nor mentally; but Jesus with so great authority speaks to us, saying: "I
give testimony of Myself,"[234] making Himself equal to God, so that no man
of good will can doubt that Jesus is truly the living God, who is speaking to
us. I say: no man of good will in the salutary sense of the Gospel, that is,
neither resisting revelation, nor internal inspiration given to one for the
purpose of believing.
When Christ says, "Come to Me, all you that labor and are burdened, and
I will refresh you... he that loveth father or mother more than Me, is not
worthy of Me,"[235] He means men of good will who do not resist the grace
of faith, do not doubt that He is more than a mere man, more than a prophet,
because no prophet uttered such words; and they are certain that Christ is the
First Truth, who is speaking to us. And it is precisely such great authority as
this that proves unbearable to the Pharisees, who therefore turn away from Him.
In other words, what is the greatest light on this earth for men of good
will, becomes obscurity for them. This means that what most of all confirms the
faith of men of good will, becomes a source of scandal for them, as Simeon
foretold, saying: "Behold this Child is set for the fall and for the
resurrection of many in Israel and for a sign that shall be
contradicted."[236] For this reason Christ Himself said: "Blessed is
he that shall not be scandalized in Me."[237] Our argument was imputed
formerly as an objection to our Lord's opponents, and is so too in our days for
the rationalists, who, so they say, would be willing to admit the truth of
Christianity if it did not include the dogma of Christ's divinity, which means
that they would accept Christianity if it were no longer Christianity, but only
a higher form of the evolution of natural religion. Thus the greatest light is
turned for them into obscurity; but this light is essentially illuminating, and
it is only accidentally that it has a blinding effect, that is, on account of
the bad disposition of the hearer. As St. Augustine says: "Light is
annoying to those of defective eyesight, but it is very welcome to those of good
eyesight."[238]
Thus the argument remains most firm, namely, that our faith is made more
certain by the Incarnation, since we believe God who speaks to us as man in His
assumed human nature. The formal motive of faith is reduced to almost sensible
proportions inasmuch it is the supreme authority of Christ speaking. Hence we
read in the Gospel that the ministers sent by the Pharisees feared to arrest
Jesus, and replied to the chief priests: "Never did man speak like this
man."[239] They meant, never did any man utter words so sublime, or in such
an exalted and divine manner; for there was a sensible manifestation of
something divine in Christ's tone and manner of speech.
St. Thomas says that by the Incarnation we are greatly strengthened in hope.
Why is this? It is because hope is a theological virtue that longs for the
supreme future and possible good, indeed, but difficult of attainment. Its
formal motive is God helping, who has promised us His help not only to keep His
commandments that are always possible to observe, but also to save our souls.
Hence hope is trust in God, and this trust increases in us inasmuch as God
not only promises His help, but actually bestows it, and manifests His
benevolence even in a way that appeals to our senses. Thus we place our trust
especially in friends, because we know their help comes from motives of true and
deep love for us.
But by the Incarnation God not only gives us His help, which means not only
His grace, but He gives us the Author of grace, who remains present in the Holy
Eucharist, which very much increases the virtue of hope in us. It is what St.
Augustine says in the passage quoted by St. Thomas in this article.
Thus the virtue of hope is very much strengthened in us since Christ says
more reassuringly than any prophet: "Come to Me all you that labor and are
burdened, and I will refresh you."[240] I am He who helps, I am the Author
of salvation. Similarly, when Jesus says to the paralytic, before healing him:
"Thy sins are forgiven thee,"[241] that is, your soul is healed,
whereas you were demanding only the cure of a bodily ailment. Likewise St. Paul
formulated this argument in equivalent words when he wrote: "The mystery
which hath been hidden from ages and generations, but now is manifested to His
saints, to whom God would make known the riches of the glory of this mystery
among the Gentiles, which is Christ in you the hope of glory."[242] Again
he writes: "Christ our hope,"[243] for Christ Himself, as God, is both
the object and the motive of our hope, for God Himself is both helper and
helping.
The following special text of St. Paul must here be quoted: "If God be
for us, who is against us? He that spared not even His own Son, but delivered
Him up for us all, how shall He not also, with Him, give us all things? Who
shall accuse against the elect of God?... Who is He that shall condemn? Christ
Jesus that died, yea that is risen also again, who is at the right hand of God,
who also maketh intercession for us. Who then shall separate us from the love of
Christ? Shall tribulation or distress or famine... or persecution or the
sword?... But in all these things we overcome because of Him that has loved
us."[244] In other words, in all these things we overcome, because of the
efficacy of the help of Him who loved us; and in the opinion of St. Augustine
and St. Thomas this help is of itself efficacious, and not because our consent
was foreseen by God.
The formal motive of hope is not man's effort cooperating with God's help,
but it is God helping, who, by the Incarnation is with us and remains present in
the Holy Eucharist. Thus we have the greatest reason for trusting in God.
Thirdly, by the Incarnation "charity is greatly enkindled," says
St. Thomas, who quotes here St. Augustine as saying: "What greater cause is
there of the Lord's coming than to show God's love for us?" And St.
Augustine afterward adds: "If we have been slow to love, at least let us
hasten to love in return."[245]
Charity obliges us to love God more than we love ourselves, loving Him as our
friend, the formal motive of our love being His goodness, which infinitely
surpasses all His favors bestowed upon us. This means that we must will
efficaciously the fulfillment of His will, that He may reign truly and
profoundly in souls and be glorified forever, since the Scripture says:
"Not to us, O Lord, not to us; but to Thy name give glory."[246] What
has been said constitutes the definition of charity that surpasses hope, just as
the love of benevolence surpasses the love of concupiscence, no matter how much
this latter be upright and ordered to its proper end. By the virtue of hope, I
desire God for myself, but as my final end, indeed, because He is God. By the
virtue of charity, however, I love God efficaciously as my friend, and I love
Him more than I love myself, and I will Him all befitting good. This most
sublime aspect of charity, more than anything hope can offer, will enable us to
cease worrying, too, about the mystery of predestination, notwithstanding its
great obscurity. By charity I love God more than myself, and in a general way
whatever God has eternally decreed in manifestation of His goodness. Thus God,
who is infinitely good, is the eminent source of all goodness being a quasi-ego
to myself, and in a certain sense more an ego than I am, for whatever good I
possess already is contained in Him in a far more eminent manner. This is that
true mysticism which is certainly the normal way to holiness.
But this divine goodness, which is the formal object of charity, is
especially made manifest by the supreme act of love in which God gave us His
only-begotten Son.[247] It is the fundamental truth of Christianity, because
this love is the fountain source of the very gift of the Incarnation. Hence
Jesus says: "As the Father hath loved Me, I also have loved you. Abide in
My love."[248] And again: "Greater love than this no man hath, that a
man lay down his life for his friends."[249] St. John writes: "By this
hath the charity of God appeared toward us, because God hath sent His
only-begotten Son into the world, that we may live by Him. In this is charity,
not as though we had loved God, but because He hath first loved us, and sent His
Son to be a propitiation for our sins. My dearest, if God hath so loved us, we
also ought to love one another."[250] Farther on he says: "Let us
therefore love God, because God first hath loved us."[251]
Likewise St. Paul says: "But God commendeth His charity toward us,
because when as yet we were sinners, according to the time, Christ died for
us."[252] Writing to Titus, he says: "For the grace of God our Savior
hath appeared to all men, instructing us, that denying ungodliness and worldly
desires... we should live Godly in this world, looking for the blessed hope and
coming of the glory of the great God and our Savior Jesus Christ."[253]
Thus these three arguments of St. Thomas not only result in a theologically
certain conclusion, but they pertain to the faith, and are the sublime object of
contemplation. It is also evident that this contemplation, which proceeds from
faith illumined by the gifts of the Holy Ghost, is the normal way to holiness of
life.
Fourth, the incarnation of the Word sets us an example in the practice of all
virtues, whereas Diogenes and several other philosophers said that the search
for an exemplar in virtues is a vain quest. It is only Christ who could say to
His adversaries: "Which of you shall convince Me of sin?',[254] Hence
holiness of life consists in the imitation of Christ.
Fifth. The Incarnation is most appropriate for withdrawing us from evil.
1) Because man by the Incarnation is instructed to despise the devil
conquered by Christ even as man, as stated in the legend of St. Christopher.
2) Because by the Incarnation we begin to realize the dignity of our human
nature, so that we are urged not to stain our soul by sin.
3) Because the Incarnation takes away all presumption from us since God, s
grace, regardless of any previous merits on our part, is approved in us or
bestowed upon us through Jesus Christ, so that St. Paul is able to say: "By
the grace of God I am what I am."[255] The sinner, too, who has committed
all crimes, can repent by trusting in the infinite merits of Christ.
4) Pride is removed and cured by a consideration of the humiliating
conditions of the passion of our Lord.
5) Man is freed from the slavery of the devil and of sin. As St. Thomas says
in this article in equivalent words: God, by assuming our human nature, did not
lessen His majesty and attracted us more by this means to know Him.[256]
Therefore the Incarnation is a more fitting way of freeing the human race
from sin. Nevertheless, God could have chosen not to become man, and this would
not have been derogatory to Him, for the Incarnation was a most free act, and an
absolutely gratuitous gift.
Hence we must say that it was more fitting for God to become incarnate, but
it would not have been inconsistent with God's goodness if He had not become
incarnate. Similarly, it was more fitting for God to have created and raised man
to the supernatural order, but it would not have been derogatory to His goodness
if He had not done so. Thus in human actions, virginity is more perfect than
matrimony, but there is nothing unbecoming in matrimony. There is freedom of
choice in both cases.
The only remaining difficulty is the one proposed in the second objection of
this article, namely, that it does not seem proper for God to demand greater
satisfaction than man can give.
St. Thomas replies to this objection by giving a brief summary of the
doctrine on satisfaction. He remarks that it would not, indeed, be fitting if
God had not given His Son as Redeemer to make the greater satisfaction. But God
gave His Son. This difficulty gives us the opportunity to present certain doubts
that must be examined in amplification of the doctrine of this article.
First doubt. Was the Incarnation necessary so as to have condign satisfaction
for sin?
St. Thomas examines this question in his reply to the second objection of
this article.
State of the question. Satisfaction is the compensation or voluntary payment
of any debt. It is of various kinds, as may be seen by the following schema.
[diagram page 65]
SATISFACTION
perfect
considered as a formal act of justice, it is called rigorous satisfaction;
considered on the part of the offense, it is called condign satisfaction.
imperfect
considered also on the part of the offense it is called congruent
satisfaction.
St. Thomas distinguishes between two kinds of satisfaction.
1) Satisfaction is perfectly sufficient, he says, when it is condign, being
in a certain sense adequate in reparation of the fault committed. Thus, if
anyone has to pay another a debt of one hundred dollars, and returns the
complete sum, then he is said to have made perfect satisfaction in a material
sense. Moreover, that the satisfaction be perfect in the formal sense, or as an
act of justice, the restitution must be made out of the debtor, s own
belongings, and must not be owing to the creditor on some other account, nor in
any way under his dominion. The last condition is that the creditor is bound to
accept the payment as satisfaction.
Perfect satisfaction considered merely materially is called condign
satisfaction. Perfect satisfaction in the formal sense is called rigorous or
according to the strictest standard of justice.
2) Imperfect satisfaction also in the material sense, or what is not condign,
is that which is deemed sufficient, and which a person is contented to accept as
satisfactory. Thus, if anyone is bound to pay back one hundred dollars, and
returns eighty, the creditor being satisfied with this sum, such satisfaction is
often called congruent.
Three certain conclusions follow from these distinctions.
1) Mere man can in the material sense satisfy imperfectly for sin. This
conclusion is expressed in equivalent words by St. Thomas toward the end of his
reply to the second objection. The expression "mere man" does not mean
the exclusion of grace, but only of the divine nature. Thus a just person can
satisfy imperfectly for his own mortal sin, or for another's, by a satisfaction
which God can accept, if He so wills, and which He could have accepted, if He
had not willed to free man from sin by the Incarnation. So also in this life our
satisfactions for our sins, or in reparation for the sins of others, are
imperfect even in the material sense. Hence St. Thomas says: "The
satisfaction of every mere man has its efficiency from the satisfaction of
Christ,"[257] even the satisfaction of the Blessed Virgin Mary. Therefore
she is not called co-redemptress except in a subordinate sense to Christ, as
being quasi sub-redemptress.
Hence Pope Pius X ratified the common teaching of theologians, when he said:
"That which Christ merited for us de condigno, the Blessed Virgin Mary
merited for us de congruo."[258] And likewise she did not satisfy for us de
condigno, but de congruo. Pope Benedict XV declared: "It can truly be said
that along with Christ she redeemed the human race,"[259] that is,
subordinate to Christ with Him, and through Him, the Blessed Virgin Mary's
satisfaction was not condign but congruent, or an imperfect satisfaction, which
was not of itself (apart from Christ's redemption) perfectly sufficient.
2) Mere man cannot offer complete satisfaction to God for his own sin or for
another's. This means that he cannot satisfy according to the strictest standard
of justice, because there is nothing either in the natural order or in the
supernatural order that he can offer to God which has not been bestowed upon him
by God who is His creditor and which God is bound to accept in satisfaction.
Thus the Holy See approved the following statement of a provincial council:
"No one but the God-man was able to satisfy in strict justice."[260]
3) Mere man could not satisfy de condigno for his own or another's mortal
sin; and for such condign reparation the Incarnation was necessary.
This conclusion, which is commonly admitted by theologians, is considered
certain by St. Thomas, and occurs in the beginning of his reply to the second
objection. However, some theologians. following Scotus and Durandus, admitted
that some creature, adorned with a very high degree of grace, such as the
Blessed Virgin Mary, could satisfy adequately for mortal sin.
There are proofs for this third conclusion.
Authoritative proof. St. Augustine says: "We would not have been
liberated through the one mediator between God and man, the man Jesus Christ,
unless He were also God."[261] Likewise, St. Leo says: "It He were not
truly God, He could not apply the remedy; if He were not truly man, He could not
give us the example."[262]
This traditional and common opinion among theologians was approved recently
by Pope Pius XI, who wrote concerning Mary reparatrix: "If the Son of God
had not assumed our human nature for the purpose of repairing it, no created
power sufficed to expiate the crimes of men."[263]
Thus the traditional thesis is now a ratified pontifical document, and is
theologically certain, being an approved theological conclusion.
Theological proof. St. Thomas gives two reasons why adequate satisfaction was
impossible. This he does in his reply to the second objection of this article.
a) Condign satisfaction was impossible by mere man "because the whole of
human nature has been corrupted by sin," and only a just person can merit
de condigno and satisfy. But some may say that God could have preserved some man
from original sin, or could have sanctified him after the sin was committed and
bestowed a high degree of grace upon him so that he could satisfy for it.
The second reason replies to this suggestion.
b) This reason may be presented by the following syllogism. Mortal sin
committed against God has a certain infinity considered as an offense. But
condign satisfaction must be adequate reparation. Therefore condign satisfaction
must have infinite efficacy, as being the satisfactory act of one who is both
God and man.
St. Thomas proves the major by saying: "A sin committed against God has
a kind of infinity from the infinity of the divine majesty, because the greater
the person we offend, the more grievous the offense."[264]
Yet not all Thomists interpret this major in the same sense.[265]
Some theologians say that St. Thomas wrote that "mortal sin has a kind
of infinity"[266]. as an offense. Therefore its gravity is not absolutely
infinite, but only in a qualified sense and objectively; for sin as an act of
the will is always finite. Likewise, its malice, since it is a turning to
changeable good, is finite; so it does not merit absolutely infinite punishment,
for the penalty of damnation consists in the deprivation of the beatific vision,
which is something created, although it concerns God objectively. So say certain
Thomists such as Soto, Conradus, along with Scotus, Suarez, and Vasquez.
Others say that the gravity of mortal sin is absolutely infinite, not indeed
considered as a physical act, nor as a moral act because of its malice and
demerit, but because it is an offense. Briefly, a grievous offense against God
is absolutely infinite. Such is the view of Capreolus, Cajetan, Gonet,
Salmanticenses, and John of St. Thomas.[267]
These theologians say that, more probably mortal sin, because it is an
offense, is absolutely infinite in gravity, and this for the reason given by St.
Thomas, namely, "because the greater the person we offend, the more
grievous the offense."[268] But He who is the supreme good, who is the
ultimate end, who is practically denied by mortal sin, is absolutely infinite in
dignity; whereas man prefers the creature to God and loves himself more than
God. If it were not so, then St. Thomas would be wrong in concluding the
necessity of infinite satisfaction.
St. Thomas also says: "Since God infinitely transcends the creature,
mortal sin committed against God is an infinite offense, by reason of the
dignity of Him to whom somehow harm is done by sin, since God Himself and His
precept are despised."[269]
Moreover, the offense is morally in the person offended, inasmuch as the
person offended is truly the victim of injustice. Hence the greater is the
dignity of the person offended, the greater is the offense. Thus it is a greater
offense to insult a genera than a soldier, and a king than a general. Hence to
insult God is absolutely infinite as a moral act, inasmuch as it practically
denies God the infinite dignity owing to Him as the ultimate end or as the
infinite good.
Nevertheless, one mortal sin can be more grievous than another in three ways,
either because it is committed with greater deliberation and consent; or,
objectively considered, because it is more directed against God; or by reason of
the circumstances.
Most certainly the gravity of the offense is estimated according to the
dignity of the person offended, whereas the value of the reparation is estimated
according to the dignity of the person who makes reparation. The whole force of
the argument rests on this statement.
Objection. Some say that although God, who is infinite, is the object of the
act of charity, this act is not absolutely infinite in dignity as a moral act.
Therefore, although mortal sin offends God who is infinite, considered as an
offense in the moral order, it is not absolutely infinite in gravity.
Reply. The difference is that, as regards charity, God is only its object and
not its subject; but He is the subject of the moral offense committed against
Him. Thus, as stated, the greater the dignity of the person offended, the
greater is the gravity of the offense. On the contrary, although God can be the
object of venial sin, it does not deny Him the infinite dignity owing to Him as
the ultimate end, and thus its offense is not absolutely infinite.
Briefly, a grievous offense against God is absolutely infinite, since it is
practically a denial of His absolutely infinite dignity.
This comparison between a mere man's act of charity that is of finite value,
and a grave and absolutely infinite offense against God, is founded on the
principle that in our negations concerning God there is more of denial than
there is of assertion in our affirmations.[270]
A practical denial of the dignity of the ultimate end denies more about it,
than its practical affirmation can affirm about it. Hence the general saying
that it is easier to destroy than to build. In a moment a man can destroy very
precious objects, which only after a long time can be replaced; and it is
generally admitted that an inferior can do more against a superior than for him.
Matter, by escaping from the domination of its form, can do more against the
form of a corporeal thing, such as a plant or an animal, than for it by
remaining under it, because without matter this form, for instance, of a lion,
totally disappears, but matter alone is not sufficient for the sensitive life of
the lion. The mineral kingdom can do more harm to man, for instance, in an
earthquake, than good to him; likewise the lack of air necessary for breathing
causes death, whereas its presence is not sufficient; for life, food and other
things are also required.
Similarly in the human order, a common man can do great harm to a king, but
he cannot render him all the honors that are due to him. Likewise the common
people can be the source of more affliction to men of great ability than joy to
them. In like manner, if it is said of a good doctor that he is not so in the
medical art, this judgment grieves him more than the opposite judgment could
cause him to rejoice.
Generally speaking, the inferior can do more harm to the superior than good
to him. Proud Satan is conscious of this; the devil wishes to have power not
from grace, but in his own right; and so he wishes to have the power to destroy,
which is tantamount to saying: I am preventing the development of the kingdom of
God; it is for this reason that I exist and have power.
Hence the truth of the principle: the inferior can do more harm than good to
the superior.
Thus it is that the subordination of the inferior helps to some extent the
action of the superior, whereas his insubordination sometimes totally impedes
it.
The reason is that frequently the inferior is an indispensable condition for
the action of the superior, and the lack of this cooperation results in not only
a partial but a total frustration of the action of the higher power, as in the
case of insanity resulting from a cerebral lesion there follows a total
impossibility of judgment. When the brain is in good condition it is of some
help to the reasoning faculty, whereas, if seriously damaged, it completely
prevents the act of reasoning. Thus many men who enjoy the best of health have
not much intellectual ability; but a man of great intellect suddenly becomes
insane because of a cerebral lesion.
Likewise, man of himself can do more against God, against the kingdom of God
by blaspheming, than he can do for God by honoring Him. Man in the purely
natural state suffices for the complete denial of God's ineffable greatness, but
he is afterward incapable of completely affirming this greatness, even though
restored by grace. Our negations are more absolute in their effect than our
affirmations. When the impious person denies God, he denies God completely in
his heart; when the just person affirms God, he does not affirm Him completely,
but in a finite manner, and, as St. Thomas says, "we cannot know what God
is, but rather what He is not."[271] To comprehend is to equate in
knowledge the knowable object. God alone has comprehensive knowledge of Himself,
which attains to the whole of Him and to all that is contained in Him.[272]
In like manner anyone who denies the principle of finality, completely denies
it; on the contrary, anyone who affirms the principle of finality, does not
completely understand it. This principle, that, "every agent acts for an
end," is known better by an angel, and a fortiori by God. Therefore a
grievous offense against God is absolutely infinite, since it denies to God
absolutely infinite dignity of the ultimate end, or the supreme Good.
Our grave disobedience toward God is graver because of the offense, than our
due subjection to Him contributes to His eternal glory. It remains true,
therefore, that the gravity of the offense is estimated according to the dignity
of the person offended, whereas the value of the reparation is estimated
according to the dignity of the person making reparation.
But what is the validity of the minor, that is, that condign satisfaction
must be adequate reparation, and hence it must be of infinite value?
Proof of minor. Condign compensation must offer to God what is no less or
more pleasing to Him than the offense is displeasing to Him.
St. Thomas says: "He properly atones for an offense who offers something
which the offended one loves equally or even more than he detested the offense.
But by suffering out of love and obedience, Christ gave more to God than was
required to compensate for the offense of the whole human race. First of all
because of the exceeding charity from which He suffered; secondly on account of
the dignity of His life which He laid down in atonement, for it was the life of
one who was God and man; thirdly on account of the extent of the Passion, and
the greatness of the grief endured."[273]
The reason why this satisfaction is of infinite value is that it was offered
to God from the charity of the Word incarnate, namely, of the divine person
whose theandric act is of infinite price, since the estimated value of the
satisfaction is derived from a consideration of the person making satisfaction.
On the contrary, an absolutely infinite injury cannot be condignly repaired
by a satisfaction of finite value. But the satisfaction of any creature whatever
is of finite value; for the value of the satisfaction is derived, as has been
said, from a consideration of the person satisfying, inasmuch as this person is
the subject who satisfies. Hence the common saying that honor is in the person
honoring.
Therefore the greater the dignity of the person satisfying, the greater the
estimate of the satisfaction. Hence the satisfaction of Christ is absolutely
infinite, because the person satisfying is divine and infinite. On the contrary,
the dignity of the creature who satisfies is finite, no matter what may be the
number of his supernatural gifts. Therefore a finite creature cannot give
adequate satisfaction for an absolutely infinite offense.
This is the reason given by St. Thomas in his reply to the second objection
of this article. But on this point, the knowledge acquired through the gifts of
the Holy Ghost is of a much higher order and more striking than discursive
knowledge.
Second doubt. Would the Incarnation be necessary if the gravity of the
offense were only in a qualified manner infinite?
Would the reason given by St. Thomas still be valid if the grievous offense
against God were not absolutely infinite, but only in a qualified manner, that
is, objectively, as the act of charity is said to be objectively infinite?
Some Thomists, such as Billuart,[274] reply that the reason given by St.
Thomas has still some value, in this sense, that the gravity of mortal sin does
not consist only in this, that it denies God His dignity as the ultimate end,
but that also the depreciation and contempt of the divine majesty comes from a
vile creature, who presumes to offend Him. This injury is not compensated by an
act of charity of a mere man, because it is more injurious to God to be
subjected to a vile creature than the subjection of this creature to Him pays
Him honor. Similarly it is more against the king's dignity to be insulted by one
of his ministers, than it adds to his honor for him to accept the apology of his
minister.
But the reason as proposed is no longer strictly the reason given by St.
Thomas, which is derived not from a consideration of the vileness of the person
offending, but from the supreme dignity of the person offended. Hence from what
St. Thomas says,[275] it is clearly enough evident that he considers a grievous
offense against God to be absolutely infinite, inasmuch as it is practically a
denial of His absolutely infinite dignity. We have said that such is the
conclusion of very many Thomists, namely, of Capreolus, Cajetan, Salmanticenses,
Godoy, Gonet, John of St. Thomas, Billuart.
Third doubt. Can a just man offer condign satisfaction for venial sin?
Reply. The answer is that he can; for a just man can make reparation for
venial sin and therefore satisfy for it, because venial sin does not take away
from the soul habitual grace, which is the root of the supernatural life, nor
does it turn us away from the ultimate end. Moreover, the injury included in
venial sin does not deny God His absolutely infinite dignity as the ultimate
end. Therefore this injury is not absolutely infinite but finite. Therefore it
can be repaired by what remains of the virtue of charity.
Cajetan in his commentary on this article examines other objections raised by
Scotus; but these belong more properly to the article on the passion of our
Lord, in which St. Thomas asks whether it brought about our salvation by way of
atonement.[276]
It must be noted that the thesis of St. Thomas on the necessity of the
Incarnation so as to satisfy de condigno for mortal sin is absolutely in
conformity with tradition. The Fathers frequently have proved, from the dogma of
the redemption admitted by heretics, that Christ was truly God.[277]
Solution Of Objections Against The Reply To The First Doubt
The Incarnation was not necessary to satisfy de condigno for sin.
First objection. Condign satisfaction returns to the one offended all that
was taken away by mortal sin. But mere man justified by an act of charity
returns to God all that was taken away by mortal sin, namely, it returns
lovingly what is His due as being the ultimate end. Therefore mere man justified
can offer condign satisfaction to God for mortal sin, and so the Incarnation is
not necessary.
Reply. I distinguish the major. Condign satisfaction that returns all, and
all that is implied by an act that is equal to the gravity of the offense, then
I concede the major.
That returns all, but not all that is implied by an act that is not equal to
the gravity of the offense, then I deny it.
I contradistinguish the minor in the same way.
Satisfaction for wrong done requires more than the mere restitution of the
object stolen; it also requires that the object taken be returned with due
compensation for slighted honor. Thus, if a commoner snatched a king's daughter,
it would not suffice for condign satisfaction that the daughter be returned, for
in this way reparation for the wrong done to the king would not be made.
Similarly, God's dignity is far more offended when the creature despises Him,
than honor is paid to Him by the creature's subjection to Him even by an act of
charity. Insubordination is not sufficiently repaired by the restitution of
subordination that is already due Him.
Mortal sin of any kind offends God's right, His right of being the ultimate
end, and therefore every mortal sin is an insult to God, not always explicitly
intended as in blasphemy, but resulting as a consequence of the sin. Although
man cannot render to God whatever is due Him according to strictest justice, yet
he can be strictly unjust to Him by practically denying Him His absolutely
infinite dignity to which He is entitled as the ultimate end.
Second objection. He who can merit de condigno for others the grace of
forgiveness of mortal sin, can likewise satisfy de condigno for the mortal sin
of others. But a mere man mercifully justified and constituted the head of the
human race could merit de condigno for others the grace of forgiveness of sin,
which is admitted by several Thomists, such as John of St. Thomas. Therefore
this mere man could satisfy de condigno for the mortal sin of others.
Reply. I deny the major, because there is no parity between merit and
satisfaction. Merit is the right to a proportionate reward in accordance with
distributive justice, whereas satisfaction concerns the equal compensation of
another, in accordance with the standard of commutative justice, by making
equivalent reparation for the wrong done. Hence this mere man would give only a
modified satisfaction that would fall short of condign satisfaction, and thus
God would condone the offense without receiving condign satisfaction, just as
the father in family life condones the offense of a younger son on account of
the merits of an elder son. Mere man cannot "offer to God offended
something He loves equally or even more than He detests the offense."[278]
Another objection. The incarnate Word did not have a higher degree of virtue
than the non-incarnate Word. But the incarnate Word could satisfy de condigno.
Therefore the non-incarnate Word could satisfy de condigno.
Reply. I distinguish the major. That the Word incarnate had also certain
virtues properly His own as man, this I concede. Otherwise I deny the major.
I contradistinguish the minor. That the Word incarnate could satisfy as the
Word in the divine nature, this I deny. As the incarnate Word, that is, as man,
this I concede.
God could have restored the human race by condoning the offense without
demanding satisfaction; but as God, He could not have obeyed, suffered, prayed,
offered sacrifice of reparation to God, and merited.
But I insist. The non-incarnate Word also had strictly the power to satisfy.
The power to satisfy implies any good without admixture of evil. But the
non-incarnate Word has whatever is good without any admixture of evil. Therefore
the non-incarnate Word has strictly the power to satisfy.
Reply. I distinguish the major; that it implies any good without admixture of
moral evil, this I concede; no admixture of physical perfection on the part of
created nature, this I deny.
I contradistinguish the minor. That the non-incarnate Word has all good
without admixture of any imperfection whatever, this I concede; otherwise, I
deny the minor.
In other words, mixed perfections are not contained formally, but only
virtually in the non-incarnate Word.
Still I insist. The non-incarnate Word can have formally, without becoming
incarnate, strictly the power to satisfy. The Word can assume the angelic
nature. But by assuming this nature the Word can satisfy formally. Therefore the
Word can satisfy formally without becoming incarnate.
Reply. I concede the major.
I distinguish the minor. That the Word can satisfy by satisfaction improperly
so called that is freely accepted by God, let it pass without comment; by
satisfaction in the strict sense, as offered by the Word in the human nature for
our redemption, this I deny.
In like manner I distinguish the conclusion.
Final objection. Mere man can satisfy for venial sin. But a slight offense is
infinite, if the distance between the offender and the offended is infinite.
Reply. The gravity of the offense is not estimated formally from the
distance, but it is estimated from the dignity of the person offended; and the
dignity of God as the ultimate end is practically denied only by mortal sin.
Third Article: Whether, If Man Had Not Sinned, God Would Have Become
Incarnate?
State of the question. We are concerned here not only with the fitness of the
Incarnation, which was discussed in the first article, but also with the
proximate motive of the efficacious decree of the Incarnation: the motive,
namely, not on the part of God willing, but on the part of the thing willed; for
God does not will one thing on account of another, but He wills one thing to be
as a means for the other.[279] The question precisely is this, whether, in
virtue of the present decree, God so willed the Incarnation for the redemption
of the human race, that if man had not sinned, the Word would not have become
incarnate.
At the time of St. Thomas there was difference of opinion among the doctors
on this question. Alexander of Hales and St. Albert held it to be more probable
in virtue of the present decree, even if man had not sinned, that God would have
become incarnate. This thesis was afterward more tenaciously defended by Scotus
and the Scotists.
On the contrary, St. Bonaventure and St. Thomas declare it to be more
probable that, if man had not sinned, the Word of God would not have become
incarnate. St. Thomas claims only greater probability for his answer.[280] In
the present article, he says: "It is more fitting to say."
For a methodical method of procedure in this complex enough question, let us
consider:
1) The difficulties of the question as set forth by St. Thomas at the
beginning of this article, are arguments in favor of the opposite opinion.
2) The solution of St. Thomas.
3) The stand taken by Scotus.
4) How Cajetan, John of St. Thomas, and Billuart interpret the teaching of
St. Thomas.
5) Godoy, Gonet, and Salmanticenses give another interpretation, Capreolus
being quoted for this view.
6) The solution of the objections advanced by Scotus against this second
interpretation, which seems to be more probable.[281]
Since the question is complex, we must say right at the beginning, that we
wish especially to defend this truth, which seems to us to be admitted by all,
namely, God willed the Incarnation for the manifestation of His goodness, to
show His mercy toward men to be redeemed, as the Creed says, "for our
salvation." We intend and understand nothing else but that: God, by one
sole efficacious decree thus willed the Incarnation.
1) The difficulties of the question are evident from the objections posited
at the beginning of this article. They are almost the same as those proposed by
St. Thomas in one of his earlier works.[282] They reproduce the opinion on this
question that was held by Alexander of Hales and St. Albert, an opinion that was
afterward developed by Scotus. From these objections it is apparent that St.
Thomas had a very good knowledge of the state of the question.
First difficulty. St. Augustine says: "Many other things are to be
considered in the incarnation of Christ besides absolution from sin."[283]
Hence, even if man had not sinned, God would have become incarnate. In that
event, He would not have been the savior and the victim, but the teacher, the
mediator, the King of kings for all mankind.
Second difficulty. The purpose of God in creating is to manifest His goodness
and omnipotence; but it belongs to God, s omnipotence to perfect His works by
some infinite effect, namely, by the Incarnation.
Third difficulty. Human nature has not been made more capable of grace by
sin. But after sin it is capable of the grace of the hypostatic union.
Therefore, if man had not sinned, human nature would have been capable of this
greatest grace, nor would God have withheld from it any good of which it was
capable.
Fourth difficulty. God's predestination is eternal. But Christ, as man, was
predestined to be truly the Son of God. Therefore, in virtue of this
predestination, even before sin, the Incarnation was a necessity.
Fifth difficulty. The mystery of the Incarnation was revealed to the first
man in his state of innocence without any reference to his future sin for which
reparation must be made.
For these reasons, Alexander of Hales, St. Albert, and later on Scotus deemed
it more probable that the Word would have become incarnate even if man had not
sinned.
This question assumes no less importance if it be proposed as follows: What
is the fundamental trait of Christ? Is it to be the Savior and victim, or
preferably to be the teacher, King of kings, Lord of all? Is it only of
secondary importance that He is the Savior and victim?
St. Thomas' conclusion in the body of this article is the following. "It
is more fitting to say that the work of the Incarnation was ordained by God as a
remedy for sin, so that, had sin not existed, the Incarnation would not have
been. And yet the power of God is not limited to this; even had sin not existed,
God could have become incarnate."
St. Thomas in one of his earlier works[284] gives this opinion as probable,
in fact, as more probable. Similarly, in another of his commentaries, he says:
"We do not know what God would have ordained (by another decree) if He had
not foreknown the sin of man. Nevertheless, authoritative writers seem to state
expressly that God would not have become incarnate if man had not sinned. I
incline more to this view."[285]
Proof. St. Thomas proves his conclusion by one argument, for, as we shall
immediately see, there is no distinction between the argument "sed
contra" and the argument in the body of this article, but he combines them
into one argument, which may be presented by the following syllogism.
What depends solely on the will of God, and beyond all to which the creature
is entitled, can be made known to us only inasmuch as it is contained in Sacred
Scripture.
But everywhere in Sacred Scripture the sin of the first man is assigned as
the reason for the Incarnation.
Therefore it is more fitting to say, since it seems to be more in accordance
with the meaning of Sacred Scripture, that the sin of the first man is the
reason of the Incarnation. This conclusion is both more and less than a
theological conclusion. It is more because it appears to be the meaning of
Sacred Scripture; it is less because it is not absolutely certain.
The major is evident, because what depends on the most free will of God is
known only to Himself, nor is there any other way by which supernatural
gifts[286] can be made known except through revelation, which is contained in
Sacred Scripture and also in tradition. Hence the Scripture says: "For who
among men is he that can know the counsel of God? Or who can think what the will
of God is."[287]
Proof of minor. Christ Himself testifies, saying: "They that are whole,
need not the physician, but they that are sick. I came not to call the just, but
sinners to penance."[288] And again: "For the Son of man is come to
seek and to save that which was lost."[289] St. Paul says: "Christ
Jesus came into the world to save sinners."[290] Elsewhere he writes:
"God sent His Son made of a woman, made under the law, that He might redeem
those who were under the law."[291] The beloved Apostle testifies:
"God so loved the world, as to send His only-begotten Son, that whosoever
believeth in Him may not perish, but may have life everlasting."[292] St.
John the Baptist on seeing Jesus, says: "Behold the Lamb of God... who
taketh away the sin of the world."[293] Likewise the Old Testament assigns
the healing of the contrite of heart and the abolition of iniquity from the
land, as the only reasons for the promise and expectation of the[294] Moreover,
the name Jesus signifies Savior.[295]
But Sacred Scripture does not say explicitly that this reason for the
Incarnation is the only possible one, and it speaks with reference to us men and
our salvation. Hence the argument from this point of view is not apodictic.
But this argument drawn from Sacred Scripture is fully confirmed by
tradition. The Council of Nicaea, in the symbol which, too, the Church sings,
says: "Who for us men, and for our salvation, came down from heaven. And
was made flesh by the Holy Ghost, and was made man."[296] Likewise, in the
Council of Sens and by Innocent II, Abelard's proposition was condemned, which
said: "Christ did not assume our human nature in order to deliver us from
the devil's yoke."[297]
The Fathers insist upon the above-quoted passages when speaking about the
motive of the Incarnation.
St. Irenaeus says: "If no flesh had to be saved, the Word of God would
not at all have become flesh."[298]
St. Cyril of Alexandria remarks: "If we had not sinned, the Son of God
would not have become like unto us."[299]
Other Fathers may be quoted. Thus, St. Athanasius writes: "The Word by
no means would have become man unless the necessity of mankind had been the
cause."[300]
St. Gregory Nazianzen declares: "But what was the reason for God to
assume our human nature for our sake? Assuredly that He might prepare the way to
heaven for us; for what other reason can there be?"[301]
St. Chrysostom, the head of the Greek Church, likewise says: "He assumed
this human nature of ours solely on account of His mercy, that He might have
mercy on us; there is no other reason whatever than this alone for dispensing us
from our obligation."[302] This means to say that the proximate motive of
the efficacious decree of the Incarnation was formally the motive of mercy.
Finally also St. Augustine, the head of the Latin Church, is quoted in the
counterargument of this article, who says: "If man had not sinned, the Son
of man would not have come." And elsewhere he says: "Since Adam was
made, namely, a righteous man, there was no need of a mediator. But when sins
had separated the human race far from God, it was necessary for us to be
reconciled to God through a mediator."[303] The testimony of the gloss,
quoted in the counterargument, must be added to the above quotations, namely:
"Take away diseases, take away wounds, and there is no need of
medicine."[304]
The Scotists say that these texts from Sacred Scripture and the Fathers prove
only that, if Adam had not sinned, Christ would not have come in passible flesh,
or as the physician and Savior.
The Thomists reply that in such a case the statements of the Fathers,
asserting absolutely, simply, and without restrictions, that Christ would not
have come if Adam had not sinned, would be false; or there would certainly be
much equivocation concealed in their words. Thus the following affirmation would
be false. Christ is not in the Eucharist meaning: He is not in the Eucharist in
passible flesh.
But St. Augustine says, as quoted above: "If man had not sinned, the Son
of man would not have come," whereas he ought to have said: He would have
come indeed but not in passible flesh, as the Redeemer.
The Scotists also appeal to the words of St. Paul, who says of Christ:
"Who is the image of the invisible God, the first-born of every creature,
for in Him were all things created in heaven and on earth.... Al] things were
created by Him and in Him. And He is before all, and by Him all things
consist."[305]
Concerning this text the Thomists remark that, even if these words refer not
only to the Word before the Incarnation, but also to Christ, yet they do not
express the proximate motive of the Incarnation, but that Christ is above every
creature, by reason of His personality.
Hence many authors say that the opinion of St. Thomas and of St. Bonaventure
has its foundation more in the testimony of the Scripture and the Fathers.[306]
Therefore, because of this fundamental argument, St. Thomas rightly says in
his conclusion: "Hence, since everywhere in the Sacred Scripture the sin of
the first man is assigned as the reason of the Incarnation, it is more in
accordance with this to say that the work of the Incarnation was ordained by God
as a remedy for sin; so that, had sin not existed, the Incarnation would not
have been,"[307] at least in virtue of the present decree; but it could
have been regardless of sin in virtue of another decree. This means that the
proximate motive of the Incarnation was formally the motive of mercy, namely, to
alleviate the misery of the human race.
Confirmation. The Thomists present a second argument which serves as a
complete corroboration of the preceding.
Since God's efficacious decrees are not modified by Him, but from eternity
include also all the circumstances of the thing to be produced, the present
efficacious decree of the Incarnation from eternity includes the passibility of
the flesh. But, as the Scotists concede, the incarnation in passible flesh,
supposes the fall. Therefore, in virtue of the present decree, the Word
incarnate would not have existed if man had not sinned.
Explanation of the major. God's efficacious decree includes all the
circumstances of the things to be produced, because it is an act of most perfect
prudence, which attends to all the circumstances of the object, inasmuch as it
is concerned with all the particulars that can and must be done right at the
moment. The difference between God and us consists in this, that we intend many
things even as much as these efficaciously be in our power, although we do not
attend to all the detailed circumstances, because these do not come under our
observation simultaneously but successively, nor can we foresee with certainty
the absolutely fortuitous circumstances even of the morrow. On the contrary, God
knows all future things from eternity, and nothing happens without either a
positive or permissive decree of His will, positive as regards that which is
real and good, permissive as regards evil. Hence God's positive efficacious
decree, since it is most prudent, includes all the circumstances of the thing to
be produced. Hence God, different from us, does not modify His efficacious
decrees, and consequently the efficacious decree of the Incarnation in passible
flesh, so that de facto the Incarnation takes place, is the only one issued by
God, and this decree, as the Scotists concede, supposes the fall of the human
race. Therefore, in virtue of the present efficacious decree, if man had not
sinned, the Word would not have become incarnate.
Therefore the Scotists ought to say that the decree of the Incarnation
considered in itself and not in passible flesh is a conditional and
inefficacious decree, like God's antecedent will of saving the human race,
because it is directed to something considered in itself, abstracting, as it
were, from particular circumstances of time and place. But it must be added in
virtue of the present inefficacious decree, nothing comes into being, for no
being or anything good is produced, because these can be produced only according
to conditions right at the moment, and at the moment nothing is realized,[308]
for the conditional and inefficacious decree does not refer to the existence of
things. Hence, in virtue of this particular, inefficacious decree, the Word de
facto would not, right in the present circumstances, have become incarnate
either in passible or in impassible flesh.
Instance. But perhaps this argument proves only that the reparation of sin
was an indispensable condition for the coming of Christ. It does not follow as
an immediate consequence that this indispensable condition was the proximate
motive of the Incarnation, because not every indispensable condition is the
motive of one's action.
Reply. We say that the Scripture assigns this condition as the motive, and no
other proximate motive is assigned to this condition, except the common and
ultimate motive in all God's works, which is the manifestation of His goodness
or His glory.
This argument is most forceful. In fact, it appears to be apodictic, inasmuch
as it is equivalent to saying that God, unlike us, does not afterward make a
change in what He has efficaciously decreed to bring into being. These decrees
are, from the moment of their utterance, most perfect and include future
circumstances even to the least detail. Thus, in like manner it was decreed by
God that Peter was to attain eternal glory only by way of penance after his
threefold denial, which was permitted by God. This argument holds good against
the opinion of Suarez.[309]
Objection. The election of Peter to heaven is an efficacious decree. But this
decree does not include in its object all the circumstances, for instance,
whether Peter will reach heaven by means of martyrdom, for this pertains to a
subsequent decree. Therefore not every efficacious decree includes all the
circumstances.
Reply. I distinguish the major. The election of Peter to heaven is an
efficacious decree of the end, this I concede; of the means, this I deny.
I contradistinguish the minor. That the decree does not include all the
circumstances of the means, this I concede; of the end, this I deny. Although
the decree concerning the end virtually contains the decree concerning the
means.
Thus Peter's election to heaven includes a certain degree of glory for this
individual person, together with all the associated circumstances. Similarly,
therefore, the decree of the Incarnation ought to terminate in the individual
Christ, right now to be born of the Virgin Mary, in passible flesh, just as it
actually happened.
The Scotists insist saying: I can decree efficaciously that someone must be
paid a debt of one hundred dollars, not considering whether this debt is to be
paid in gold or silver.
Reply.
1. We mortals can certainly do so, for our decrees are from the beginning
imperfect, often vaguely expressed, especially if they concern something to be
fulfilled in the future.
2. Moreover, the aforesaid decree concerns the end, namely, the price to be
paid, not the means by which it is to be paid.
3. This decree does not concern the production of the thing, but the use of a
thing already produced, namely, of a sum of gold or silver. On the contrary, the
efficacious decree of the Incarnation concerns a thing to be produced right now,
hence in passible flesh, as it actually happened. Therefore this argument rests
on very solid grounds, that is, after the Incarnation has become an accomplished
fact.
Confirmation of proof. St. Thomas confirms his proof by the solution of the
objections which he placed at the beginning of this, his third article.
The first objection was proposed by St. Augustine,[310] who says: "Many
other things are to be considered in the Incarnation of Christ besides
absolution from sin."
Reply to first objection. "All the other causes which are assigned in
the preceding article have to do with a remedy for sin," since, by the
Incarnation man is withdrawn from evil and given the greatest of incentives to
practice the virtues of faith, hope, and charity.
We must also concede that God, in the decree of the Incarnation, besides the
redemption of the human race, had in mind as the ultimate and common end of all
His works, the manifestation of His goodness or of His glory; but now it is a
question of the proximate motive of the Incarnation, namely, whether it is
connected with sin.
The second objection was: It belongs to God's omnipotence to manifest Himself
by some infinite effect.
Reply to second objection. "The infinity of divine power is shown in the
mode of production of things from nothing. Again, it suffices for the perfection
of the universe that the creature be ordained in a natural manner to God as to
an end (that is, in the purely natural state). But that a creature should be
united to God in person exceeds the limits of the perfection of nature."
Therefore, this constitutes the object of a most free decree, the motive of
which is made manifest only by revelation.
The third objection was: Human nature has not been made more capable of the
grace of the hypostatic union by sin. Therefore, if man had not sinned, God
would have willed the Incarnation.
Reply to third objection. St. Thomas concedes the antecedent. He
distinguishes the consequent, and concedes that, if man had not sinned, human
nature was capable obedientially of the Incarnation; that it would de facto have
been raised to the dignity of the hypostatic union in virtue of the present
decree, this he denies.
The whole of this beautiful reply to the third objection must be read,
because it is of great importance.
There are two things to be noted in this reply.
1) The obediential power concerns a supernatural agent, namely, God whom it
obeys; but God, who is absolutely free, does not always complete this
obediential power, though He sometimes does so, and gratuitously.
2) "But there is no reason," says St. Thomas, "why human
nature should not have been raised to something greater (de facto) after sin.
God allows evils to happen in order to bring a greater good therefrom. Hence it
is written (Rom. 5:20): 'Where sin abounded grace did more abound.’ Hence too,
in the blessing of the paschal candle, we say: 'O happy fault, that merited such
and so great a Redeemer. "
Thus it is confirmed that the motive of the Incarnation was formally the
motive of mercy, and, moreover, it is evident that God permitted original sin
for a greater good, which is the redemptive Incarnation. Thus causes are to each
other causes, though in a different order. In the order of material cause to be
perfected, the merciful uplifting of the fallen human race precedes the
redemptive Incarnation; but this latter precedes the fall in the order of final
cause or of greater good for which reason sin of the first man is permitted.
Thus the body of this particular embryo in the order of material cause to be
perfected precedes the creation and infusion of this particular soul, and yet
this latter precedes the embryo in the order of final cause, for this soul would
not be created unless the embryo were disposed to receive it.
Several Thomists insist on this point, as we shall see, such as Godoi, Gonet,
Salmanticenses, whose interpretation is already contained in this reply to the
third objection, which was not sufficiently considered by John of St. Thomas and
Billuart.
The fourth objection was: Christ as man was eternally predestined to be the
natural Son of God.[311] But predestination is always fulfilled. Therefore even
before sin, it was necessary for the Son of God to become incarnate.
St. Thomas replies: "Predestination presupposes the foreknowledge of
future things; and hence, as God predestines the salvation of anyone (for
example, of Augustine, to be brought about by the prayers of others, for
example, of St. Monica), so also He predestined the work of the Incarnation to
be the remedy of human sin."
This reply of St. Thomas to the fourth objection requires a brief
explanation. "Predestination," says St. Thomas, "presupposes the
foreknowledge of future things," not indeed of all future things. Certainly
St. Thomas does not mean that it presupposes the foreknowledge of merits, for
then he would contradict himself;[312] but predestination presupposes the
foreknowledge of certain future things. Thus, when God predestines Peter, He
first wills him eternal life in the order of final cause, but previously in the
order of material cause He wills him individuation by means of matter by which
he is constituted as Peter. Similarly, when it is a question of the whole human
race and of Christ's predestination as the Redeemer of the human race, this
predestination presupposes the foreseeing of Adam's sin in the order of material
cause only. Likewise a foreseen persecution is the occasion for someone being
predestined to the grace of martyrdom. The Thomists consider the person of the
predestined, native talents, and other natural gifts, temperament, to be effects
postulated by predestination, which follow it in the order of final cause. And
as Augustine would not have attained eternal life if St. Monica had not prayed
for him, so if man had not sinned, the Word would not have become incarnate.
This reply must be correctly understood, so that it be not interpreted as
contrary to a previous conclusion,[313]. which stated that the foreknowledge of
merits is not the cause of predestination, because the merits of the elect are,
on the contrary, the effects of their predestination.
Cajetan explains this point well. He remarks that, when St. Thomas says in
his reply to the fourth objection that "predestination presupposes the
foreknowledge of future things," he does not mean "of all future
things," for Peter's predestination does not presuppose the foreknowledge
of Peter's future eternal happiness, but, on the contrary, the foreknowledge of
Peter's future eternal happiness presupposes Peter's predestination to eternal
happiness, inasmuch as God foresees future things in the decrees of His will.
But St. Thomas means in this case that "predestination presupposes the
foreknowledge of some future things which are presupposed by
predestination."[314]
Thus St. Thomas considers that Christ's predestination to natural divine
sonship presupposes the foreknowledge of sin, since it was to repair this
offense that Christ was predestined; for, as Cajetan observes, the ordering of
medicine presupposes knowledge of the disease.[315]
But the difficulty is not solved, for Scotus will argue that this dependence
of the Incarnation on sin holds good in the order of execution but not in the
order of intention of Christ's predestination.[316] For the orderly way of
willing for anyone is to will the end and those things nearer to the end, than
other inferior things. Thus God wills for anyone, such as Adam, before He saw
either His merits or a fortiori His demerits. Therefore a fortiori God wills
divine natural sonship to Christ before having foreseen Adam's demerit.
In answer to this objection it can be said, in accordance with the reply to
the third objection, what St. Thomas means is that, even in the order of
intention, Christ's predestination is dependent on the foreseeing of Adam's sin,
not indeed that it is dependent on this latter as being the final cause, but as
being the material cause that is to be perfected.[317]
Thus, when God predestines Peter, He first wills him eternal happiness in the
order of final cause, and He first wills him individuation from matter already
qualified in the embryo, in the order of material cause; and "to them that
love God all things work together unto good."[318] He also wills them their
physical temperament.
Likewise, when it is a question of the whole human race, and of Christ's
predestination as the Redeemer of the human race, this predestination
presupposes the foreseeing of Adam's sin in the order of material cause only.
This distinction is made by Cajetan on this point,[319] and, although not
everything that he says here on the ordering of the divine decrees concerning
the three orders of nature, grace, and the hypostatic union are true perhaps,
nevertheless this distinction must be and is upheld by subsequent Thomists.[320]
For Cajetan replies by distinguishing the antecedent as follows: in the order
of final cause, one who wills methodically, wills the end before other things,
this I concede; that one does so in the order of disposing cause, which reduces
itself to material cause, this I deny
Thus we will first and preferably health to purification in the order of
final cause; contrary to this, however, in the order of material or disposing
cause we will purification as a means to health.
This distinction has its foundation in the principle that causes mutually
interact, and the application of this principle is afterward developed by the
Salmanticenses and Gonet, whose interpretation differs somewhat from Cajetan's,
as will be stated farther on.
Cajetan concludes: "It is evident that the Incarnation can be willed by
God, without such an occasion (i. e., Adam's sin), but it is not evident that it
is de facto willed by God independent of such occasion.... We must turn to the
Scripture if we wish to know that de facto God ordained that the Incarnation
will come to pass, whether Adam did or did not sin. Rut because from the
Scripture we have knowledge only of a redemptive Incarnation, we say, although
God could have willed the Incarnation even without a future redemption, de facto
He willed it only in the redemption; because by revelation, He did not reveal
things otherwise to us, and it is only by revelation that we can know His
will.... The conclusion is that God willed the greatest good only in conjunction
with such less good."[321] Thus, although God could have willed
efficaciously the salvation of the whole human race (which to us appears
better), it is certain that He willed efficaciously that many be saved, but not
all.[322]
Likewise, as Cajetan says: "It is not derogatory to God's wisdom to have
disposed things so that He will effect so sublime a good as that (of the
Incarnation), sin being only the occasion that urged Him to have mercy....
Therefore we must not on this account rejoice at another's fall (that is,
Adam's), but at the mercy of God, who causes the foreseen fall of one to redound
to another's good."[323] Hence we conclude that the motive of the
Incarnation was formally the motive of mercy, since our salvation was the
motive, as stated in the Nicene Creed.
Fifth objection. St. Thomas states that the mystery of the Incarnation was
revealed to man in a state of innocence without any reference to future sin.
Therefore it has no connection with this sin.
Reply to fifth objection. St. Thomas says: "Nothing prevents an effect
from being revealed to one to whom the cause is not revealed."
What Is Precisely The View Of Scotus?[324]
The question whether Christ was predestined to be the Son of God, affords
Scotus the occasion to discuss the problem of the motive of the Incarnation.
After replying to the first question in the affirmative, he goes on to show that
Christ was predestined as man to the grace of the hypostatic union and to glory
independently of the foreseeing of Adam's sin. Scotus proves his point by seven
arguments that have been splendidly reproduced by Cajetan.[325] We shall give
here the principal arguments with Cajetan's replies.
First argument. The predestination of any person whatever to glory precedes
naturally, on the part of the object, the foreknowledge of sin or of the
damnation of any man whatever. Therefore with far greater reason this is true
concerning the predestination of Christ's soul to supreme glory.
Cajetan replies.[326] He denies the antecedent, because he holds that the
foreseeing of sin pertains to the order of general providence, presupposed by
the ordering of predestination. But this reply gives rise to many difficulties,
since the permission of sin in the life of the predestined, for example, and
therefore in the life of Adam himself, is the effect not only of general
providence, but also of the predestination of these elect, which itself
presupposes the predestination of Christ.[327] Hence theologians in general, and
even subsequent Thomists, do not uphold Cajetan in this reply.
But very many Thomists reply as follows. They concede that Christ's
predestination precedes by nature the foreseeing of Adam's sin in the order of
final cause; they deny that it precedes in the order of material or disposing
cause.
Thus they concede that Peter's predestination to glory precedes by nature the
foreseeing of his individuation, in the order of final cause; they deny this
precedence in the order of material cause. Likewise, one is predestined to the
grace of martyrdom, on the occasion of a foreseen persecution.
Second argument. The orderly way of willing is for one to will first the end,
and then those things more immediate to the end. Thus God first wills to give
heavenly glory to one before grace, and He first wills this to Christ, and then
to the predestined as subordinated to Christ. Moreover, God first wills anyone
heavenly glory and grace which He may foresee are in opposition because of sin
and its consequences. Therefore God first wills heavenly glory to Christ
previous to foreseeing Adam's fall.
Cajetan replies,[328] and this reply is upheld by subsequent Thomists. He
distinguishes the major: that the orderly way of willing is for one first to
will the end in the order of final cause, this he concedes; in the order of
material and disposing cause, this he denies.
By way of example: someone might wish to build the Collegio Angelico in Rome,
but has not yet found a suitable place and, having found such a place, his wish
of having this college built is realized, or the opportunity offers itself,
because he has received the necessary money. Similarly God wills first the soul
in the order of final cause, and first the body in the order of material cause,
and this particular soul would not be created right at this moment, if this
embryonic body were not disposed to receive it. Likewise the Word would not have
become incarnate, in virtue of the present decree, unless man had sinned or the
human race had to be redeemed.
But you insist. Causes do not mutually interact in the same order. However,
this would be the case here in the same order of final cause, if sin is
permitted because of this greater good of the Incarnation, and if the
Incarnation is willed for our redemption.
Reply. The causes are not in the same order, for sin is permitted because of
this greater good of the Incarnation considered as the end for which it is
decreed; whereas, on the contrary, the human race to be redeemed stands in
relation to the Incarnation in the order of material cause to be perfected, or
is the subject to whom the redemptive Incarnation is beneficial. Hence the human
race is not called the end for whose sake the Incarnation is decreed, but the
end to whom it is beneficial. Therefore the causes are not mutually interactive
in the same order. And this very redemption of ours as willed by God,
presupposes as a prior requisite in the order of material cause the human race
to be redeemed.
So also let us take as example one who saves the life of a boy who, because
of his imprudence, falls into the river. The rescuer first wills to save the
boy's life in the order of final cause, but he would not save the boy's life
unless the boy had fallen into the river, and thus had afforded the other the
opportunity to come to his rescue. In like manner, the more solemn dogmatic
definitions of the Church are always given on the occasion of some error that
must be rejected, because it is endangering the freedom of souls.
Third argument. Redemption or the heavenly glory of a soul to be redeemed is
not so great a good as the glory of Christ's soul. Therefore the Redemption does
not seem to be the sole reason why God predestined Christ's soul to so great
glory.
Cajetan replies:[329] God could have willed indeed this great good (of
Christ's glory) without its being connected with a less good; but from Sacred
Scripture it is evident that He willed this greatest good only as connected with
such less good. It is not therefore a question of a possibility, but of a fact.
God could have willed efficaciously to save the whole human race, for instance,
but from Sacred Scripture it is evident that not all are saved,[330] although,
by God's help, the fulfillment of His commands is always possible. Herein lies a
mystery that must be believed according to the testimony of Sacred Scripture and
not to be determined in human fashion by a priori reasoning.
Fourth argument. It is not very likely that a less good is the only reason
for the existence of so supreme a good.
Reply. The Thomists say that the Incarnation is not an incidental good in the
strict sense, but it is only improperly so called. For that which the agent does
not intend and which happens by chance, is called strictly incidental; such is
the case when one digs a grave, and finds a treasure, or when one rescues a boy
accidentally who happens to fall into the river. That is improperly said to be
occasioned which depends on some incident, although it be intended by the agent,
as the rescuing of a boy who fell into the river. Thus the Incarnation is an
incidental good, and it is fitting that evil be the occasion of eliciting from
God so great a good, namely, a good that results from His liberality and mercy,
because misery is the reason for commiserating.
Scotus overlooks the fact that many of the finer things in life are
improperly incidental, especially many heroic acts, such as saving another's
life with danger to one's own, as in the case of shipwreck or of fire. Such are
heroic acts performed in defense of one's country, on the occasion of an unjust
aggressor; hence the glory acquired by many soldiers is thus incidental. Also
incidental are heroic acts in defense of one's faith, such as martyrdom on the
occasion of a persecution. The most beautiful dogmatic definitions uttered by
the Church on the occasion of the refutation of an error that is threatening to
enslave souls, belong to this class. So it was on the occasion of the rise of
Pelagianism and Semi-Pelagianism, that St. Augustine wrote his books On Grace.
But the difference between God and man is that man could not infallibly
foresee the occasion that prompted these heroic acts, and so he does them
unforeseen. Other arguments of Scotus presented in different aspects repeat the
same objection.
The Scotists insist. They say, with Father Chrysostom,[331] that the material
cause is not the end (of the Incarnation), nor is the material element in the
Incarnation its motive. Therefore the difficulty remains.
Reply. The material element that enters into the redemptive Incarnation is
the reason for the Incarnation, since "the alleviation of misery is the
reason for commiseration."[332] Thus in this third article, St. Thomas is
able to say: "Redemption is the reason for the Incarnation,"[333]
although the Incarnation is not subordinated to the redemption.
All these objections can be reduced to the following syllogistic argument:
God cannot will that the higher order should be subjected to the lower, for this
would be the inversion of order, or perversion.
But our redemption is inferior to the Incarnation.
Therefore God cannot will the Incarnation to be for our redemption.
Reply. I distinguish the major. That God cannot will the higher order to be
subjected to the lower, as being the perfective and ultimate end, this I
concede; that God cannot will the higher for the lower, as being the end that
must be perfected or repaired from a motive of mercy, this I deny. For the
alleviating of misery, is the reason for commiseration. I concede the minor.
I distinguish the conclusion. That God cannot will the higher order to be
subjected to the lower on account of this latter being the perfective and
especially the ultimate end, this I concede; as being the end that must be
perfected or repaired from a motive of mercy, this I deny.
Thus the Thomists say that the redemption of the human race is not the end
for the sake of which the Incarnation is decreed, but it is the material element
that enters into the motive of the redemptive Incarnation, or the end for which
the Incarnation is beneficial. Thus a doctor visits a sick person, or a priest
says Mass for the restoration of somebody's health, for the common good and the
glory of God.
Therefore the whole teaching of St. Thomas, of St. Bonaventure, and others is
summed up in these words: the motive of the Incarnation was formally the motive
of mercy. As the Psalmist says: "Have mercy on me, O Lord, for I am
weak."[334] "Have mercy on me, for I am poor."[335] "Have
mercy on me, O Lord, for I am afflicted."[336]
Cajetan replies most appropriately: "It is not unbefitting God's wisdom
that He was disposed to perform so great a good, only because sin was the
occasion that urged Him to be merciful."[337] "It is because the
alleviation of misery is the reason for commiseration,"[338] and divine
mercy, alleviating the misery of the human race, is the greatest manifestation
of divine goodness and omnipotence. If God's omnipotence is already made
manifest in the creation of a grain of sand from nothing, a fortiori it is shown
when He brings good out of evil, and so great a good as eternal life of those
justified. St. Thomas says: "In itself mercy is the greatest of virtues
(and so it is in God, but not in us, because we have someone above us, who must
be honored by the practice of virtues); for it belongs to mercy to be bountiful
to others, and, what is more, to succor others in their wants. And this pertains
especially to the one who is above others; hence mercy is accounted as being
proper to God, and therein His omnipotence is declared to be chiefly
manifested."[339] St. Augustine likewise says: "The justification of
the sinner is greater than the creation of heaven and earth; for heaven and
earth shall pass away, but the justification of the ungodly shall
endure."[340] But since misery is the reason for having mercy, the
alleviation of misery is more the matter about which mercy is concerned; it is
the motive of mercy, not indeed as constituting the perfective end, but as being
the end in the order of redemption.
In this there is no inversion of orders. There would indeed be a perversion
of orders if the higher were ordained for the lower, as if this latter were the
ultimate and perfective end; but not, if by way of mercy, the higher is ordered
to the lower end for its perfection or reparation.
Thus it is that the Son of God through His incarnation certainly stoops down
to us with sublime mercy, so that the saints are moved to tears at the thought
of it. But by thus lowering Himself, He in no way subordinates Himself to us; on
the contrary, in alleviating our misery, He restores the original subordination,
by making us again subordinate to Himself and God the Father. Thus God, by
mercifully lowering Himself, has most splendidly made manifest His goodness and
omnipotence, since "to have mercy belongs especially to one who is above
others."[341]
In God, inasmuch as He has nobody above Him to whom He would owe allegiance,
the greatest of all virtues is mercy, and misery is the reason for being
merciful.[342] Thus the beginning of a certain collect reads: "O God, who,
more than in all things else, showest forth Thine almighty power by sparing and
by having mercy."[343] Therefore Scotus did not destroy the demonstrative
middle term of this article.[344]
The preceding doctrine is certainly what St. Thomas taught. On this point, he
wrote: "God therefore did not assume human nature because He loved man,
absolutely speaking, more than angels; but because the needs of man were
greater; just as the master of a house may give to a sick servant some costly
delicacy that he does not give to his own son in sound health."[345] He
also says: "Nor did anything of Christ's excellence diminish when God
delivered Him up to death for the salvation of the human race; rather did He
become thereby a glorious conqueror"[346] Of sin, the devil, and death.
The thesis of St. Thomas, as proposed by him, is most convincing inasmuch as
he declares mercy to be the motive of the Incarnation; wherefore Christ was the
first of the predestined, but He was predestined as Savior and victim, as the
victor of sin, the devil, and death. This title of Savior belongs primarily to
Christ, as expressed in the name Jesus, which signifies Savior. This title
belongs more fundamentally to Him than do such titles as Doctor, or King of
kings, Lord of lords.
Christian faith itself seems to teach this doctrine, although the Scripture
does not say that mercy was the indispensable motive of the Incarnation. This
doctrine is also most beneficial in the spiritual order. urging us to imitate
Christ and show zeal for souls.
Cajetan remarks[347] that, as in the act of hope I desire God for myself,
because God is my final end (since God is the ultimate end of this act of hope),
so Christ is given to us (for our sake or as our end), for the glorification of
God (who is the ultimate end for which God performs all His works). Thus the
Incarnation is not subordinated to our redemption,[348] but is its eminent
cause. Thus contemplation is not subordinated to apostolic action, which must
result from the fullness of contemplation, this being its higher source, as St.
Thomas points out.[349] Therefore, no matter what the Scotists may say, the
words of St. Paul still apply, who says: "For all are yours. And you are
Christ's. And Christ is God's"[350] In this Thomistic thesis, Christ is not
subordinated to us, but we are subordinated to Him.
Agreement and disagreement between Thomists. They all agree upon the
principal conclusion as explicitly formulated by St. Thomas, which is: If Adam
had not sinned, the Word would not have become incarnate.
But they are not altogether in agreement concerning a secondary issue.
Several Thomists, adopting the views of Cajetan, such as John of St. Thomas
and Billuart, refuse to answer the question, why God permitted Adam's sin and
original sin. Moreover, they multiply divine conditional decrees. According to
their views: (1) God willed the natural order; (2) the elevation of the human
race to the supernatural order; (3) He permitted the sin of the first man; (4)
He decreed the redemptive Incarnation in passible flesh.
Other Thomists, such as the Salmanticenses, Godoy, Gonet, and very many of
more recent times, insisting on what St. Thomas remarks in this article, and
elsewhere, say:[351] Certainly God permits evil only because of a greater good.
This doctrine is certain and de fide, otherwise God's permission of sin would
not be a holy act. It cannot indeed be said a priori that God permitted original
sin because of some greater good, but, after the fact of the Incarnation, it
appears that God permitted original sin because of the redemptive Incarnation,
so that the redemption of the fallen human race is prior in the order of
material cause to be perfected, and the redemptive Incarnation is prior in the
order of final cause. This distinction is made by Cajetan in his commentary on
this article, but much of its force is lost inasmuch as he multiplies
exceedingly the divine decrees, so different from what he wrote earlier in his
commentary.[352]
Moreover, these Thomists say that divine conditional decrees must not be
multiplied, for this multiplication results from the weakness of our intellect,
and we must do our best to overcome this defect. Hence God, previous to any
decree, saw by His knowledge of simple intelligence all possible worlds with all
their contents, just as the architect has in mind various possible houses and
all their component parts. Thus God had in mind a sinless world not in need of
redemption, but brought to perfection by the example of the Word incarnate; also
another possible world, in which man sinned, and which was perfected by the
redemptive Incarnation. God chose de facto, by a single decree, this latter, in
which, therefore, the redemptive Incarnation is prior in the order of final
causality (as the soul is prior to the body), and the reparation of the fallen
human race is prior in the order of material causality to be perfected, as the
body is prior to the soul.[353]
This second interpretation is entirely in conformity with the reply given by
St. Thomas to the third objection of this article, and also with a previous
statement in his Summa, in which he says: "God loves Christ not only more
than He loves the whole human race, but more than He loves the entire created
universe, because He willed for Him the greater good in giving Him a name that
is above all names, so far as He was true God. Nor did anything of His
excellence diminish when God delivered Him up to death for the salvation of the
human race; rather did He become thereby a glorious conqueror,"[354]
namely, of sin, the devil, and death.
This reply of these Thomists is also precisely what St. Thomas says in his
reply to the third objection of this article, in which he quotes the words of
St. Paul: "Where sin abounded, grace did more abound,"[355] and of the
liturgy: "O happy fault, that merited such and so great a
Redeemer!"[356]
And St. Augustine says in his commentary on the forty-seventh psalm:
"Therefore Adam fell for our resurrection,"[357] which means that God
permitted Adam's sin for this greater good of the redemptive Incarnation.
Moreover, the divine decrees must not be multiplied without necessity; for
this frequency of recourse to divine decrees has its foundation in the
imperfection of our manner of understanding the divine decrees. In fact, it is
evident that various events of the natural order, such as the death of a good
person from some disease, which at first sight seems to depend solely on natural
causes and the general provisions of Providence, are to be attributed to the
supernatural operation of predestination.[358] Therefore it is apparent that
God, by a single decree, willed this present world with its three orders of
nature, grace, and the hypostatic union.
The Liberty Of The Decree Concerning The Incarnation: A Comparison Between
The Doctrine Of St. Thomas And That Of Scotus
On first consideration, it is surprising that St. Thomas, who is an
intellectualist, should say: Since the Incarnation is a most free and absolutely
gratuitous gift of God, its motive can be known only by revelation; whereas
Scotus, who is a voluntarist inclined to liberalism, wishes to establish this
motive of the Incarnation by arguments or quasi a priori reasonings, as the
extreme intellectualists do, such as Leibnitz and Malebranche, who say that the
Incarnation is morally necessary so that the world may be the best of all
possible worlds.
The reason for this difference of opinion between St. Thomas and Scotus seems
to consist in this, that St. Thomas, because of his moderate intellectualism,
distinguished exactly between the order of nature and the order of grace, by
establishing the proper object of the created intellect, whether human or
angelic.[359] Hence St. Thomas fully acknowledges God's perfect liberty in
elevating the human nature (or the angelic) to the order of grace, and a
fortiori to the hypostatic union. Thus his moderate intellectualism most
correctly acknowledges the rights of divine liberty.
On the contrary, Scotus, in virtue of his voluntarism does not succeed in
distinguishing so exactly between the orders of nature and of grace; he says
that there is in our nature an innate appetite and not merely one that is
elicited for the beatific vision, and he adds that, if God had so willed, the
beatific vision would be natural for us.
Hence he is inclined to regard the supernatural order as the complement of
the natural order, and the hypostatic order as the complement and quasi-normal
consummation of the supernatural order. Thus he does not acknowledge
sufficiently the rights of divine liberty as regards this twofold elevation; and
he speaks finally, almost like the absolute intellectualists of the Leibnitz
type, who think that the Incarnation is morally necessary for the world to be
the best of all possible worlds. Thus extremes meet.
Absolute intellectualism reduces to an ideal right the accomplished fact.
Absolute libertism reduces the right itself to an accomplished fact.
These two systems are in the inverse order, but practically they meet,
because both admit that the accomplished fact is the same as the ideal right,
and success is identical with morality; yet the followers of the former system
insist on the right, whereas the followers of the latter system insist on the
accomplished fact. But moderate intellectualism lies between these two extremes,
because it safeguards both the validity of the first principles of reason and
true liberty, which latter is denied by absolute intellectualism.
Thus in Thomism the Incarnation is seen to be the supreme fact of the entire
universe, but it is a contingent fact in which God's most free and gratuitous
love for us is made manifest by way of mercy. "For God so loved the world
as to give His only-begotten Son."[360]
Thus this thesis of St. Thomas, if we compare it with his other theses on
moderate intellectualism and liberty, has a deep significance, for it means
that, in the supernatural order, inasmuch as this order is gratuitous, divine
liberty reigns supreme and its predilection is most free, the motive of which
can be known only by revelation. But the discarding of this principle results in
the incomplete understanding of several fundamental utterances in the
supernatural order, suck as the following words of St. Paul: "But the
foolish things of the world hath God chosen that He may confound the wise;...
and things that are not, that He might bring to nought things that
are."[361]
But these questions are most profound, and their solution has caused great
intellects to take opposite views.
Spiritual corollaries. These corollaries are developed in another book,[362]
in which the doctrine of St. Thomas on the motive of the Incarnation is
explained not so much scholastically as spiritually. These corollaries are as
follows:
1) It follows from this doctrine that it is not something accidental that
Christ is the Savior, both priest and victim. This is the dominant trait of
Jesus, as the name indicates. Jesus is not especially King of kings and sublime
Doctor who happened to become the Savior of humanity and victim on account of
the fall of the human race. No, but in virtue of the present decree He came
principally and primarily as the Savior of men. His entire life was directed to
this final end, namely, the sacrifice on the cross.
2) Christ thus appears nobler, and the unity of His life is better made
manifest, since it is the unity of the Savior's life, who is merciful and also
victorious over sin, the devil, and death.[363]
3) Wherefore Christ calls the hour of the Passion "My hour" as if
it were pre-eminently this.
4) Therefore in the present economy of salvation, it is not something
accidental in the sanctification of souls, that they must carry their cross
daily in union with our Savior, as He Himself says.[364]
5) Hence for sanctity, even great sanctity, learning is not necessary, nor
the performance of many external works; it suffices for a person to be conformed
to the image of Christ crucified, as in the case of St. Benedict Joseph Labre of
the seventeenth century, who showed himself a living image of Christ in his
poverty and love of the cross.[365]
6) Finally it follows, as St. Thomas explains in his treatise on the effects
of baptism,[366] that sanctifying grace in the redeemed is strictly the grace of
Christ, for it is not only a participation of the divine nature as in Adam and
the angels before the Fall, but it makes us conformable to Christ the Redeemer,
and by it we are made living members of His mystical body. Wherefore this grace,
inasmuch as it is the grace of Christ, disposes us to live in Christ the
Redeemer by a love of the cross, for it disposes us to make reparation for our
own sins and the sins of others, inasmuch as the living members of Christ must
help one another in the attainment of salvation.
Therefore, it is only after a period of painful probation that any Christian
ideal and any Christian society produces true fruits of salvation, for our Lord
says: "Unless the grain of wheat falling into the ground die, itself
remaineth alone. But if it die, it bringeth forth much fruit."[367]
Thus Christians are made conformable to Christ, who said of Himself to the
disciples on the way to Emmaus: "Ought not Christ to have suffered these
things, and so to enter into His glory?"[368] Hence St. Paul says: "We
are heirs indeed of God and joint heirs with Christ; yet so, if we suffer with
Him that we may be also glorified with Him."[369]
These spiritual corollaries are deduced from this teaching.
A certain special opinion. It has been held by some in recent times[370] that
so far the question is always presented unfavorably since it always appears in a
hypothetical form, namely, "Whether, if man had not sinned, God would have
become incarnate." "For," as they say, "if man had not
sinned (or in this supposition), there would be another order absolutely
different from the present order, and what would have happened in such an order
God alone can know." The proper way of positing the question, according to
these theologians, must be by presenting it in the form of a positive and
universal proposition, that is, "What is the adequate universal reason for
the Incarnation in the present order?" Father Roschini[371] replies to this
question as follows: "The primary reason of the Incarnation is God's free
election from all eternity of the present order with all that is included in it;
inasmuch as only the present order exactly corresponds to the measure and mode
likewise freely prearranged by God, by which He willed to bestow His goodness ad
extra and hence procure extrinsic glory."
An answer to Father Roschini's view appeared in the Angelicum;[372] its gist
is as follows: The question posited by the Scholastics concerns the present
order, and a new way of presenting the question is outside the scope of the
present problem, and brings us only to the common truth that is admitted by all
schools of thought. It is most certain to all theologians that the Incarnation
depends on God's free choice of the present order, and what He has ordained for
the manifestation of His goodness. This is God's supreme reason, but, now the
question is, what is His proximate reason?
Evidently the hypothetical question put by the great Scholastics concerns the
present order; namely, in virtue of the present decree, if we make abstraction
of the sin of the first man, would the Word have become incarnate? This
abstraction is not a lie, nor does it change the order of the thing considered.
It is the same as asking: Would the soul of this particular man have been
created if his body in his mother's womb was not sufficiently developed to be
informed by it? Or we might ask: Will this temple remain intact if this
particular column is removed? The truth of a conditional proposition, as logic
teaches, depends solely on the connection between the condition and the
conditioned.
Hence in replying to the objection, we say: If man had not sinned, the
present order of things would be changed, I distinguish: if it meant there would
be a change in virtue of another decree, this I concede; in virtue of the
present decree, this I deny.
As stated in the above-mentioned reply to Father Roschini: "The
reasoning of the Scholastics is not, and cannot be, other than this, otherwise
how are we to explain the fact that those doctors are so eager in their futile
search, concerning which nothing for certain can ever be known?... Without
saying, then, what to attribute to those ponderous and so circumspect
theologians, with St. Thomas as their leader, a general view of the case would
justify us in considering them at least as scholars."
St. Thomas would have improperly stated the question, or would not have
corrected the question improperly stated, a question that is even useless, and
of course quite irrelevant.
But it is true to say, with the holy Doctor, that in speaking of another
order of things, "We do not know what (God) would have ordained, if He had
not had previous knowledge of sin."[373] St. Thomas says the same in the
present article, for he writes: "And yet the power of God is not limited to
this; even had sin not existed, God could have become incarnate, namely, in
another order of things."
Final Conclusion: The Motive Of The Incarnation
Therefore it must simply be said that God willed the Incarnation for the
manifestation of His goodness by way of mercy for the redemption of the human
race, or "for our salvation," as stated in the Creed.
Those who admit, as the Thomists do, one efficacious decree concerning the
redemptive Incarnation in passible flesh, by this very fact must say with St.
Thomas that, in virtue of the present decree, "if Adam had not sinned, the
Word would not have become incarnate," or, expressed affirmatively, it must
be said that, in the present decree, the redemptive Incarnation supposes the
fall of the human race to be redeemed, although this fall was permitted for a
greater good, which is the redemptive Incarnation. Thus the creation of the soul
presupposes that the embryonic body is sufficiently disposed, and this
sufficient predisposition was willed and produced by God for the soul. Causes
mutually interact though in a different order, without implying a vicious
circle. It would be a vicious circle if we were to say that the permission of
Adam's sin was on account of the Incarnation, and that the Incarnation took
place because of the permission of Adam's sin. The truth is that the Incarnation
took place, not on account of the permission of sin, but for its reparation.
It would likewise be a vicious circle to say that men are for the sake of
Christ, and in the same way Christ is for the sake of men. But it is true to say
that Christ is the destined end of men, and men are the end to whom the
redemptive Incarnation is beneficial.
Hence the truth of the assertion is established, that God willed the
Incarnation as a manifestation of His goodness by showing His mercy toward men
for their redemption, or "for our salvation," as stated in the
Creed.[374]
Fourth Article: Whether God Became Incarnate In Order To Take Away Actual
Sin, Rather Than To Take Away Original Sin?
The reply is in the affirmative.
Scriptural proof. We read in the Gospel: "Behold the Lamb of God who
taketh away the sin of the world,"[375] that is, as St. Bede says, the sin
that is common to the whole human race. St. John wrote "the sin of the
world."[376]
But the principal text is quoted in the body of the article, in which we
read: "For judgment indeed was by one[i. e., by Adam] unto condemnation...
as by the offense of one, unto all men to condemnation: so also by the justice
of one [i. e., of Christ], unto all men to justification of life."[377]
This purpose of the Incarnation of the Son of God is likewise expressly
affirmed in a provincial council and also to some extent in the Council of
Trent.[378]
Theological proof. It includes two conclusions.
1) Christ came to take away all sins, because He came to save men, and all
sins are an obstacle to salvation.
2) St. Thomas proves that Christ came first of all to take away original sin,
since this sin is absolutely greater extensively, inasmuch as it extends to the
whole human race, by which the race is infected; although actual sin is greater
intensively, because it has more of the nature of voluntary.
Hence in virtue of the present decree, it is probable that Christ came also
only to take away original sin, but not solely for the taking away of actual
sins; because, if there had been no original sin, this would eliminate the more
important reason for the Incarnation. Moreover, in virtue of the present decree,
Christ came in passible and mortal flesh; but, if there had been no original
sin, His flesh would have been neither passible nor mortal.[379]
Fifth Article: Whether It Was Fitting That God Should Become Incarnate In The
Beginning Of The Human Race?
The answer is in the negative. But He came "in the fullness of
time" as St. Paul says.[380]
For it was not fitting that God become incarnate before sin, since the
Incarnation is for the redemption of the human race; nor was the Incarnation
fitting immediately after sin, and this for three reasons.
1) That man, being humbled, would more readily acknowledge the seriousness of
the disease and the necessity of Redemption, and so would cry out for it.
2) That the human race might gradually be led from imperfection to perfection
by means of the natural law, the Mosaic law, and the Gospel.
3) Because it befitted the dignity of the Word incarnate that His coming be
announced by the prophets.
Sixth Article: Whether The Incarnation Ought To Have Been Put Off Till The
End Of The World?
St. Thomas denies this, but says it was fitting for the Incarnation to take
place "in the fullness of time," as stated by St. Paul,[381] or
morally speaking "in the midst of the years."[382]
Three reasons are given.
1) Because it is not fitting that the efficient cause of perfection be put
off so long a time.
2) Because at the end of the world there would have been almost no knowledge
of God among men.
3) Because it was fitting that the salvation of the human race be effected by
faith in the Savior, not only by faith in some future thing but also by faith in
something present and past.
Thus the question of the fitness of the Incarnation has been sufficiently
examined both as to its relative necessity for the reparation of the human race,
and its absolute necessity as regards condign reparation. The proximate motive
of the Incarnation has also been considered, which was formally the motive of
mercy, namely, the alleviation of the human race from its misery, or "for
our salvation," as the Nicene Creed says.
Having discussed the fact of the Incarnation, we now come to consider its
nature.
CHAPTER IV: QUESTION 2
Prologue: The Mode Of The Union Of The Word Incarnate
St. Thomas has the following considerations about this mode of union.
1) The union itself (q. 2).
2) The person assuming the human nature (q. 3).
3) The nature assumed and the perfections or defects of this assumed nature
(q. 4-15).
Then the consequences of this union will be discussed, namely, as regards
being, volition, and operation.
Hence this second question is about the essence of the Incarnation, or about
the hypostatic union.
This second question contains twelve articles, and is divided into three
parts.
The first part (a. 1-6) discusses what is and what is not the nature of this
union. It inquires 1. whether the union took place in the nature; 2. or in the
person; 3. or in the suppositum; 4. whether the person of Christ is composite;
5. what is the union of body and soul in Christ?
Thus the question is gradually solved, and the sixth article, which is of
great importance, unites the preceding articles, by asking whether the human
nature was united to the Word accidentally.
The second part considers the union with reference to the divine actions,
which are creation and assumption (a. 7, 8).
The third part considers the union with reference to grace: Is it the
greatest of unions (a. g)? Did it come about by grace (a. 10)? Was it the result
of merit? Was the grace of union natural to the man Christ (a. 12)?
This second question virtually contains the whole treatise on the
Incarnation, just as the third question of the first part of the Summa in which
God is defined as the self-subsisting Being, virtually contains the whole
treatise on the One God.
As regards the order of the questions, it must be noted that in the Summa
Theologica St. Thomas follows the logical order rather than the historical,
whereas in the Contra Gentes (Book IV, q. 27 f.) he follows primarily the
historical order by refuting the various heresies that arose concerning the
Incarnation.
Heresies concerning the Incarnation. For an understanding of the articles of
this question, a brief explanation must be given of the principal heresies
condemned by the Church: Arianism, Apollinarianism, Nestorianism, Monophysitism,
and Eutychianism.[383]
A threefold division is made in these heresies, inasmuch as some erred
concerning the divinity of Christ, others denied His humanity, and finally some
erred about the union of the two natures.
God permits errors so that by opposing them the truth may be presented in
clearer light.
[diagram 109]
ERRORS
divinity of Christ:
This was denied by the Ebionites, Cerinthians, Arians, and others. The Arians
and Apollinarians denied that Christ had a soul.
humanity of Christ:
The Docetae and Valentinus denied that Christ had a real body
the union of the natures:
The Nestorians denied that the union was personal
The Eutychians and Monophysites denied that there were two natures in Christ
Thus it was that already in the first four or five centuries of Christianity
almost all the errors possible against the Incarnation were proposed.
1) The divinity of Christ was denied.
In the first century, by the Ebionites and Cerinthians. In the second and
third centuries by the Adoptionists and Gnostics.
In the fourth century, by the Arians. They declared that Christ is not the
Son of God consubstantial with the Father but is a creature; that the Word
(Logos) pre-existed, but was created, and is a mediator, who assumed in the womb
of the Blessed Virgin Mary only a body and not a soul. Thus the Arians concluded
that Christ is neither truly God nor truly man. Hence St. Athanasius
replied[384] that such a conception of Christ made it impossible for Him to
satisfy for the human race or free it from sin. This means that the denial of
the mystery of the Incarnation includes the denial of the mystery of Redemption,
and thus there is left but the semblance of Christianity.[385]
Later on, in the sixteenth century, the Socinians denied the divinity of
Christ, and the same must be said in our times of the Unitarians, who deny the
Trinity, and also liberal Protestants and Modernists of the present day.
2) The humanity of Christ. Some denied that Christ's body was real, others
that He had a soul. The Docetae, such as Marcion and the Manichaeans, said that
Christ merely appeared to have a body.
Appelles and Valentinus in the third century said that Christ's body was real
but celestial, sidereal or aerial, and therefore He did not derive His human
nature from the Virgin Mary.
The Arians and Anomoeans taught that the Word did not assume a soul. In the
fourth century the Apollinarians held that Christ had only a sensitive soul, and
that the Word performed the functions of the rational soul, though they
admitted, contrary to the Arians, that the Word was not created.[386]
3) Some denied the unity of person in Christ, others the twofold nature. In
the third century, the unity of person was denied by Paul of Samosata. In the
fourth century, Diodorus of Tarsus said that the Word was only accidentally
united to Christ. So also Theodore of Mopsuestia and the Nestorians, teaching a
sort of personal union, rejected it really, however, inasmuch as they posited
merely a moral union between the two natures. In this way they sought to refute
Apollinarianism. The consequence of these errors was the view that Mary is not
the Mother of God.
The prominent opponent of the Nestorians was St. Cyril of Alexandria who, in
refuting them, availed himself of the principal argument used by St. Athanasius
against the Arians, namely, that, if Christ is not God, but only morally united
to Him, as a saint is, then how could He satisfy for us or free the human race
from sin?[387]
In our times, too, the disciples of Gunther denied the unity of person in
Christ, since they defined a person as a self-conscious nature, for in Christ
there are two self-conscious natures.
So also, Rosmini acknowledges between the Word and the human will in Christ
merely an accidental union, inasmuch as the human will, since it was completely
dominated by the Word, ceased to be personal. Rosmini says: "Hence the
human will ceased to be personal in Christ as man, and, since it is personal in
other men, in Christ there remained but the human nature."[388] Thus the
union in Christ between the Word and the human will would be merely accidental
and moral. The error of Rosmini and Gunther is that both do not seek to define
person ontologically by reason of subsistence, but only psychologically through
self-consciousness, or by reason of liberty. This error is the result of the
nineteenth-century psychologism.
The Modernists say about the same, since they reduce the hypostatic union, if
they give it any thought, to God's influence upon the human conscience of the
historic Christ, or to the subconscious self in Christ by which He perceived
that He was loved by God above all others.
Finally, the Eutychians or Monophysites denied that there were two natures in
Christ. Eutyches posed as the adversary of Nestorius and the defender of the
theology of St. Cyril of Alexandria, which he did not understand. He was a man
of little learning, and obstinate, and so he went to the other extreme of
Nestorianism. He was so insistent in affirming the unity of person in Christ
against the Nestorians that he ended in denying His twofold nature. He said:
"I confess that our Lord was of two natures before the union; but after the
union I acknowledge one nature,"[389] either because the human nature was
absorbed by the divine nature, or because each nature commingled to form a third
nature, distinct from each before the union, or because the human nature and the
Word were absolutely united as the soul and the body are. Hence Eutyches by this
method succeeded in proclaiming something that the Nestorians denied, since they
denied that the Blessed Virgin Mary is the Mother of God.
In the fourth century, however, the Monothelites, professing that Christ had
but one will, by this very fact rejected the doctrine that there were two
natures in Him. The followers of the modern heresy that declares the Word really
emptied Himself, also deny a twofold nature in Christ, since they hold that the
Word, at least partly and for a time, set aside His divine attributes.[390]
Thus several heresies made their appearance as excessive reactions against
the preceding ones; so also not infrequently it happens that the human mind in
its aberrations passes from one extreme to the other.
1) Arius says that Christ is the created Word united to a human body, without
a soul. St. Athanasius says correctly: then Christ could not have satisfied for
us.
2) But Apollinaris says that Christ is the uncreated Word united to a human
body, without a rational soul, since this latter was capable of sinning, and
consequently could not satisfy for us.
3) Then Nestorius, in a reactionary spirit, says that Christ has a rational
soul which is morally united to the Word. Thus the union of the natures is no
longer personal.
4) Finally, Eutyches goes to the other extreme and asserts that the union of
the natures is not only moral but also physical, meaning that after the union
there is only one nature. This doctrine is Monophysitism.
These last three mentioned heresies deny that the Blessed Virgin Mary is the
Mother of God, and they do so for various reasons. Apollinaris says that Jesus
is not a man, Eutyches says that His body is not of the same nature as ours,
whereas the Nestorians assert that Jesus is not God, but morally united to Him.
The dogma strikes a medium between Nestorianism and Monophysitism,
transcending both of them, inasmuch as it states that both natures in Christ are
united in one person.
Teaching of the Church. It is evident from the Gospels, the Apostles' Creed,
and the condemnation of the above-mentioned heresies.
1) Already even in the Apostles' Creed it is stated that Jesus Christ is
truly God and truly man, inasmuch as it says: "I believe... in Jesus Christ
His only Son, who was conceived by the Holy Ghost, born of the Virgin
Mary."[391]
2) In the First Council of Nicaea (325) and the First of Constantinople
(381), the consubstantiality of the Word with the Father is explicitly declared.
The First Council of Nicaea says: "God of God, light of light, true God of
true God, born not made, of one substance with the Father, which the Greeks call
homoousion."[392] It is likewise declared against the Docetae, Gnostics,
and Apollinarians that "Christ had a complete human nature."[393]
3) In the fifth century, the Athanasian Creed declares all that is of faith
on this point, in these few words: "Jesus Christ the Son of God is God and
man. God, of the substance of the Father, begotten of the Father from all
eternity; and man, of the substance of His Mother, born in time.... Who,
although He be God and man, yet He is not two, but one Christ; one, not by
conversion of the Godhead into the flesh, but by the assumption of the manhood
into God; one altogether, not by confusion of substance, but by unity of
person."[394]
The Council of Ephesus (431) proclaims against Nestorius that there is one
person in Christ, and two natures hypostatically united,[395] and also proclaims
"that this same Christ is both God and man."[396]
Likewise, not long afterward (451), the Council of Chalcedon defines against
Eutyches and the Monophysites that "One and the same Christ, Son, Lord,
Only-begotten, must be acknowledged to be in two natures, without confusion,
change, division, separation; the distinction of natures being by no means
destroyed by their union; but rather the distinction of each nature being
preserved and concurring in one person and one hypostasis;[397] not in something
that is parted or divided into two persons, but in one and the same and
only-begotten Son of God the Word, the Lord Jesus Christ."[398] This text
is quoted almost verbatim in various subsequent councils, the Council of
Florence being the last to refer to it (1441).
Finally Pope Pius X condemned the following proposition of the Modernists:
"The Christological teaching of SS. Paul and John, and of the Councils of
Nicaea, Ephesus, and Chalcedon is not Christ's own teaching, but that which the
Christian conscience conceived concerning Jesus."[399]
Let us now undertake the philosophical analysis of these definitions of the
Church.
First Article: Whether The Union Of The Incarnate Word Took Place In The
Nature
State of the question. The meaning is: Does this union, referred to in the
heading of this article, result in only one nature, as Eutyches and Dioscorus
taught? In this article we have the refutation of Monophysitism.
The reason why St. Thomas refutes Eutyches before Nestorius is that he is
following the logical order and not the historical order. It is in accordance
with logical procedure to state first in what this union does not consist, and
afterward what constitutes it.
The difficulties presented at the beginning of this article are arguments of
Eutyches, who sought to defend the teaching of St. Cyril of Alexandria against
the Nestorians, but Eutyches had a wrong conception of St. Cyril's teaching.
First difficulty. The text quoted by St. Thomas in this first objection is
not St. Cyril's, as found in the acts of the Council of Chalcedon, but is to be
attributed to the heretic Dioscorus. However, since the words can be interpreted
in a good sense and are attributed to St. Cyril, they are examined by St. Thomas
here. The text reads: "We must understand not two natures, but one
incarnate nature of the Word of God." It does not say simply "one
nature," but "one incarnate nature"; and this is true, since only
the divine nature became incarnate, as explained afterward in the Second Council
of Constantinople,[400] and the words of the council on this point are quoted by
St. Thomas in his reply to the first objection.
St. Cyril had said that this union was not moral but physical.[401] By
calling the union physical, St. Cyril by no means meant that it signified a
commingling of the two natures, but that the union was more than moral and
accidental, and as used by St. Cyril the expression came to be commonly accepted
as equivalent to hypostatic union.[402]
In the Latin Church, the terms "person" and "nature" have
a distinct meaning already from the time of Tertullian, who admits in Christ one
person but two natures, almost as clearly as St. Hilary and St. Augustine
declared after him.[403]
Second difficulty. It is taken from the Athanasian Creed, in which it is said
of Christ: "As the rational soul and the flesh together are one man, so God
and man together are one Christ." But the soul and the body unite in
constituting one nature. Eutyches applied this remote analogy in the literal
sense.
Third difficulty. St. Gregory Nazianzen says: "The human nature[in
Christ] is deified," just as St. Cyril had said, "the divine nature is
incarnate." But some could understand the expression to mean a certain
transmutation and blending of the natures.
Eutyches understood the expression in the following sense: "That our
Lord was of two natures before the union; but after the union there was one
nature." Eutyches said: "Christ is of two natures, not in two natures,
nor is He consubstantial with us according to the flesh; the deity suffered and
was buried."
The reply of St. Thomas, notwithstanding these difficulties, is as follows:
The union of the Word incarnate did not take place in the nature or essence,
such that in Christ there is only one nature. In fact, this is absolutely
impossible; but there are in Christ two distinct natures.
This conclusion is a dogma of our faith defined as such against Eutyches in
the Council of Chalcedon in these words: "We teach that Christ... is
perfect as God and that He is perfect as man, true God and true man... and that
He is in two natures,[404] without confusion, ... the properties of each nature
being preserved, and that He is in one person and one subsistence."[405]
The Second Council of Constantinople defines similarly.[406] Likewise the
Athanasian Creed declares: "One altogether, not by confusion of substance,
but by unity of person."[407] Subsequent councils and professions of faith
give similar definitions.
Scriptural proof. From the many passages already quoted, it is evident that
Christ is truly God and truly man. It suffices here to give the following text
from the Old Testament: "A child is born to us... and His name shall be
called... God the Mighty."[408] Thus also in the New Testament, the greater
and especially more sublime prophets were already illumined to perceive the
divine nature of the promised Messias.
From the New Testament we have the following texts: "I am the way and
the truth and the life."[409] "Who being in the form of God, thought
it not robbery to be equal with God, but emptied Himself, taking the form of a
servant."[410] Here we have the twofold form or nature, namely, of God and
the servant, each distinct, without confusion (of natures). Again we read:
"That which was from the beginning, which we have heard, which we have seen
with our eyes, which we have looked upon, and our hands have handled, of the
Word of life."[411] Here again we have the two natures distinctly
mentioned, namely, the one divine in the words "of the Word of life,"
the other the human nature, in the words "which we have looked upon and our
hands have handled."
Proof from reason. It is given in the body of the article, in which, from an
analysis of the notion of nature, the absurdity of Monophysitism is shown, which
is just as absurd as pantheism. There are two parts to this article. The first
part considers what is meant by the word "nature." The second part
shows the impossibility of the union taking place in the nature.
First part. It determines, by the way of invention, following Aristotle[412]
and Boethius, the various acceptations of the term "nature."
This noun signifies: 1. birth or begetting of living beings; 2. the principle
of this begetting; 3. whatever intrinsic principle of motion essentially belongs
to the subject in which it is, such as the principle of the vegetative life, or
of the sensitive life, in each and every subject; 4. The substantial form, which
is this radical principle of natural operations, for instance, in the plant; 5.
matter, which is the principle of natural passivity; thus it is said that the
animal is naturally mortal; 6. the essence also of spiritual things and of God
Himself, inasmuch as this essence is the radical principle of their operations.
So says Boethius, who is quoted in this article, and St. Thomas concludes:
"But we are now speaking of nature as it signifies the essence."
Second part. It is shown to be impossible for the union to take place in the
nature. The argument of St. Thomas may be reduced to the following syllogism.
There are only three possible ways for the union to take place in the nature,
namely: 1. by the composition of things that are perfect in themselves and that
remain perfect; 2. by the mixture of things perfect in themselves that have
undergone a change; 3. by the union of things imperfect in themselves that have
been neither mixed nor changed.
But these ways are incompatible. Therefore it is impossible for the union to
take place in the nature.
[diagram page 117]
UNION
of two perfect things
that remains such, as a heap of stones or a house: called composition. One
nature does not result from this union
that have changed, as a combination of elements resulting in a mixture; but
the divine nature is absolutely unchangeable; for Christ would be neither truly
man nor truly God.
of imperfect things
that have been neither changed nor mixed, as man is composed of soul and
body. But both the divine and the human natures are in themselves perfect. But
the divine nature cannot be even a part of the compound as form, for then it
would be less than the whole
The whole article must be read.
More briefly: This union does not take place in the nature, so that there
results from it but one nature:
1) Because Christ would not be truly man and truly God, but a sort of
chimera.
2) Because the divine nature is unchangeable and cannot constitute a part of
any whole, not even as form, for thus it would be less perfect than the
whole.[413]
Objection. Some have said that there can be a transubstantiation of the human
nature into the divine, just as there is a transubstantiation of the bread into
the body of Christ, without any corruption in the process.
Reply. Even if this transubstantiation were not incompatible, the result of
this would be that after the Incarnation the human nature would cease to exist.
and thus Christ would not be truly man, which is against the faith. Christ is
truly man, for He was born, suffered, and died.
The reply of St. Thomas is confirmed from the solution of the difficulties
presented at the beginning of the article.
Reply to first objection. This difficulty is taken from the text attributed
to St. Cyril and explained by the Second Council of Constantinople,[414] in the
sense that the physical union,[415] which St. Cyril spoke of when arguing
against the Nestorians, who admitted only a moral union, was meant by St. Cyril
as referring not to a union in the nature, but in the person, or to a
subsistential union, as the words themselves denote.[416]
Reply to second objection. When the Athanasian Creed says, "As the
rational soul and flesh together are one man, so God and man together are one
Christ," the analogy has its foundation in the similarity between the
parts, namely, inasmuch as soul and body constitute one person, but not in the
dissimilarity, namely, inasmuch as the soul and the body constitute one nature.
Reply to third objection. Damascene explains correctly the words attributed
to St. Cyril, who says: "The divine nature is incarnate," inasmuch as
it is united personally to flesh. He gives a similar interpretation to the words
of St. Gregory Nazianzen, who says that "the human nature is deified";
namely, not by change, but by being united with the Word, the properties of each
nature remaining intact.
Second Article: Whether The Union Of The Incarnate Word Took Place In The
Person
State of the question. The meaning is: whether this union took place in such
manner that there is only one person.
In this article we have the refutation of Nestorianism, a heresy that denied
there was only one person in Christ, and that admitted only a moral union such
as found in saints united by love with God.
The first two difficulties posited at the beginning of this article, are
arguments raised by the Nestorians.
First difficulty. In God there is no real distinction between person and
nature. If, therefore, this union did not take place in the nature, as the
Nestorians say, then it did not take place in the person.
Second difficulty. Personality is a dignity that belongs to us as human
beings. Hence it is not attributed to irrational animals or to other beings of a
lower order, for these have individuality, but not personality. But Christ's
human nature has no less dignity than ours. Therefore it was much more
reasonable that Christ's human nature should have its own personality.
This difficulty is still proposed in our days by many theologians who
disagree with Cajetan's interpretation of St. Thomas' teaching. These
theologians, as we shall see, in advancing this difficulty against Cajetan, seem
to be unaware of the reply to the second objection of this present article.
Third difficulty. It is taken from the definition of person as given by
Boethius, who says: "a person is an individual substance of a rational
nature." But the Word of God assumed an individual human nature, namely,
this humanity belonging to Christ. Therefore this humanity belonging to Christ
has its own personality.
This difficulty of necessity calls for the making of a profound distinction
between individuality, or individuation, and personality. St. Thomas most
fittingly makes this kind of distinction in his reply to the third objection,
which is thoroughly explained by Cajetan. Nevertheless, even many Scholastics
seem to have only a superficial knowledge of this reply to the third objection,
perhaps because they did not begin by examining with sufficient care the state
and difficulty of the question, as St. Thomas did in his presentation of these
difficulties, which constitute, so to speak, the very problem to be solved in
this article.
The reply, in spite of these difficulties, is: The union of the Word
incarnate took place in the person of the Word, such that there is only one
person in Christ. This declaration is a dogma of our faith.
This reply was defined against the Nestorians in the Council of Ephesus, in
which the union was declared to be hypostatic, or personal,[417] and it
condemned the assertion of two persons morally united in Christ. It likewise
condemned the Nestorian expression, Christ the man is theophoron, that is, God
bearer.[418] Likewise it declared that, "if anyone does not confess that
the Word of God suffered and died in the flesh, let him be anathema."[419]
It also defined that the Blessed Virgin Mary is the Mother of God,[420] since
she is the mother of this man Jesus who is God, constituting one person.[421]
These definitions are confirmed in the Council of Chalcedon, which says:
"One and the same Christ... acknowledged to be in two natures, without
confusion... and concurring in one person and one hypostasis, not in something
that is parted or divided."[422]
Similarly the Apostles' Creed confesses that one and the same person is the
Son of God and of man; particularly the Creed of St. Athanasius, which says of
the union, "absolutely one, not in confusion of substance, but in unity of
person."[423]
Sacred Scripture. This doctrine of the faith is already clearly expressed in
the New Testament; for it attributes the properties of both the divine and the
human natures to one and the same Christ, since it is the same Christ who is
conceived, born, baptized in the Jordan, who fears, is sad, hungry and tired on
His journey, who suffers and dies on the cross. This same person is called the
Son of God, God above all, the Author of life, for He Himself says: "I am
the truth and the life."[424] Hence we see that the properties of each
nature are attributed in Sacred Scripture to the same intelligent and
incommunicable subject, that is, to the same person. But this person is the
eternal person of the Word, as expressed by the Evangelist in these words:
"The Word was made flesh,"[425] that is, the Son of God became man.
Therefore the Son of God and man are not two persons, but one person.
The common notion of person suffices for an understanding of the preceding
statements, namely, that a person is an intelligent and sui juris[426] or free
agent. This subject can be merely a man, an angel, God, or any divine person.
Nestorius objected that a moral union was sufficient.
Reply. A moral union is established by means of affection. But, however
intimate is the friendship between two persons, one friend is not said to have
become the other friend, neither is a saint who is united with God by a bond of
most fervent love said to have become God, nor is God said to have become either
Peter or Paul, although there is a moral union between them and God.
In fact, Christ could not have said truthfully: "I am the way, the
truth, and the life."[427] In other words, speaking of Himself, He could
not have attributed truly to Himself divine attributes and also those that
belong to the human nature. The pronoun "I" denotes the person
speaking, and there is only one person; for if there are two persons? it cannot
be said that one is the other. In affirmative judgments, the verb "is"
expresses real identity between subject and predicate. Thus: I am the truth,
signifies: I, who by my mouth, am speaking, am the same person who am the truth.
Otherwise the judgment is absolutely false, and it is as if Paul were to say: I,
who am Paul, am Peter.
Testimony of the Fathers.[428] Tertullian, Origen, St. Ephrem, St.
Athanasius, St. Gregory Nazianzen, St. Jerome, St. Cyril of Alexandria, St. Leo
I, and St. John Damascene quoted by St. Thomas in the counter-argument of this
third article have all affirmed clearly and most explicitly that there is one
person in Christ.
It must be noted that in the liturgy of the Church the termination of the
orations frequently is, "Through our Lord Jesus Christ who liveth and
reigneth with Thee in the unity of the Holy Ghost, forever and ever."
Body of the article. It contains two parts. In the first part a distinction
is made between person and nature. The second part proves that the union of the
Word incarnate took place in the person.
First of all the article must be explained, and then we shall consider the
erroneous system of several modern philosophers concerning personality, and also
the systems freely discussed among Catholic theologians.
In the first part of this article, as regards the distinction that is made
between person and nature, by a gradual process the argument proceeds from
common sense or natural reasoning, to the establishment of a philosophical proof
that acknowledges and defends the real validity of natural reasoning against
either empiric or idealistic phenomenalism.
The first part of this article must be read. It is divided into three parts:
1. the conclusion; 2. definition of suppositum; 3. definition of person, which
is completed in the reply to the third objection.
First conclusion. It may be expressed briefly as follows: There is a real
difference between suppositum and nature in every creature, just as there is a
real difference between the whole and its parts.
The reason is that the nominal definition of suppositum or the subject of
predication signifies the whole, and in every creature existence and accidents
are not included in its essence. Such is the case in the angels, for Michael is
not his existence nor his action.[429] Moreover, in corporeal things, in
addition to the essence of the species, each has individuating principles that
are derived from quantified matter, such as these bones, this flesh.
Hence this real distinction between the created nature and the suppositum
that contains it, is not a distinction between two separate things, but it is a
distinction that prevails between a real and actual whole, and its real, formal,
and perfective part.
Contrary to what has been said, there is, a real distinction in God between
suppositum and nature.
The real definition of suppositum is given in the following words. The
suppositum is taken to be a whole which has the nature as its formal part to
perfect it; and as stated in the reply to the third objection, the suppositum is
the whole that exists and acts separately by itself. This point must be
carefully considered, because it constitutes the philosophical foundation of the
whole treatise.
Thus the suppositum is that which is, namely, the real subject of
attribution, so that the suppositum is not attributed to any other subject;
whereas nature is that by which a thing is such as it is, in such a species.
Similarly, existence is that by which a thing is placed outside of nothing and
its causes; a faculty is that by which the subject can operate, and operation is
that by which it actually operates.
All the above-mentioned are attributed to the suppositum, and this latter is
not attributed to any other subject. Moreover, it must be noted that the
following divers affirmative judgments: Peter is a man, Peter exists, Peter can
act, Peter does act, all these affirmative judgments assert real identity
between subject and predicate by the word "is." They are equivalent in
meaning to: Peter is the same real subject that is the man that exists, that can
act, that does act. For these judgments to be true, this real identity between
subject and predicate must be verified outside the soul, although Peter's
essence is not his existence, nor the faculty by which he acts, nor his action.
Hence there must be something by which the subject is the same real subject, or
that by which something is "that which by itself (separately) exists and
acts,"[430] as stated in the reply to the third objection.
Farther on we shall see how that by which a thing is a quod (or subject of
attribution)[431] is subsistence, for which reason the suppositum is that which
is competent to exist by itself separately. This truth constitutes the
philosophical foundation of this entire treatise.[432]
Person is defined as an intelligent and sui juris or free subject, namely, a
suppositum having a rational, or intellectual, nature.
This definition is given at the end of the first part of this article in the
following equivalent words: "And what is said of a suppositum is to be
applied to a person in rational, or intelligent, creatures; for a person is
nothing else than an individual substance of a rational nature, according to
Boethius."
In addition to this it must be said that a person is an intelligent sui juris
subject by itself separately existing and by itself operating, such as Peter,
Paul. St. Thomas says similarly: "Person is a subsistent individual of a
rational nature."[433]
This definition is explained at the end of the third objection. The objection
states that according to Boethius, person is an individual substance of a
rational nature; but Christ assumed an individual human nature; therefore He
assumed a human person, and so there are two persons in Christ, namely, the
person assuming and the person assumed.
In the solution of this objection, St. Thomas in his reply most splendidly
illustrates the definition of Boethius, by distinguishing accurately between
individuality, or individuation, and personality.
This reply to the third objection must be read.
Not every individual in the genus of substance, even in rational nature, is a
person, but that alone which exists by itself, and not that which exists in some
more perfect thing. Hence the hand of Socrates, although it is a kind of
individual, is not a person, but the part of a person, the part of a person and
the part of a substance.
On the other hand, we know that according to St. Thomas[434] quantified
matter is the principle of individuation, that is, as Cajetan explains:
"Matter capable of this particular quantity so that it is not susceptible
of that other quantity; for it is in this way that we distinguish between two
drops of water that are most alike: not having the same quantified matter, they
are thus in different parts of space. Hence individuation, which is derived from
matter, is of the lowest order in man, whereas personality, as stated in the
reply to the second objection, pertains to the dignity of a thing and to its
perfection, so far as it pertains to the dignity and perfection of that thing to
exist by itself."[435]
In Christ, as we shall see, individuation, as in our case, is effected by
matter, whereas His personality is uncreated and thus there is an infinite
difference between the two. St. Thomas discusses this point in his reply to the
third objection, and elsewhere he says: "Person signifies what is most
perfect in all nature, that is, a subsistent individual of a rational
nature."[436]
Therefore we must not confuse the individual nature, individuated or
singular, with suppositum and person. For even the individuated nature is not
that which is, but that by which anything is constituted in a certain species
that is limited or contracted to an individual grade of being, for example, an
individuated nature is this humanity. Similarly matter is that by which anything
is material.[437] On the contrary, by suppositum or person is meant this person
separately existing by himself and acting, to whom this humanity is attributed,
as constituting a part of him; hence we do not say that this man is his
humanity, for the verb "is" expresses by a logical distinction real
identity between the whole and its parts. We truly say that this man is not his
humanity, but has humanity, or has his nature. Thus the common sense or natural
reason of all men, by so speaking, distinguishes in a confused manner between
person and nature, or between that which is, and that by which something is
constituted in a certain species.
Hence St. Thomas[438] and the Thomists, in explaining the definition of
person as given by Boethius, make some addition and say that a person is an
entirely incommunicable individual substance of a rational nature, inasmuch as a
person is the first subject of attribution, which is predicated of no other
subject, and to whom is attributed whatever pertains to person, such as nature,
existence, properties and actions. But communicability is threefold.[439]
[diagram page 126]
COMMUNICABILITY
of the part to the whole
to this whole that is the suppositum: e.g., of the humanity to the Word
to this essential or quantitative whole: e.g., of the soul to man; e.g. of
the arm to the body
of the universal to the inferior
e.g., of the humanity to all individuals of the species
Hence, when it is said that a person is incommunicable, what is especially
meant is that such person is incommunicable to another suppositum, although even
both to inferiors and to the quantitative whole.
St. Thomas discusses this incommunicability of person in various parts of his
works.[440]
Thus the transition is made gradually from the common or popular notion of
person to the philosophical notion of the term. It is not necessary here by way
of conclusion to this article to explain the various systems freely disputed
among Catholic theologians concerning personality, or what formally constitutes
a person.[441]
Second conclusion. Toward the end of the argumentative part of this article,
what St. Thomas intends to prove concerning the formal constituent of person may
be expressed by the following syllogism.
Everything that adheres to a person, whether it does or does not pertain to
the nature, is united to it in the person, which is the whole by itself
separately existing.
But our Catholic faith teaches us that the humanity of Christ adheres to the
person of the Son of God.
Therefore it is united to the person of Christ, but not to His nature.
The major follows from the definition of person, since it is the whole or the
subject by itself separately existing and acting to whom are attributed as to
the ultimate subject of attribution all those things that pertain to a person,
such as nature, existence, accidents, and other notes.
The minor is evident from revelation, inasmuch as the human nature as also
its parts and properties, such as the soul, the body, passibility, and other
qualities are attributed to the Son of God.[442]
First confirmation. There are only two possible unions; either the union of
the Word was with the nature, or with the person. For union by affection or by
reason of the extraordinary grace bestowed upon the person loved, such as
Nestorius imagined in the case of Christ, does not belong solely to the Word,
but is common to the three persons of the Trinity operating together ad extra,
and this union is already found in varying degrees in all the just.
Second confirmation. If there are two persons in Christ, then we are not
redeemed; for neither of these two persons could have redeemed us from sin: not
the divine person, because He could neither suffer nor satisfy for sin nor merit
for us; not the human person, because he could not confer infinite value upon
his satisfactory and meritorious works, such as was required for our redemption,
so that the redemption be adequate.
It remains for us to reply to the first two difficulties proposed at the
beginning of this article.
The first objection was: The person of God is not distinct from His nature.
But the union of the Word incarnate did not take place in the nature. Therefore
it did not take place in the person.
Reply to first objection. I distinguish the major: that there is no real
distinction between nature and person in God, this I concede; that they do not
differ in meaning, this I deny. I concede the minor.
I distinguish the conclusion. Therefore the union did not take place in the
person, if by this is meant that the divine person is not even distinct in
meaning from nature, then I concede the conclusion; otherwise I deny it. The
reply to the first objection must be read.
Therefore this union of the humanity with God took place, not in the divine
nature, but in the person of the Son.
Thus the mental distinction between God's mercy and justice is the foundation
for the truth of these propositions: God punishes not by His mercy, but by His
justice, although these two attributes are not distinct. Thus God understands by
His intellect and not by His will. Likewise the Word is united to the humanity
not in the nature but in the person.
As Cajetan says: "The reply is confirmed by reason of the fact... that
the union of the human nature in the mystery of the Incarnation does not add
anything to the meaning of nature, but it does indeed add something to the
notion of person, because it adds the notion of subsisting in the human
nature."[443]
Moreover, it must be noted that St. Thomas in this reply to the first
objection and often afterward, says: "The Word subsists in the human
nature." So does Cajetan,[444] whereas many modern theologians say less
correctly: The humanity subsists in the Word. In truth, that which subsists is
not the humanity, which is that by which the Word is man; that which subsists is
the very Word incarnate.
Second objection. It is still proposed in these days by many theologians who
object to Cajetan's interpretation of St. Thomas' teaching. It reads as follows:
Christ's human nature has no less dignity than ours. But personality belongs to
dignity. Hence, since our human nature has its proper personality, there is much
more reason for Christ's to have its proper personality.
Several theologians in our times revive this argument against Cajetan,
saying: Personality cannot be a substantial mode that terminates the nature,
rendering it immediately capable of existence, as constituting it that which by
itself separately exists.
The reply of St. Thomas is quoted by Pius XI in his encyclical commemorating
the decrees of the Council of Ephesus against Nestorius. The following statement
summarizes the reply of St. Thomas: Personality pertains to dignity inasmuch as
it is that by reason of which a person exists separately by oneself. But it is a
greater dignity to exist in something nobler than oneself than to exist by
oneself. The complete reply to the second objection should be read.
Thus it is more perfect for the sensitive life to be united to the
intellective, and for every inferior to be united to the superior. Just as it is
more perfect for the deacon to be made a priest, so it is more perfect for the
human nature to exist in the person of the Word, than to have its own
personality; because whatever perfection there is in its own personality, is
found infinitely and more eminently in the Word, so that there is intrinsic
independence not only from inferior material things, as in the case of every
rational soul, but from every creature, for Christ, indeed, is not a creature,
but above every creature.
And what St. Thomas says in this reply concerning one's own personality can
be said of the substantial mode by which, as Cajetan remarks, it is that by
which it exists separately.
Cajetan gives a good explanation of St. Thomas' reply to the second
objection, saying: "Just as it is nobler for the sensitive life to have its
complete specific nature by a form of a nobler order, namely, by the rational
soul, so a greater dignity was bestowed upon the human nature of Christ from the
fact that it was assumed by the divine personality."[445]
Later Thomists, such as Billuart, make this additional comment: Subsistence
or personality is the perfection and completion of the nature, perfecting it not
in its notion of nature or essence, but in its notion of suppositum or person,
inasmuch as it pertains to the dignity of a thing that it exist by itself; as
St. Thomas says: "It is a greater dignity to exist in something nobler than
oneself than to exist by oneself. Hence, from this very fact, Christ's human
nature is not less noble but more noble than ours."[446]
It must be noted that the above definition of person, namely, an intelligent
and free subject, easily finds its verification both in the human person, the
angelic person, and the divine person. In all of them the subject is
incommunicable, which cannot be attributed to another, and all of them enjoy
intelligence and free will. But it is evident that person is not predicated
univocally of God and man; it is predicated analogically, though not
metaphorically, but properly; for the formal signification of person is properly
retained in God proportionally, just as the proper signification of intelligence
and liberty, of the real subject.[447]
Difficulty proposed by more modern critics. The final difficulty is thus
proposed by many modern philosophers of the Guntherian and Rosminian trend of
thought. They say that the mystery of the Incarnation is absolutely
unintelligible from the mere abstract and metaphysical notion of either
suppositum or subsistence or personality. For it is not only the metaphysical or
ontological concept of personality that must be considered; it must be viewed in
its psychological and moral aspects likewise, which come under experience. But
psychologically, personality seems to consist in consciousness of oneself, and
in personal judgment. Hence Locke, and after him Gunther, defined person as
"a nature conscious of itself."[448] But in the moral order,
personality seems to consist in this, that every one is sui juris, or is master
of himself, or is free to act as he wishes, and Rosmini insists on this
point.[449]
In the days of Modernism (1905) several students of dogmatic theology
attending this course in a certain university did not even listen to the
professor who was explaining the treatise on the Incarnation. They wrote letters
or read books not pertaining to dogmatic theology, because, as they said, the
conception of personality as proposed by scholastic theology is unintelligible.
I then said to one of these students: "Therefore, in your opinion in
what does personality consist so as to give us a better understanding of the
mystery of the Incarnation?" He replied: "Personality consists in a
consciousness of oneself, and this is enough." I asked him how many
consciousnesses and intelligences there are in Christ? This student had not even
considered the fact that there are two intelligences and consequently two
consciousnesses in Christ. Therefore there ought to be two personalities in
Christ, if personality formally consisted in consciousness of oneself.
Another of these students replied to me: "Personality consists in
freedom or dominion over oneself." But neither had he considered that in
Christ there are two freedoms, and so there ought to be two personalities and
hence two persons, which is the heresy of Nestorianism.
Hence it is manifest that, for assuming a more profound notion of
personality, it must be considered in its ontological aspect, and not merely in
its psychological and moral aspects.
For the solution of this difficulty, which is very widespread in these days,
it will be useful at the beginning of this treatise, for its clarification, to
start with a certain introduction or ascent from the psychological and moral
notion of personality, especially as found in the saints, ending in the
ontological notion of the most exalted personality of Christ. The notion of
personality will thus be present in a less abstract, but more vivid and concrete
manner, as befitting this mystery, when speaking not only with modern
philosophers, but also with the faithful who are not accustomed to the language
of philosophy, and who must, nevertheless, live by faith in the Incarnation, and
who aspire to the contemplation of this mystery.
Introduction Or Ascent Toward A Certain Understanding Of The Incarnation
There are three articles of St. Thomas that enable us to make this
ascent.[450] But what pertains to the psychological and moral aspects of person
must be added.
This introduction must begin by a definition of person considered under this
threefold aspect, namely, ontological, psychological, and moral, and in
accordance with the law of true progress from the psychological and moral
aspects of personality.
Person under this threefold aspect is defined as an intelligent and free
subject, or a substance of a rational nature, by itself separately existing and
operating, conscious of and responsible for itself, such as Peter and Paul.
Human personality is that by which a man is thus by himself separately
existing, and hence conscious of and responsible for his actions, which means
that he is master of his actions. What must especially be noted about
personality is that, besides its common independence from every suppositum,
inasmuch as it exists separately by itself, it enjoys a threefold special
independence, for a person is a suppositum by itself separately existing, whose
specific existence and operation, namely, understanding and willing, does not
intrinsically depend upon matter.
Therefore a person enjoys the following threefold independence:
1. Its existence does not intrinsically depend upon matter, and thus the soul
separated from the body remains immortal.
2. In like manner its understanding does not intrinsically depend upon
matter, and thus it transcends actually existing individual things and extends
to the universal.
3. It will also remain independent of particular goods that are mingled with
evil, for these do not infallibly attract the will, which is specified by
universal good. Thus personality far surpasses individuation by means of matter.
What, then, is the law of true and complete progress concerning psychological
and moral personality?
Some think that this law consists simply in progress of the aforesaid
independence, which would finally be in every respect absolute, or it would
consist in complete autonomy of spirit and will, as Kant says. In accordance
with this tendency, however, the complete evolution of man's personality would
mean that he recognizes nobody his superior. Once this personality is fully
developed, there would no longer be any place for virtues that are called
passive, such as humility, obedience, patience, meekness, even for the
theological virtues; and hence this superior personality would not differ much
from the perfect insubordination of him who said: "I will not serve."
This absolute autonomy, which is the doctrine of Kant, was condemned by the
Vatican Council in these words: "If anyone shall say that human reason is
so independent that faith cannot be enjoined upon it by God; let him be
anathema."[451]
It is manifest that the law of true and complete progress of personality does
not consist merely in progress of the above-mentioned independence; for the true
and legitimate independence of the human person toward things inferior to it has
its foundation in the strict dependence toward realities that are superior to
it. Thus our reason transcends sensible things, space and time, because it is
ordered to universal truth, and so to the knowledge of Him who is supreme Truth,
at least so far as He is naturally knowable.
Likewise, as our will is free and independent with reference to the
attraction of particular good, this is because it is ordered to universal good,
and so to the supreme Good, which means to God the author of nature, who is to
be loved above all things.
True personality has this characteristic, that its legitimate independence or
relative autonomy toward things inferior to itself has its foundation in
immediate dependence on truth and goodness, on supreme Truth and supreme
Goodness, that is, God.
What follows from this characteristic as regards the law of true and complete
progress of psychological and moral personality? It follows that the more
personality dominates inferior things and the more intimately it is dependent on
God, then the more perfect it is.
This is the true law of its progress, which is easily illustrated by
examples, ascending gradually from the lowest grade of human personality until
we reach the personality of Christ.
Thus the lowest grade of psychological and moral personality is verified in
the man who is addicted to inordinate passions. Yet this man is a person or a
substance of an intellectual nature, but insufficiently conscious of his dignity
and dominion. Such a man is not ruled by right reason, but by his senses,
imagination, and inordinate passions as in the case of irrational animals. He
has not dominion over himself, nor independence as regards those things inferior
to him, acting as if invincibly attracted by the lowest kind of good, by
pleasure and every concupiscible object, living according to the prejudices of
the world, rather its slave than its master; he is the slave of sin. What is
developed in him is not personality but the lowest type of individuality, which
manifests itself as individualism or egoism. He wishes to be the center of all
things, and truly becomes the slave of all things, the slave of his passions
that are in open rebellion against one another, inasmuch as they are not
controlled; he becomes the slave of men and events that can in the twinkling of
an eye definitely take away from him the least happiness he enjoys.
Moral personality is far nobler in the virtuous man, who is conscious of his
human dignity and succeeds in controlling his passions, in proportion as he
increases in the love of truth and justice, that is, in proportion as he
increasingly makes his life dependent on God who is to be loved above all
things.
This was, in a certain manner, understood by the great philosophers of
antiquity, such as Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and to some extent by the
Stoics.[452]
Likewise, in the intellectual order, to what shall we attribute that
superiority of intellectual personality in men of great genius compared with
those of ordinary intellectual ability? It must be attributed to the fact that a
man of great genius depends less on the help to be obtained from men of his age
and country, and this because he receives a higher inspiration from God, and is
more dependent on God. Aristotle said about these great men, who are called
divine, such as the divine Plato: "They follow an interior instinct, and it
is not expedient for them to be given advice, because they are moved by a better
principle,"[453] that is, they depend more immediately on God, and their
lives are dominated by this higher inspiration, which sometimes is most
impelling. Thus genius is defined as a certain special nearness to God, a
relationship with the absolute.
But how far superior are the saints to men of ordinary virtue and to men of
great genius! The saints alone fully understood the law of true and complete
progress of human personality, that human personality is the more perfect in
proportion as it is more dependent on God, and united with Him, dominating
inferior things. This aspect of personality is something that belongs most
especially to the saints, being found only in them, since they exemplify in
their lives these words of Christ: "He that loveth his life shall lose it;
and he that hateth his life in this world keepeth it unto life
eternal."[454] The saints, thoroughly understanding these words of our
Lord, engaged in a real conflict with their own ego, fought against a
personality that is the result of egoism or self-love, and reached such a
superior degree of psychological and moral personality that it is truly
supernatural, and even distinguished in the order of grace.
The saints in dying to themselves, submerge themselves, their personality in
God's personality, so that they become truly and most profoundly servants of
God, as the Church says: for the servant is not free, is not master of himself.
God's servant, however, participates in His supreme independence; hence it is
commonly said that to serve God is to reign, and this is the culmination of
created personality, which bears a certain remote resemblance to Christ's
uncreated personality.
How did the saints acquire this eminent personality? In dying to themselves,
they are guided in their intellect not by their own more or less inordinate
judgment, but by the most correct judgment of God received in them by means of
faith and the gifts of the Holy Ghost. Thus it is said that the just man lives
not by his own inspiration but by faith, and considers all things, so to speak,
as God sees them, in the mist of faith.
Likewise, in the case of the will, the saint gradually substitutes God's will
for his own will, in accordance with our Lord's words: "My meat is to do
the will of Him that sent Me that I may perfect His work."[455] They live
continually faithful to the divine will of expression, and they completely
abandon themselves to the divine will of good pleasure not yet made manifest, so
that they become in the profoundest sense the servants of God, just as our hand
is the servant of our will; they become in some manner something of God, or a
creature of God, always in the hand of his Creator. As St. Thomas says,
"They live not for themselves, but for God,"[456] in that charity of
friendship with God, and God is to them another ego.
In fact, the saints keenly perceive that God is to them another ego that is
much more intimate to them than their own ego, and infinitely more perfect,
inasmuch as what perfection there is in their own ego is found most eminently in
God, and inasmuch as God is the radical principle of their intimate life. Thus
the saints, giving up entirely, as it were, their own will and independence in
their relation to God to be loved above all things, finally come to say with St.
Paul: "I live, now not I, but Christ liveth in me,"[457] or "For
to me, to live is Christ, and to die is gain."[458] As St. Thomas remarks:
"As the hunter is preoccupied with hunting, and the student with study, and
as the sick person is preoccupied in regaining health, so with the saints to
live is Christ, because He is the principle and end of their lives."[459]
Thus the psychological and moral personality of the saints in the
supernatural order exceedingly transcends the type of personality found in wise
pagans, just as grace transcends nature. The personality of the saints
transcends not only sensible things, space and time, but in a certain manner all
created things inasmuch as the saints live not for themselves but for God.
This supernatural transcendence is the extraordinary secret of St. Paul's
personality, so that after twenty centuries a vast number of Christians daily
model their lives according to his epistles, as if these had been written
yesterday; whereas only a few of the learned read once in their lives the
epistles of Seneca. It is also the secret of the personality of all the saints,
for example, of St. Francis of Assisi, of St. Catherine of Siena, of St. Vincent
de Paul, who, in a certain manner die to their own personality, so that they
might live to God, so that their supernatural influence is felt not only in
their own times and countries, but practically throughout the Church and for
many centuries.
Pascal excellently pointed this out in one of his works, saying: "The
saints have their realm, their glory, their victory, their luster, and have no
need of temporal or spiritual (intellectual) aggrandizement which in no way
affects them, neither increasing nor decreasing their greatness. The saints are
seen by God and the angels, not by bodies or curious minds. God suffices for
them."[460]
This is strictly speaking to live not for oneself but for God, as St. Thomas
remarks.[461] This means, so to speak, to lose one's own personality in God by
denial of oneself, acquiring perfect mastery over one' passions and all inferior
things. Yet there is an infinite distance between God and the saints, inasmuch
as their ontological personality is created, even though they may say with St.
Paul: "I live, now not I but Christ liveth in me."[462] They are
intimately united with Him in the moral order..
The error of Nestorius, and afterward of Rosmini, consisted in reducing the
union of the Word incarnate to God's union with the saints, so that the
difference between them was only one of degree, and the union itself was
accidental. Hence the following proposition of Rosmini was condemned: "In
Christ's humanity the human will was so rapt by the Holy Spirit to adhere to the
objective entity of the Word, that it gave up completely its human control to
the Word, and the Word personally assumed this control, thus uniting the human
nature to Himself. Hence the human will ceased to be personal in Christ as man,
and, although it constitutes a person in other human beings, in Christ as man it
remained a nature,"[463] This means the confusion of the psychological and
moral manifestation of the ontological personality with its personality.
Truly the uncreated personality of Christ is the inaccessible culmination of
the true and complete progress of personality that can be conceived by us. For
not only in Christ's intellect is God's judgment substituted for His own human
judgment, not only in His will is God's will substituted for His own volition,
but radically in these faculties, in fact, radically in the very soul of Christ,
there is no human personality, but in its place there is the uncreated
personality of the Word that assumed Christ's humanity in an ineffable manner.
And whereas the saints almost never speak in their own person except to accuse
themselves of their sins, Christ speaks of His uncreated and adorable person
saying: "I am the resurrection and the life."[464] "I and the
Father are one."[465] "I" designates the uncreated personality of
the Word, in whom the human nature of Christ exists.
Thus the fitness of the Incarnation is in a certain way made manifest, and a
certain knowledge of this mystery is acquired by considering, on the one hand,
that it belongs to the notion of the supreme Good, namely, God, that He
communicate Himself in the highest manner to the creature, which means in
person, as already stated.[466] On the other hand, the more intimately
personality is dependent on God and is united with Him, dominating things that
are inferior, the more perfect it is. The saints are, in a way, one in judgment
and will with God, since theirs is in complete conformity with His. The ideal
union would be if our human nature were united, without any commingling, with
the divine nature in the same divine person, and in the same divine existence.
But this wonderful union, which absolutely transcends our natural desire, is
verified in the Incarnation of the Word, in which supreme personality is made
manifest according to the greatest possible intimacy with God, and its
domination over inferior things.
All these notes are implicitly contained in the true definition of person,
which is an intelligent and free subject. To say that a person is a subject or
person is to declare its ontological personality; to say that it is intelligent
and therefore conscious of itself is to declare its psychological personality;
to say that it is free and is master of itself is to declare its moral
personality, or to consider it in its moral aspect. From what has been said, it
is clearly evident that ontological personality is the root or foundation of
psychological and moral personality. Therefore they must not be separated, but
must be considered as one person.
Thus it is easy to see that in accordance with revelation, Christ is but one
person, namely, just one intelligent and free subject, although He has two
intellects and two wills. In Christ it is not merely the ontological union of
two natures in one person, for it also follows that there is a wonderful union
in Him in the psychological, moral, and spiritual orders. This union is a kind
of compenetration of Christ's two intellects, inasmuch as His most holy soul,
from the moment of its creation, enjoys the beatific vision, as will be stated
farther on.[467] Thus His human intellect sees immediately, without any
impressed and expressed species, God's essence and intellection, and by this
supreme intellection is comprehensively seen, and by it is continually
reinforced by the light of glory, which is preserved in it and measured by
participated eternity. Likewise there is in Christ's most holy soul from the
beginning of its existence a kind of interpenetration of the two wills, for
Christ as man, by reason of His infused charity intensely loves God's good
pleasure as regards everything, and is in the highest degree loved by God.[468]
Thus Christ's ontological personality results in a union not only of natures
in the order of being, but also in a union of activities in accordance with the
most perfect and intimate subordination of the two intellects and wills in the
order of operation, or in the psychological, moral, and spiritual orders.
Two Theories About The Hypostatic Union
It is of faith, as we have said, that the union of the two natures in Christ
was personal or subsistential,[469] as the Council of Ephesus stated,[470] and
for this reason the union is called hypostatic. But theologians dispute about
what formally constitutes a person, or what is meant properly by personality or
subsistence.
Hence, after a brief examination of the theories condemned by the Church, we
must explain those freely disputed among theologians.
Theories condemned by the Church. There are two, namely, Gunther's system
that reduces personality to consciousness of oneself, and Rosmini's that would
have personality to consist in freedom of will or in dominion over oneself.
Gunther's theory.[471] According to Gunther the fundamental question in
philosophy is the theory of knowledge, which, he said, has its foundation in the
consciousness of oneself, which is what Descartes taught. Gunther rejects
pantheism, of course, but he admits a substantial unity of all created beings,
considering these to be manifestations of the same substance, which he calls
nature. This nature that is unconscious of itself, becomes conscious in man.
Hence Gunther holds that personality properly consists in a consciousness of
oneself, and this note belongs to the rational soul.
From the notion of personality Gunther seeks to explain the mysteries of the
Trinity and the Incarnation. He is unwilling to admit that God is conscious of
Himself by His essence, for then there would be only one person in God. If,
therefore, says Gunther, God knows Himself, it is because in Him subject and
object are in opposition, and he affirms the equality of each. The subject
conscious of itself is the Father, the object conscious of itself is the Son;
finally, the consciousness of equality between each results in the Holy Spirit.
Thus Gunther seeks to demonstrate the Trinity, and reduce it to the order of
philosophical truth. In this we have the essence of semi-rationalism, which does
not deny supernatural revelation, but seeks to reduce all revealed mysteries to
truths of the natural order, as if revelation were supernatural only as to the
manner of its production, not substantially or essentially, namely, on the part
of the object revealed.
Gunther also denies the freedom of creation, admitting the absolute optimism
of Leibnitz. Just as the elevation of the human race to the supernatural order
was necessary, as Baius contends, so also was the Incarnation.
Finally, Gunther explains the union of the Word incarnate. His theory that
personality consists in a consciousness of oneself leads to Nestorianism, for
there are in Christ two consciousnesses, just as there are two intellectual
natures. Gunther, however, in order to avoid the heresy of Nestorianism, devises
a theory that scarcely differs from it, inasmuch as he makes the human nature in
Christ conscious of its subordination and dependence on the divine nature. But
this condition is already verified in all the saints, and is not something
special that is found in Christ alone.
This theory, as also Gunther's semi-rationalism, was condemned by Pius IX in
his papal brief to Cardinal de Geissel, archbishop of Cologne.[472]
This theory is refuted philosophically and theologically.
Philosophically. Consciousness of oneself testifies to or asserts the
identity of our person, but does not constitute it. This means that we know and
remember from our past lives that we are the same persons, and consciousness of
ourselves tells us that we are today the same persons we were in the past.
Therefore both memory and consciousness imply or presuppose an already
constituted person; they merely announce the presence of or are attributed to
person. They constitute only the psychological aspect of personality.
Hence the saying: I am conscious of myself or of my personality; if
consciousness constituted personality, we should have to say: I am conscious of
my consciousness. Person is a substance, whereas consciousness is an act.
Confirmation of the preceding. If consciousness together with memory
constituted personal identity, this identity would be lessened, in fact would be
destroyed, as often as the exercise of memory or consciousness is lessened or
suspended.[473]
Expressed briefly, a person is a subject conscious of itself, but it must be
first constituted as a subject in order that it be conscious of itself.
Theologically. Gunther's theory is refuted by the very fact that it posits in
Christ two persons regardless of his wishes; for Christ's humanity is conscious
of itself, and so is the Godhead. Nor does he avoid the error of Nestorianism by
saying that Christ's humanity is conscious of the subordination to and
dependence on the Godhead; for this union, which is already realized in the
saints, is nothing else but a moral and accidental union with God's judgment and
will. Pius IX was right in condemning this theory. Modernists express themselves
in almost the same terms as Gunther.
Rosmini's theory. Rosmini (1797-1855) did not start, as Gunther did, with the
"cogito" of Descartes, being more of an ontologist than Gunther. St.
Thomas says: "The first thing conceived by the intellect is being. Hence
being is the object of the intellect."[474] But Rosmini teaches[475] that
what is first conceived by the intellect is the beginning of being, which is
something divine, belonging to the divine nature; it is something divine not by
participation, but in the strict sense it "is an actuality that is not
distinct from the remainder of the divine actuality";[476] "it is
something of the Word."[477]
All Rosmini's theories are deduced from this principle.
1) He seeks to prove the Trinity about the same way Gunther did, by
distinguishing in God between subjectivity, objectivity, and sanctity, or
between reality, ideality, and morality, inasmuch as these are three supreme
forms of the being, namely, subjective being, objective being, and their union
by love.[478]
2) He denies the freedom of creation, as Gunther did.[479] He admits
generationism or traducianism, saying: "The human soul, by coming in
contact solely with its intuitive sentient principle, becomes a being, and by
this union that principle, which before was only sentient, becomes intelligent,
subsistent, and immortal."[480] Rosmini held that the will constitutes
human personality, by which everyone is responsible for and master of himself.
Hence Rosmini teaches: "In Christ's humanity, the human will was so rapt by
the Holy Spirit to adhere to the objective entity of the Word, that it gave up
completely to the Word its human control.... Hence the human will ceased to be
personal in Christ as man, and, although it is a person in other human beings,
in Christ as man it remained a nature."[481]
This theory is refuted both philosophically and theologically about the same
way as Gunther's.
Philosophically. It is false to say that the will constitutes the person in
human beings, for the will is attributed to an already ontologically established
person, such as Peter or Paul, and the will is this will, since in that it is
the will of this particular subject, by itself separately existing. Person is a
substance, whereas will is its accident, an inseparable accident, indeed, but a
predicamental accident, although it is not a predicable, which means that it is
not contingent.
Theologically. Rosmini's theory leads to Nestorianism, for the union it
admits is only a union of wills or a moral union, such as we find in the saints,
who would differ from Christ only according to the degree of their love for Him.
What results from the condemnation of these two theories?
It follows that merely phenomenalist or dynamistic notions of personality
cannot be reconciled with the Catholic doctrine of the Incarnation, as we showed
in another work.[482]
According to the empiric phenomenalism of Hume, Stuart Mill, and Taine, we
have knowledge only of phenomena or states of consciousness, but not of the
"ego" itself as substance. But conscious facts are united according to
the laws of association, and then personality is established by a dominating
state of consciousness. But if there be a psychological disturbance, as in
madness, some think that there are two personalities, for at times a person
considers himself a king, and at other times a servant.
The rational phenomenalism of Renouvier considers personality to be an a
priori form of our mind, which unites all that belongs to us. Our existence is
merely so far as it is represented.[483]
As for the dynamic evolutionism or philosophy of becoming (of such
philosophers as H. Bergson), person is neither an association of phenomena nor a
certain category of the mind, but it is a vital and free impulse, which
manifests itself in an unbroken series of divers states of consciousness.
It is evident, however, that the person of the Word incarnate, as conceived
by the Catholic Church, cannot be either a certain association of phenomena or a
certain category of the mind, or a vital and free impulse; all these pertain to
the finite and hence created order, and cannot constitute the uncreated
personality of the Word incarnate.
But in contrast to either empiric or rational phenomenalism, or the
philosophy of becoming, traditional philosophy may be called the philosophy of
being, inasmuch as the formal object of our intellect is neither an internal nor
an external phenomenon, nor a category of the mind, but it is the intelligible
being of sensible things. This is, as H. Bergson avows, the natural metaphysics
of human intelligence, or the conception of natural reason, or the sensus
communis, which develops by a gradual process from the confused state of
rudimentary knowledge to the clearly defined state of philosophic knowledge.
Gradually our intellect ascends from the knowledge of the being of sensible
things to the knowledge of the soul and of God, who is conceived as the First
Being or as the self-subsisting Being.
According to this philosophy of being, however, person is something more
profound than phenomena and their laws, either empiric or a priori, something of
even deeper significance than the becoming of being that underlies phenomena,
for it is a substance of a rational nature by itself separately existing, or an
intelligent and free individual subject, permanent in itself, by itself
operating, and hence conscious of itself and because of free will responsible
for its actions. Briefly, person is an intelligent and free subject. Hence the
aforesaid theories consider only the psychological or moral aspects of
personality, but not ontological personality, on which these aspects depend.
This ontological personality is that by which a person is a subject or a whole
by itself separately existing, intelligent and free.
As we said, a person enjoys a threefold independence, inasmuch as its being,
its understanding, and its will are not intrinsically dependent on matter. Thus
it is evident that ontological personality is the foundation of psychological
personality and of moral personality.
It is also apparent that those notes which constitute personality, namely, a
subject subsisting in itself, endowed with intelligence and freedom, are
absolutely simple perfections, which can be attributed analogically and in the
proper sense to God, whereas, on the contrary, merely phenomenal personality
cannot be attributed even analogically to Him, since God is absolutely above the
phenomenal order.
Various Scholastic Views About Personality
There are different views about ontological personality among the
Scholastics. They are radically divided: some admit and others do not admit a
real distinction between what is and its existence, a distinction that is
declared among the greater in the philosophy of St. Thomas, and which forms one
of the twenty-four theses approved by the Sacred Congregation of Studies in
1916.
Some say, in these days, that the first of these twenty-four propositions on
which the others depend, is not found in the works of St. Thomas, who admitted,
so they say, only logical composition of potentiality and act, but not real
composition in every created:[484]
On the contrary, St. Thomas said explicitly: "Everything that is in the
genus of substance is a real composite...; and its existence must be different
from itself.... Therefore everything that is directly in the predicament of
substance is composed at least of existence and that which exists."[485]
This means that there is a real distinction in the created suppositum between
that which exists and its existence. The suppositum is the whole, and its
existence is a contingent predicate.
Again he writes: "The act that is measured by aeviternity, the
aeviternal existence, differs indeed really from that whose act it
is";[486] which means that an angel's essence differs really from his
existence. On this point Father Norbert del Prado, O. P., has collected many
similar texts from St. Thomas in the famous book he wrote on this subject.[487]
In this work, he shows that the first truth by way of doctrinal judgment though
the highest of causes is that in God alone essence and existence are the same;
He alone can say: I am who am.
These truths presupposed, however, among Scholastics who deny a real
distinction between what is and its existence, and between essence and
existence, Scotus says that personality is something negative, namely, the
negation of the hypostatic union in a singular nature.[488] Suarez considers
personality to be a substantial mode that presupposes the existence of a
singular nature, and that renders it incommunicable.[489]
Among those Scholastics who admit a real distinction between existence and
what exists, there are especially three opinions. Cajetan and very many Thomists
say that personality is that by which a singular nature becomes immediately
capable of existence.[490]
Others, following Capreolus, say less clearly that personality is a singular
nature as constituted before it exists.[491] Lastly, Father Billot reduces
personality to existence that actuates the singular nature.[492]
[diagram page 145]
PERSONALITY
real distinction admitted
It is that by which a singular nature becomes what it is, or becomes
immediately capable of existence. (View of Cajetan and very many Thomists).
It is a singular nature as constituted before it exists (Capreolus)
It is existence that actuates a singular nature (Billot)
real distinction denied
It is a substantial mode that presupposes the existence of the substance
(Suarez)
It is something negative, the negation of the hypostatic union. (Scotus)
Criterion To Be Followed In The Examination Of These Opinions
All these theologians wish to retain the ontological validity of the common
notion of person, namely, an intelligent and free subject, and they wish to pass
methodically, although they do not all do so, by the light of revelation, from
this common notion of person to the more philosophical notion of person, which
is like the guiding star.
We said, however, that according to natural reason, a person is an
intelligent subject by itself separately existing, and this absolutely must be
maintained.
Moreover, it must be observed that there are assertions of natural reason
confirmed by revelation, and these must likewise be preserved intact. First of
all, there are affirmative judgments, in which those things that pertain to a
person are predicated of the person as a real subject of predication, such as:
Peter is a man, Peter is existing, Peter is acting. In these affirmative
propositions, however, the verb "is" affirms real identity between
subject and predicate, and postulates the same real subject underlying nature,
existence, and operation.
Lastly, the following truth must be retained. God alone is His existence, He
alone can say: "I am who am."[493] Peter is not his existence. This
statement means that the act of existence even when in act is included only in
God's essence, which is related to existence as A is to A, for God's essence is
the self-subsisting Being.[494] On the other hand, no created essence is its
existence, no created essence contains existence as an essential predicate, for
in such a case it would be self-existent and would not be created; but existence
befits it as a contingent predicate, inasmuch as it is possible for this essence
not to exist. Hence it is said of Michael the archangel, that he is not his
existence, just as a grain of sand is not its existence. These propositions are
commonly admitted by theologians as true, which means that they correspond to a
reality, and hence we must say, as the Thomists assert, that before the
consideration of our mind, Michael's essence or man's essence is not his
existence, which means that it is really distinct from its existence.[495]
Nevertheless we say that Michael is existing, Peter is existing. Thus the
verb "is" signifies real identity between subject and predicate
notwithstanding the real distinction between created essence and existence.
This principle is the criterion in the judgment of the above-mentioned
opinions, and it is manifest that it makes a considerable difference in the
notion of person, to whom essence and existence are attributed, according as a
real distinction between essence and existence is or is not admitted. The true
teaching about person has its foundation in this, that it is a requisite for the
verification of the following judgments: Peter is existing, but is not his
existence, whereas Christ is existing, and is His existence, just as "He is
truth and life."[496]
1) Opinion of Scotus. Scotus holds that a twofold negation is added to the
notion of person as applied to a singular human nature, namely, actual
dependence on the divine person, and aptitudinal dependence on this same divine
person.[497] Thus this humanity of ours is a person, because it is neither
naturally apt to be terminated, nor actually terminated by the divine
personality.
Scotus gives the following reasons for this conclusion:[498]
(1) Because then there would be some positive entity in the human nature that
would be incapable of assumption by the Word. (2) Because it would follow that
the human nature assumed by the Word would be wanting in some positive entity...
and thus Christ would not be universally a man.
Criticism. Cajetan[499] reproduces exactly these arguments of Scotus, and
examines them.[500] Capreolus had already examined them.[501] Later on John of
St. Thomas,[502] Zigliara,[503] and Billot[504] had discussed these arguments.
The Thomists show that this opinion of Scotus is contrary to the teaching of St.
Thomas, and that it does not preserve the common notion of person.
Fundamental argument. The constitutive element of that which is not perfect
in nature cannot be assigned to something negative. But as St. Thomas says,
"Person signifies what is most perfect in all nature, that is, a subsistent
individual of a rational nature."[505] Therefore its constitutive element
or its personality cannot be assigned to something negative. John of St. Thomas
explains this point well.
1) "Subsistence," he says, "is not the negation of dependence.
It is impossible for the independent not to be more perfect than the dependent.
But dependence is something positive. Therefore, a fortiori, independence in
that genus, cannot be a pure negation, although it is explained negatively, just
as simplicity is explained by indivision."[506]
Thus infinity in substance; although it is explained negatively, yet it is
something positive. Hence God's independence in being constitutes His greatest
perfection.[507] Therefore that by which anything is a subject by itself,
separately existing, cannot be a mere negation, for it is that which constitutes
a subject as the first subject of attribution. Likewise every negation has its
foundation in something positive, as Father Billot says against Scotus.
2) "Moreover," adds John of St. Thomas, "natural and proper
subsistence is not only opposed to the hypostatic union, but it is also opposed
to the existential mode of accident, or even of a part. And if the inherence of
accident is something positive and not a negative notion, a fortiori the
subsistence of first substance, to which second substance is attributed, must be
something positive."[508]
3) Then again, proper subsistence is something primo and per se natural,
because it constitutes something of the natural order. Therefore it cannot primo
and per se consist in the negation of the hypostatic union, which is
supernatural, although the negation may also include this latter, just as in
anything of the natural order we have the negation of the supernatural, although
things of the natural order are not primo and per se constituted as such by this
negation. Thus, according to the opinion of Scotus, either Heraclitus or Thales
would have been persons, because their nature was not hypostatically united to
any divine person.
4) Finally, in the case of the divine persons, there are in the strictest
sense of the terms, three subsistences and three personalities, which, inasmuch
as they are subsistences, denote positive realities, and not three negations.
And the subsistence of the Word substituting Its subsistence for that of the
human nature; but this union did not consist in anything negative, but in
something positive.
But there must be analogy between the divine personality and created
personality. "Nor is there something unbefitting resulting from this, as
Scotus would have, for the Word assumed whatever pertains to the human nature,
as a nature, although not whatever pertains to man as a suppositum." As St.
Thomas says, "It is a greater dignity to exist in something nobler than
oneself than to exist by oneself."[509]
5) Furthermore, it must be said against Scotus that this theory does not make
it clear how the following affirmative judgments can be true: Peter is a man,
Peter is existing; for the verb "is" expresses real identity between
subject and predicate. But this real identity cannot be established by something
negative. In other words: that by which anything is a who or a what, or a first
subject of attribution, cannot be something negative.
Some Scotists say that a subject is a singular nature.
Reply. The nature itself is not this subject, for as St. Thomas often says:
"nature, i. e., humanity, is that by which anything is such, i. e., a man;
it is not that which is."[510] Individuation alone is not that by which
anything is a who or a what, for matter constitutes this individuation in
Christ, namely, this humanity; yet it does not constitute a subject distinct
from the Word. Individuation is also found in the parts of a nature, for
example, in this flesh, these bones, but these parts do not have the
incommunicability that belongs properly to the suppositum.
Moreover, as we said, individuation derived from matter is something very low
in dignity, but subsistence and especially personality is something far nobler,
for it is that by which anything is a subject by itself separately existing and
operating. On the contrary, matter is not that which is, but that by which
anything is material.
6) Finally, Scotus denies a real distinction between created essence and
existence, and so we should have to say: Peter is his existence, just as we say:
God is His existence. But before the consideration of our mind it is true to
say: God is His existence, and there is no real distinction between the Deity
and His existence. Whereas, on the contrary, before any consideration of the
mind, it is true that Peter is not his existence, but has existence, just as
Peter cannot say: "I am the truth and the life," but only "I have
truth and life." Hence, before any consideration of the mind, there is a
certain distinction, not indeed spatial, but real or ontological between Peter's
essence and his existence. More briefly, that which truly is not its existence,
before any consideration of the mind is distinct from its existence, in some way
just as matter is not form, but is related to it as potency is to act, as
potency limiting to act determining. Act of itself is not limited, but is
limited by the potency in which it is received; so also existence is in various
ways limited in the essence of stones, plants, animals, and other things in
which it is received.
Wherefore we said that the true doctrine of person has its foundation in
this, that it postulates the truth of the following judgments: Peter is
existing, but is not existence; whereas Christ is existing and is His existence.
7) It follows from the thesis of Scotus that there are two existences in
Christ, which is contrary to the teaching of St. Thomas,[511] and then this
means that the humanity of Christ has its own ultimate actuality, namely, its
own existence. Thus, before its union with the Word, it is absolutely complete,
both substantially and subsistentially. Hence there is danger of Nestorianism in
this opinion, since the human nature in Christ appears to be a suppositum
distinct from the Word, with whom it can be united only accidentally. Scotus
does not wish to affirm this, but his principles ought to lead him to this
conclusion. There would be two supposita whose union would not have its
foundation in anything positive.[512]
2) Opinion of Suarez.[513] This opinion of Suarez is examined after that of
Scotus, since the two views are much alike, although Suarez departs from Scotus
inasmuch as he holds personality to consist in something positive, namely, in a
substantial mode, which in his opinion presupposes existence for the essence.
How does Suarez reach this conclusion?
Often in his eclecticism, Suarez searches for a via media between St. Thomas
and Scotus. In the present question, he sees, as the Thomists say, that
personality must consist in something positive, and then he says: this positive
element cannot be an accident, since person is a first substance. Therefore it
must be a substantial mode by which a singular nature is rendered
incommunicable, which is what Cajetan said. In Christ, he says, the human nature
is not a person, because the mode of personality is wanting to it, the mode of
the union taking its place.
But, on the other hand, Suarez holds, as Scotus does, that there is no real
distinction between created essence and existence. Hence, in his opinion, the
substantial mode which constitutes ontological personality, presupposes not only
essence or nature, but also existence.
Thus Suarez frequently in accordance with his eclecticism, as in this
question, refutes Scotus by St. Thomas, and St. Thomas by Scotus. But this via
media is most difficult to follow, since it is very difficult to maintain the
proper equilibrium or stability by this method, so that Suarez in the
development of his theses not infrequently fluctuates or oscillates between St.
Thomas and Scotus, not taking a firm stand for either view.
Criticism. The Thomists reply:
1) This opinion does not preserve what is fundamental in the truth of the
following proposition: Peter is not his own existence, for only God is His
existence. He alone can say: "I am who am,"[514] "I am the truth
and the life,"[515] and not merely "I have being, truth, and
life." But these judgments, acknowledged to be true by all theologians,
demand a real distinction between created essence and existence; for, that these
propositions be true even before any consideration of our mind, there must be a
real distinction between Peter and his existence, whereas, on the contrary, God
is really His existence, without even the least of real distinctions.
Hence the Sacred Congregation of Studies (1916), among the twenty-four
propositions of St. Thomas that it declared to be the greater, posited a real
distinction between created essence and existence. It is the third proposition
which reads: "All other beings (except God) which participate in being,
have a nature which is limited by existence, and consist of essence and
existence, as really distinct principles."[516]
Furthermore, the Thomists with John of St. Thomas[517] say that the
substantial mode, which is subsistence, does not presuppose existence, for it is
by subsistence that the suppositum is formally constituted as either a
suppositum or a person. But, as St. Thomas says: "Being is consequent upon
nature, not as upon that which has being, but upon that whereby a thing is such;
whereas it is consequent upon person or hypostasis, as upon that which has
being. Hence it has unity from the unity of the hypostasis, rather than duality
from the duality of the nature."[518] Peter is that which is, and first
comes the concept of person and personality before existence that is attributed
to the person when we say: Peter is existing, but is not his existence.
Hence personality terminates the nature and ultimately comes existence as
primarily befitting the suppositum, and through the intermediary of the
suppositum the nature. This is the constant teaching of St. Thomas.[519] There
is no existing subject unless the whole being is terminated and incommunicable
(e. g., Peter), to whom existence is applicable as a contingent predicate. Being
and becoming befit the suppositum, as St. Thomas shows,[520] for the terminus of
creation, or even of generation, is that which is, not that by which anything is
such as it is.
Therefore very many Thomists say with Cajetan that the substantial mode is
the terminus that causes the singular nature to be incommunicable and
terminated, just as the point terminates the line and does not continue it,[521]
nor is subsistence an unexplainable entity. But it must be something real that
constitutes this mode, not nature alone, however, nor existence. Therefore it
must be by what terminates the mode. Thus John of St. Thomas, following
Cajetan.[522]
3) The Thomists and Father Billot also say against Suarez:
Since the existence of substance is its ultimate actuality, as St. Thomas
often says, whatever accrues to substance already complete in its existence
accrues to it accidentally. But this mode consisting in personality or
subsistence, according to Suarez, accrues to substance after existence.
Therefore the mode is not substantial as he would have it, but accidental.
Hence, as already stated against the opinion of Scotus, the union of the Word
incarnate would thus be merely accidental, since each nature would have its own
existence, or its ultimate actuality.
3) Opinion of Father Billot. Father Billot, S. J.,[523] insists especially on
this, that St. Thomas maintains there is only one existence in Christ.[524]
Father Billot vigorously asserts this against Scotus and Suarez, because he
firmly defends against them the opinion of a real distinction between essence
and existence. On this point he is truly in agreement with St. Thomas and the
Thomists.
But on the other hand, Father Billot, always attacking Suarez, will not admit
a substantial mode even in Cajetan's sense, for-he says: "There is nothing
positive about the terminus itself except what it terminates, for all that the
point does which terminates a line is to deny its further extension, adding
absolutely nothing to it."[525]
Cajetan would reply by saying that the terminus itself is not indeed a new
thing or reality, but is a real mode, really and modally distinct from the thing
itself. Thus a line is made up of divisible parts and of indivisible points; a
point that terminates a line, or two lines that converge in it, is neither a
nonentity nor a part;[526] So the roundness of a metallic sphere is not nothing;
it is something really and modally distinct from substance, even from the
metallic quantity that it terminates; the quantity of this metal is not its
roundness, and it could have another shape.[527]
But since Father Billot refuses to admit this substantial mode as terminating
the nature, so that it is immediately capable of existing, he says that person
is a singular nature under its own existence, and he identifies subsistence or
personality with the existence of the substance.[528]
He quotes for his opinion especially the passage[529] in which St. Thomas
asserts, and in similar passages, that there is one being in Christ. This
assertion is indeed valid against Scotus and Suarez, but not against Cajetan,
for he also maintains that there is one being in Christ.
Father Billot,[530] who quotes Capreolus for his view, interprets him as
saying that person is a singular nature with its existence. Cajetan's answer
would be: Yes, it is a singular nature (terminated) with its existence, but it
must be declared terminated, for nature in itself is only that by which anything
is such as it is, it is not that which is.
The exact words of Capreolus on this point are: "1. The name suppositum
is affirmed of that individual which subsists by itself. 2. Understood formally,
as a mode, and then by suppositum is meant the composite that consists of the
individual with its suchness and its own subsistence."[531] It cannot be
inferred from this text that a person and the singular nature are identical, for
a person is what is, and the nature that by which something is; nor can it be
said that personality is existence, for personality is attributed to a person
already formally constituted as a person.
Criticism of Father Billot's opinion. It may be reduced to the following
arguments.
1) This opinion is not in harmony with the teaching of St. Thomas, who says:
"Being is consequent upon nature not as that which has being, but upon that
whereby a thing is; whereas it is consequent upon person or hypostasis as upon
that which has being."[532] Hence being or existence does not formally
constitute personality, because it is consequent upon a person already formally
constituted as such by personality. St. Thomas speaks similarly in the body of
the article just quoted.
2) Moreover, St. Thomas takes up this disputed point in discussing Christ's
unity of being,[533] by considering, as he himself says in the prologue to the
previous question,[534] the consequences of the union. Therefore he first
established his teaching on the hypostatic union,[535] and from this that there
is only one person in Christ. Then he goes on to deduce that there is one being
in Christ, inasmuch as being is immediately consequent not upon nature, but upon
person, which alone is what is.
Hence if Father Billot's opinion were the true teaching of St. Thomas, the
holy Doctor ought to have shown at the beginning of this treatise[536] that
there is one being in Christ, so as to make it clear that there is only one
person and only one personality in Christ. But he considers this point only
farther on,[537] which presupposes the solution of the problem concerning what
constitutes the hypostatic union.
3) The Complutenses Abbreviati[538] note that St. Thomas teaches that
"the angel is composed of existence and what is."[539] Thus Michael is
existing but is not his existence. Hence the holy Doctor teaches that existence
enters into composition not only with essence, but also with the suppositum. It
would not be so, however, if existence were the same as subsistence or
personality. Likewise, the principium quod of the theandric operations in Christ
is not common to the three divine persons.[540] But existence is common to the
three divine persons. Therefore the principium quod in Christ is not formally
constituted by existence.
4) St. Thomas says: "Existence does not pertain to the notion of a
created suppositum,"[541] which means that Peter is not his existence. But
subsistence pertains to the notion of suppositum, and personality to the notion
of person. Therefore they are not really the same as being or existence, at
least for St. Thomas.
Finally, St. Thomas[542] treats as distinct the following two questions,
namely, whether essence and existence are the same, and whether essence and
suppositum are the same. This would be superfluous if there were no real
distinction between existence and subsistence. Such is the excellent observation
of the Complutenses Abbreviati.
Moreover, it must be observed so as to avoid ambiguity, that subsistence does
not mean existence of substance, but subsistence is the abstract name that is
the correlative of the concrete name suppositum. Hence subsistence is to
suppositum as personality is to person, as existence is to exist, and as running
is to run.
Hence subsistence is not an abstract name that would correspond to the
concrete to subsist, but to the concrete that is called suppositum. But to avoid
this ambiguity, it is better to use the word personality than subsistence,
because it is evident that personality corresponds in the concrete to person,
and not as such to the word "subsist." Hence subsistence is to
suppositum as personality is to person, and as existence is to exist or to
being.
5) Father Billot's opinion leads to the denial of a real distinction between
essence and existence, a distinction that he firmly maintains nevertheless
against Scotus and Suarez. For it must be said that being which is not its
existence, is, before the consideration of the mind, really distinct from its
existence. But Peter's person, even his personality, is not his existence.
Therefore Peter's person, even his personality, is really distinct from his
existence.
The major of this argument is the principle from which we deduce that there
is a real distinction between essence and existence, and this Father Billot
accepts. But the minor is most certain, namely, that Peter's person is not his
existence, and therefore it differs from the person of the Word; moreover
Peter's personality is not his existence, because it formally constitutes
Peter's person, which is not his existence.
In other words, the denial of a real distinction between a created person,
constituted as such by his own personality and existence, means that a real
distinction between created essence and existence is without any foundation; for
a being that is not its own existence is, before the consideration of the mind,
really distinct from its existence. But Peter's person, formally constituted as
such by his personality, just as his essence, is really distinct from his
existence. Only God is His existence, and the truth of this assertion will be
most clearly seen in the beatific vision.
This point was more fully explained by quoting several texts of St.
Thomas,[543] and in the examination of the recent work of Father Charles Giacon,
S. J.[544]
Certain disciples of Father Billot advance the following objection. Peter is
not his nature. Yet there is no real distinction between him and his nature.
Therefore between him and his existence there is no real distinction.
Reply. I concede the major. I deny the minor and parity of agreement. For
Peter is not his nature, because his nature is an essential part of himself, and
even an essential part is not identified with the whole.
Thus I concede the major: Peter is not his nature. I deny the minor, for
there is a real distinction between Peter and his nature, just as there is a
real distinction between the real whole and its real part, and I deny also the
parity of argument, because Peter's nature is an essential part of himself, but
his existence is not. Thus when we say, "Peter is a man," man is an
essential predicate; on the contrary, when we say, "Peter is
existing," existing is a contingent predicate.
Father G. Mattiussi replies to this as follows: "St. Thomas says that
existence is not included in the notion of suppositum, inasmuch as existence is
not essential to any finite thing; but the suppositum can be considered in the
order of possible things, without its actually existing"[545]
To this it must be said: When I say that Peter is not his existence, I am not
concerned with Peter's possible existence, but with his actual existence; just
as when we say that the essence of a created thing really differs from its
existence, it is not a question of a possible essence, but of a real essence
that underlies the existence which it limits. For as Father Mattiussi himself
admits, the act of existing is multiplied and limited only by the real essence
and not the possible, in which it is received. Similarly, existence is a
contingent predicate of existing Peter, and not of possible Peter. Of existing
Peter we say that Peter is existing, but is not his existence; whereas of God,
we say that God exists and is His existence.
That being which is not its existence is really distinct from its existence.
But Peter's person, even his personality, is not his existence, which is a
contingent predicate. Therefore Peter's person, even his personality, is really
distinct from his existence, which is really distinct from his personality.
Father Mattiussi[546] quotes three texts of St. Thomas in proof that he, too,
was of the same opinion, namely, that subsistence is the existence of substance.
On the contrary, in these texts we read: "Subsistence is said of that whose
act is to subsist, just as essence is said of that whose act is to
exist."[547] On the contrary, these texts do not in any way contradict
Cajetan's opinion. Father Mattiussi does not search for that by which anything
is a what, or for that in which the concrete, this man differs from this
humanity. This man is what is, humanity that by which he is. They differ however
by that which constitutes man the first subject of attribution, for it is the
concrete that is constituted, whereas the form is in the subject. The
Complutenses Abbreviati present this argument in various forms and excellently,
showing that otherwise the proposition, man is existing, would be an eternally
true proposition, just as this proposition, man is a substance of a rational
nature. They insist on this, that subsistence or personality is intrinsic to the
notion of a created person, whereas existence accrues to it and is completely
outside the notion of person.[548] Hence Father Billot's opinion denies the
truth of the following proposition: Peter is not his existence.
6) Moreover, Father Billot's opinion denies the truth of another proposition,
-namely, that Peter is existing. For in every affirmative proposition, the word
"is" expresses real identity between subject and predicate. This real
identity, however, must have its foundation in some real positive thing, in that
by which anything is a what. But that by which anything is a what, is neither
even a singular nature nor existence. For nature is that by which anything is
such, for example, a man; existence is that by which anything is established
beyond nothing and its causes. And two elements related to each other as by
which, do not constitute a one that is a what, that is, a subject of itself
separately existing.[549]
7) Moreover, Father Billot overlooks the fact that in God there are three
personalities and one existence, not three relative existences but one esse in
that is substantial. St. Thomas says: "There is only one being in God and
three subsistencies."[550] Therefore personality is not being.[551]
8) Capreolus does not say that personality is formally constituted by
existence, but he says, supported by Cajetan on this point: "The being of
actual existence is called the act of the essence as whereby of the suppositum,
and the act of the suppositum as what exists....Existence thus pertains to the
notion of suppositum, not forming a part of the suppositum, nor is it included
in the essence of this latter, but is related to it by way of connotation and is
implied indirectly, which is about the equivalent of saying that the suppositum
is identical with the individual substance having existence. Such was the
opinion of St. Thomas, so I think."[552] Cajetan admits this. There is,
indeed, a more recent opinion that maintains person is the singular nature
itself underlying its existence.
Criticism. This does not explain whereby anything is properly what is, or the
first subject of attribution subsisting of itself, first substance. For the
singular nature, for example, this humanity, is not what is, but whereby anyone,
namely, Peter or Paul, is a man. Hence we say: Peter is not his humanity,
because the whole is not its part, it is not identical with its part, but
includes other things besides; thus Peter includes his nature, existence, and
accidents. Hence we seek that whereby a person is formally constituted the first
subject of attribution, not attributable to another subject; whereas, on the
contrary, this humanity is attributed to each human being.
Moreover, this humanity immediately is not capable of the act of existing,
for it is not what exists. We are seeking the subject of this singular nature,
of its existence and accidents.[553]
Common opinion among Thomists. It is Cajetan's opinion, which he
explains,[554] and very many Thomists follow.
Cajetan passes methodically from the commonly accepted definition of person,
namely, a subject of a rational nature, to the definition of personality. He
notes that the name personality signifies that whereby a person is constituted
the first subject that is of itself separately, so that it cannot be attributed
to another subject.
But that whereby anything is a subjective what, cannot be anything
accidental, or a permanent accident, such as the intellectual faculty, or the
free will, or a transitory accident, such as an act of conscience or even a free
act. It must be something substantial, as constituting the subject of
attribution.
But this substantial can be neither a singular nature that is an essential
part of this subject but not the subject itself, nor existence, which is a
contingent predicate of whatsoever created person, and hence does not formally
constitute it. Therefore personality is a substantial mode that terminates the
singular nature, so that it may become the immediate subject of existence, for
the subject is what is, and not the nature.
This substantial mode terminates the singular nature in some way as the point
terminates the line and makes of the line a complete whole; thus, when a line is
divided by a point into two lines, whichever of these, that before was in
potentia to be continued, now becomes a line in act, becomes some whole in act,
by the very fact that it is terminated. Similarly, the line itself, for
instance, a circular line terminates the surface of a scroll. This is also the
case in the order of substances, for, when an animal of the lower order, a worm,
for instance, is divided in two, then we have two worms, two supposita; before
the division they were potentially two, now they are actually two.
Thus this humanity, which is in Christ, could be terminated in its own right,
and thus it would be a distinct suppositum, a human person. De facto, however,
it is terminated by the pre-existing personality of the Word, just as a line is
extended so that it remains one line and not two lines; or, better still, just
as two lines terminate in the same point at the apex of an angle.[555]
Cajetan's fundamental argument. It may be reduced to the following syllogism.
Something real and positive is required by which the created subject is what
is, which is against Scotus. But this cannot be either the singular nature,
which is related to the subject as whereby, or existence, which is a contingent
predicate of the created subject, which is against other opinions. Therefore
something else positive is required, namely, personality, which ultimately
disposes the singular nature for existence. It would indeed be repugnant if a
substantial mode accrued to substance already existing, for then it would be an
accident, which is against Suarez; but it would not be so if it accrued to
substance before it existed.
Cajetan's opinion is admitted by Francis Sylvester (Ferrariensis),[556] by
Bannez,[557] by John of St. Thomas, Gonet, Goudin, by Billuart,[558] by the
Salmanticenses, and by very many Thomists.
There are two proofs for this opinion. 1. It is proved on the authority of
St. Thomas; 2. it is proved from reason; 3. it explains satisfactorily the dogma
of the Incarnation; 4. it is defended against those who attack the opinion.
Proof from St. Thomas. Cajetan quotes four texts,[559]
a) "Being is consequent upon nature, not as upon that which has being,
but as upon that whereby a thing is; whereas it is consequent upon person or
hypostasis, as upon that which has being."[560] Therefore being does not
constitute personality but presupposes it, and as that which is really distinct
from the singular nature, which is not the what or suppositum, as is evident in
ourselves who have this flesh, these bones, and also in Christ who has this
humanity.
b) "Temporal nativity would cause a real temporal filiation in Christ if
there were in Him a subject capable of such filiation."[561] The subject
would be a human person, not a nature. On the contrary, the Word cannot acquire
a new relation, or an accident that is superadded to Him.
c) "If the human nature had not been assumed by a divine person, the
human nature would have had its own personality.... The divine person by His
union hindered the human nature from having its personality."[562]
d) "If the human personality had existed prior to the union... then it
would have ceased to exist by corruption."[563] And again: "I say that
essence is predicated of that whose act is to exist, subsistence of that whose
act is to subsist."[564] Therefore subsistence is not identical with
subsist. Finally St. Thomas says: "The form signified by the word 'person'
is not essence or nature, but personality."[565] But in God there are three
personalities and only one essence and one existence. Therefore personality is
not existence. St. Thomas likewise says: "The name 'person' is imposed by
the form personality, which means the reason for subsisting in such a
nature."[566]
Proof from reason. Cajetan's opinion has its foundation in the principle that
on the part of the object it is required that the commonly accepted definition
of person, namely, an intelligent and free subject, be true, and that these two
judgments are true: Peter is existing, but is not his existence.
Cajetan says: "If we all acknowledge this principle, in examining the
quiddity of the thing signified, why turn away from what is commonly
admitted?"[567] In other words, in the transition from the nominal
definition to the real definition, why depart from the nominal definition of
person, which is, what exists separately of itself in a rational nature? The
quiddity of the name contains confusedly the quiddity of the thing, and the
explicit definition must not be the negation of the implicit or nominal
definition, but must be in conformity with it, otherwise philosophical reason
disagrees with the findings of natural reason.
Moreover, for the verification of the two above-mentioned judgments (Peter is
existing, but is not his existence), there must be a foundation for the real
identity between subject and predicate, which is affirmed in the first judgment,
yet such that there is not identity, which is rightly so denied in the second
judgment. But this foundation, must be something positive, real, which is
substantial and not accidental, which is not existence, however, for this is a
contingent predicate of Peter, or nature, which is related as whereby and as an
essential part of this subject. It must formally be that whereby anything is a
what or a real subject of these divers predications.
Therefore a terminus is required or a mode that is substantial and not
accidental. This argument, namely, that on the part of the object there is
required real identity between subject and predicate in the affirmative
judgment, Peter is existing, is confirmed by several theologians.[568]
The search or hunt for the definition of personality can be more briefly set
forth, by beginning with the nominal definition, and by comparing personality
with those things unlike it, namely, with negations and accidents, and with
those things like it and related to it, such as with the singular nature and
with existing substance, as also by separating in this way those things that do
not pertain to the genus of substance to which person belongs.
1) Personality is not anything negative, but is something positive, because
it formally constitutes person, which is something positive.
2) Personality is not anything positive that is accidental, because person is
a substance. Thus consciousness of self, liberty, or dominion of oneself cannot
constitute ontological personality.
3) Personality is not the singular nature itself, because the singular nature
is not what is, but that whereby anything is constituted in a certain species.
If personality were the singular nature itself, then in Christ there would be
two personalities, and in God there would be only one person.
4) Personality is not existence itself that actuates the nature, because
existence is a contingent predicate of a created person, and it comes to the
person already formally constituted as having existence. Peter is not his
existence, but only has existence. Peter exists contingently, whereas Peter
necessarily is Peter, and, by virtue of the principle of identity, can be only
Peter.
5) Personality is therefore that whereby the singular nature becomes
immediately capable of existence, and thus the subjective what is really
constituted.
This is the commonly accepted opinion among Thomists, and this real
definition of personality corresponds to the nominal definition, that
personality is that whereby any intelligent subject is a person, just as
existence is that whereby a subject exists. This latter assertion is almost
frankly admitted by all, and in a confused manner implies that personality is
not the same as a person's existence.
3) Finally, Cajetan's opinion very well explains the dogma of the
Incarnation.
1) It explains that there is one person in Christ, because it posits in Him
two natures, indeed, but only one subsistence or personality, and only one
existence, which follows the one and only person in Christ.
2) It explains why the councils call this union subsistential or hypostatic,
and not existential or natural. It is not called an existential union, but a
hypostatic union, which means a union that is according to subsistence or
personality, which means that whereby anything is a what, or a terminated whole,
of itself separately existing.
Moreover, as St. Thomas says, "the three persons in God have only one
being."[569] Therefore St. Thomas is of the opinion that personality or
subsistence is not being or existence, nor is it the singular nature, which is
related to the suppositum as whereby and as an essential part. Therefore
personality is a substantial mode by which a singular nature is made immediately
possible of receiving existence.
The truth of this doctrine is to be seen in the instinct of
self-preservation. Now, for instance, every suppositum whether mineral,
vegetable, or animal seeks to retain what it possesses. Similarly the human
person seeks to retain his nature, body and soul, his existence, his faculties,
his integral parts, his operations; he seeks to retain all he possesses. It is
not his individualized nature that possesses all these things, but his very
person considered as the first subject of attribution, his very "ego."
What has been said also clearly shows the sublimity of Christ's personality;
for He has not a human personality, and therefore all that pertains to His human
nature is under the dominion of the Word incarnate. It is the person of the Son
of God who possesses all these things, and therefore nowhere in creation has
there been such a perfect illustration of God's supreme dominion both in the
past and in present times, as in the case of Christ's most holy humanity.
The Complutenses Abbreviati give a good explanation of this doctrine in their
philosophical works. It is fitting here to quote their proofs. They remark:
"It must be said that there is a real distinction between subsistence and
existence. Such is the teaching of St. Thomas, for he says: 'Being is consequent
upon nature, not as upon that which has being, but upon that whereby a thing is;
whereas it is consequent upon person or hypostasis, as upon that which has
being.’[570] But that which is consequent upon another is really distinct from
it.... He also says: 'An angel is composed of existence and what is,’[571] and
he expounds this doctrine here remarkably well by saying that existence forms a
composite not only with the essence of a thing, but also with its suppositum;
but if it were really identical with the subsistence of a thing, it could not
enter into composition with the suppositum, but we should have to say that it
formally constitutes the suppositum. Then in another work, he says: 'Existence
does not pertain to the notion of suppositum,’[572] but subsistence belongs to
the notion of suppositum, and even formally constitutes it as such....
"Finally, the holy Doctor, in discussing various questions, asks whether
essence and existence are identical in created things, and also whether the
essence and suppositum are the same.[573] This would be superfluous if existence
and subsistence are not really distinct....
"The second proof for this thesis is founded on an argument taken from
St. Thomas,[574] which may be presented as follows: Act is really distinct from
the real subject in which it is received; but the suppositum is the real
susceptive subject of existence. Therefore the suppositum is really distinct
from its existence. This second consequence is a legitimate inference from the
first consequence; for it is by subsistence that the suppositum is formally
constituted. Hence if existence really differs from the suppositum, and is
received in this latter, it must presuppose subsistence as a reality, and be
really distinct from this latter. The minor is clarified: because that receives
as what existence, which comes into being as what and operates as what; for
becoming is ordered to being, and being to operation; but to come into being as
what, and to operate as what belongs properly to the suppositum, which is the
common teaching of scholastic theologians and philosophers. Therefore the
suppositum really is the recipient as what of existence.
"The third proof for this assertion made above is taken from the
previously quoted argument of St. Thomas,[575] and is substantially as follows:
That which belongs intrinsically to the notion of suppositum is really distinct
from that which accrues to it and is completely superfluous to the proper notion
of suppositum; but subsistence belongs intrinsically to the notion of
suppositum, whereas existence accrues to it and is not at all included in its
proper notion. Therefore existence is really distinct from subsistence. The
major and the consequence are evident. But the first part of the minor is
sufficiently clear, ... and the Complutenses give a brief proof and conclude
that this is an eternal verity, namely, the suppositum is a subsisting substance
and incapable of being attributed to another.... The second part of the minor is
expounded as follows: Existence does not apply necessarily and essentially to
the suppositum, otherwise this proposition, the suppositum exists, would be an
eternal truth, which is absurd. Therefore existence is an accidental attribute
of the suppositum, and is not included in its proper notion.
"The first confirmation of these proofs is that the suppositum is
identical with the first substance that is directly assignable among the
predicamentals; but the aforesaid substance is not constituted a reality by
existence, inasmuch as all things placed among the predicamentals prescind from
the notion of existence....
"The second confirmation is that existence and subsistence are lacking
in every principle of identity. Therefore they are not really the same. The
antecedent is proved first of all because existence does not pertain to the
notion of subsistence; otherwise anything of which subsistence is predicated
would also require existence to be predicated of it. Consequently, just as this
proposition, man is subsisting, is eternally true, so also this proposition, man
is existing, would be eternally true, which nobody would concede. Again,
existence does not enter into the concept of any third object by which it would
be identified with subsistence: for no third object can be thought of, except
the suppositum, whose concept, however, does not include the notion of
existence, as we have just seen. Finally, existence and subsistence do not
originate from the same form."[576] Such are the splendid comments of the
Complutenses, who preserve absolutely intact, therefore, the interpretation of
St. Thomas offered by Cajetan.
Solution Of Objections Against Cajetan's Opinion
First objection. In a certain work we read: "The necessity of this
substantial mode is freely affirmed, namely, that an individualized substance be
immediately capable of existing separately; it is of the very notion of an
individualized and complete substance that it exist in itself and of
itself."[577]
Reply. Substance or individualized nature is not what exists, but whereby any
subject is such as it is, constituted in a certain species with its
individualizing conditions. What exists is not this humanity of Peter. Otherwise
this humanity of Christ would already be what is, and thus there would be two
supposita in Christ, or two persons. On the contrary, there is only one
suppositum in Christ, to whom the two natures are attributed.
Such is the common teaching of theologians in discussing the theandric acts
of Christ, and the infinite value of His merits and satisfaction. They say these
meritorious and satisfactory acts are of infinite value not because of the
principle from which they are elicited, namely, the human nature, its faculties
and infused virtues, but because of the subjective principle that elicits these
acts, that is, the divine suppositum or divine person.
Personality must therefore be a real, positive, and substantial thing,
distinct from the individualized nature and also from existence that is a
contingent predicate of the created person. This means that personality is
properly that whereby any intelligent and free subject is what is. Thus the
common teaching of St. Thomas is that, in any creature whatever, there is a
difference between what is and being.[578]
Second objection. On the part of substance, to subsist is to exist. But the
relation between subsistence and to subsist is the same as between existence and
to exist, with which latter it is identified. Therefore subsistence is the same
as existence.
Reply. I concede the major, inasmuch as subsistence is the fact of existence
attributed to the person, but not constituting the person, for the person is the
thing that de facto exists. Hence we concede the major, or let it pass without
comment.
I deny the minor; for the relation is not between subsistence and to subsist,
but between subsistence and the suppositum, which is the same as between
existence and to be or to exist; which means that it is a relation between the
abstract and the concrete, as between a race and running. This becomes clearer
if we substitute "personality" for "subsistence"; for the
relation is not between personality and subsistence, but between personality and
person, which is a relation between the abstract and the concrete. Hence the
relation is the same as that between existence and to exist, and between a race
and running. And thus there is a real distinction between personality or
subsistence and existence, or between to exist and to subsist, which de facto is
attributed to the suppositum as a contingent predicate.
St. Thomas admits this distinction; for he writes: "The relation between
life and to live is not the same as that between essence and to exist; but
rather as that between a race and to run, one of which signifies the act in the
abstract, and the other in the concrete."[579]
Thus there is a threefold order in the signification of both the abstract and
the concrete:
[diagram page 169]
abstract: essencehumanitypersonality or subsistenceexistence
concrete: beingmanperson (Peter) |to exist
As St. Thomas says: "The three persons in God have only one
being,"[580] and this latter is identified with the divine essence, which
is not really distinct from the divine persons, although there is a real
distinction between the persons.
Against Cajetan's argument other objections have been proposed in our times,
such as the following.
Objection. St. Thomas says: "Being and operation belong to the person by
reason of the nature, yet in a different manner. For being belongs to the very
constitution of the person, and in this respect it has the nature of a term,
that is, as ultimate actuality; consequently unity of person requires unity of
the complete and personal being. But operation is an effect of the person by
reason of the former nature. Hence plurality of operations is not incompatible
with personal unity."[581]
Reply. In this text St. Thomas is not inquiring into the formal constituent
of person, which has already been determined;[582] but why there are two
operations just as there are two natures, whereas there is one being. He replies
that "being belongs to the very constitution of the person,"[583]
namely, to the person constituted as a person, as to that which has being, as
St. Thomas said. For it is the person that immediately is, whereas operation,
which follows personal being, belongs to the person through the intermediary of
the nature and its faculties. Thus in Christ there are one being and two
operations, just as there are two natures. In this text St. Thomas is not
inquiring about the formal constituent of person, since this he had already
done,[584] and had no need to postpone the determination of this formal
constituent of person, when confronted by the doubt, which he proposed to
himself, namely, whether there is only one operation in Christ;[585] for
operation follows being, and what belongs to being must be considered before
what concerns operation.
Father Mattiussi, S. J.,[586] presents three texts from the works of St.
Thomas in proof that he taught the identity between subsistence and existence.
But the true gist of these texts is: "Subsistence is said of that whose act
is to subsist, as essence is said of that whose act is to exist."[587]
Therefore, as existence is really distinct from essence in which it is received,
so suppositum and subsistence that formally constitutes suppositum, is distinct
from existence.
Another objection. From two acts there does not result per se unity;
wherefore prime matter must be pure potency. But essence, subsistence, and
existence are three acts.[588] Therefore these three acts cannot result in per
se unity.
Reply. I distinguish the major. That there cannot result from two acts a
nature one per se, this I concede; that there cannot result a suppositum one per
se, this I deny. I concede the minor. Essence, subsistence, and existence are
three acts, yet so ordered that one is the terminus of the other. I distinguish
the conclusion. Therefore from these three acts there does not result a third
per se nature, this I concede; that there does not result a one per se
suppositum, this I deny. For when the rational nature is completed by
personality, it is constituted a person, to whom existence applies accidentally
or contingently. Aristotle distinguished between four modes of per se
predication:[589] (1) definition which shows that the nature is one per se; (2)
per se predicate that denotes a necessary property; (3) per se predication that
declares something is of itself subsisting or a suppositum, which means that it
is one per se as a subject, although it may be an essential part and have
accidental parts; (4) predication that denotes a cause that is per se, and not
per accidens. It must be noted that in a certain article of a Carmelite
periodical, personality is something relative and is only reduced to the
category of substance.[590] In reply to this, we say that the divine
personalities are indeed relative entities, that is, they are subsisting
relations, paternity, filiation, passive spiration, whose esse in (or
inexistence) is substantial. But either human personality or angelic personality
is not a relative entity, but an absolute entity; for it does not imply
reference to another person, as paternity does. It is predicated as belonging
indirectly to the category of substance, as a substantial mode, whereby an
individual nature becomes immediately capable of existence.
Conclusion. Thus in the opinion held by Cajetan there is a legitimate
transition from the commonly accepted definition of person, namely, that person
is the first subject of attribution in a rational nature, to the philosophical
notion of personality. Cajetan so very well says: "If all acknowledge this,
then why in scrutinizing the quiddity of the thing signified, do we turn away
from the common admission?"[591]
According to this common admission, person is that which exists separately of
itself in a rational nature, and personality is that whereby person is formally
constituted as a what of itself separately existing, to whom existence is
attributed contingently.
Hence the entire opinion of Cajetan reduces itself to what is required on the
part of the object, which is the verification of these two judgments admitted by
all theologians, namely, the person of Peter exists, but he is not his
existence. And just as no created essence is its existence, so no created
person, formally constituted as such, by its own personality, is his own
existence. Only God is His existence.
Doubt. Does Cajetan consider subsistence or personality to be the intrinsic
terminus of substance?
Reply. He certainly does, inasmuch as subsistence is the formal constituent
of first substance, or the suppositum, although it does not belong to the notion
of nature. Thus subsistence pertains to the substantial order. Father Hugon
correctly says: "The metaphysical foundation for this opinion is the
radical difference prevailing between what belongs to the existential order and
what belongs to the substantial order. This means that no created person is his
existence. Likewise the end of motion is what properly terminates it, but it is
no longer motion, which has ceased; so also it is subsistence that terminates
the nature, but is not the nature; however, it constitutes the first substance,
or suppositum. No created person, whether understood denominatively as a
singular nature, or formally, that is, with personality, is its existence. The
second article of St. Thomas may now be read again, so that this doctrine may be
more clearly understood."[592]
Recapitulation. The principal argument in this opinion that is held by very
many Thomists is reduced to the following conclusion, as stated above. Something
real and positive is required whereby a created and existing subject is what is,
which is against Scotus. But this something cannot be either the singular
nature, which is related to the subject as constituting it in its species, or
existence, which is a contingent predicate of the created subject, which is
against other opinions. Therefore some other positive entity is required,
namely, personality, which is the ultimate disposition of a singular nature for
existence. A substantial mode that would accrue to substance already existing
would, indeed, be a contradiction in terms, for it would thus be an accident,
which is against Suarez; but there would be no contradiction if it came to
substance before it existed.
Third Article: Whether The Union Of The Word Incarnate Took Place In The
Suppositum Or Hypostasis
The meaning of the title is: whether the union of the Word incarnate so took
place that in Christ there is one suppositum, only one hypostasis..
The answer is in the affirmative, and it is of faith. The Council of Ephesus
declares that "the union is subsistential."[593] But some heretics
said that there is one person but two supposita.
St. Thomas refutes this heresy by three arguments.
1) He points out that, by the addition of the note of person to the
hypostasis, the nature becomes determinate and rational.
2) If it be said that "what person adds to the hypostasis is a
dignity," then the union would be according to a certain dignity, or it
would be a moral union, as Nestorius contended.
3) If there were two supposita in Christ, then to one of these what pertains
to God would be attributed, and to the other what pertains to man. This would
result in the severance of the subsistential union.[594]
Fourth Article: Whether After The Incarnation The Person Or Hypostasis Is
Composite
State of the question. Some deny that the person of Christ is composite, such
as St. Bonaventure, Durandus, Scotus; and this for reasons posited by St. Thomas
in his objections at the beginning of this article. He points out: (1) that the
person of Christ is the very person of the Word, who is in Himself most simple,
and in no way composite. (2) Moreover, the divine nature cannot be a part in
Christ, because the part is always less perfect than the whole. (3) It cannot be
said that Christ is composed of two natures, because thus there would be a
composite nature, just as the human nature is composed of soul and body, and
then the Deity would be to the composite as form, and therefore as part. This
would be Monophysitism.
Reply. The person of Christ is one, but is composed of two natures.
First proof. It rests on the authority of St. Damascene, who is quoted in the
counterargument of this article. Moreover, the Second Council of Constantinople
corroborates the conclusion stated above, saying: "The Holy Church of
God... confesses that the union of the Word of God with the flesh was by way of
composition, which means that it was subsistential."[595]
Second proof. The argument is from reason, and there are two parts to it.
a) The person of Christ in itself is an absolutely simple uncreated being,
even as the nature of the Word is, and therefore in itself is in no way
composite. Thus Christ is one subsisting being.
b) Nevertheless, this person of Christ subsists in two natures, and thus He
can and must be said to be a composite of two natures.
First objection. The reply is evident from the argumentative part of the
article.
Reply to second objection. The divine nature, however, is not to be
considered as a part of this composite. For "this composition of a person
from natures is not so called on account of parts, but by reason of number, even
as that in which two things concur may be said to be composed of them."
Hence Christ is not a composite of parts, but of extremes that are united. St.
Thomas explains this point more fully elsewhere,[596] remarking that composition
may be viewed in two ways.
1) It may be considered as the union of parts which causes and results in the
totality of the being, and this union implies imperfection, inasmuch as the part
is an incomplete being, not so perfect as the whole, and inasmuch as the being
of the whole is dependent on its parts and thus is caused.
2) Composition may be viewed as the union of extremes in some third entity
that communicates being to the extremes. The extreme, however, prescinds from
the notion whether it be a complete or incomplete being. Thus, for example,
seeing terminates in the thing seen without resulting in any imperfection on the
part of the object seen, on which the seeing depends, but which does not depend
on the seeing. Thus the intellect of the blessed is united to God who is clearly
seen, without involving any imperfection on the part of God. There is something
similar to this in the hypostatic union, but in the order of being and not
merely of operation, since the human nature is terminated by the absolutely
simple person of the divine Word, without involving any imperfection on the part
of the divine person. The person of the Word is related to the human nature not
as informing act, but as terminating act.
First corollary. Christ is also a composite of the person of the Word and the
human nature, because He consists of these really distinct and united. Yet it
cannot be said that Christ is a creature, because created being applies to the
person, who is what is. The person of Christ, however, is uncreated, but in Him
the human nature is something created.
Second corollary. Although Christ is thus composite, He is not more perfect
than the Word not made flesh in this composition, because the Word is the
infinite extreme eminently containing the perfection of the human nature.
In contrast to this, God is not said to be a composite of persons and nature,
because the divine persons, although united in the same nature, are not united
among one another, but are rather in opposition, not being united with the
nature, because They are simply identical with the nature. Thus They are not
really distinct from the nature, but They are really distinct from one another
by a relation of opposition.
Fifth Article: Whether In Christ There Is Any Union Of Soul And Body
State of the question. If so, then it seems that there would be in Christ a
human person, for the human person is the result of the union of the soul with
the body.
Reply. The answer is in the affirmative and it is of faith.[597] But the
human nature thus being a composite has not its own personality.
Sixth Article: Whether The Human Nature Was United To The Word Of God
Accidentally
This article is both a recapitulation of the preceding articles and the
completion of their definition of the hypostatic union.
State of the question. It seems that this union is accidental, for whatever
accrues to a being after it is complete as an entity, accrues to it
accidentally. Whatever does not pertain to the essence of anything, is its
accident. But the human nature does not pertain to the divine nature of the Son
of God. Therefore the union of the human nature with the divine nature is
accidental.
Reply. It is given about the end of the argumentative part of the article.
St. Thomas says: "The Catholic faith, holding an intermediate position
between Monophysitism and Nestorianism, does not affirm that the union of God
and man took place in the essence or nature, nor yet in something accidental,
but midway, in a subsistence or hypostasis."[598]
1) Indirect proof. It is drawn from the counterargument, and is expressed by
the following argument. Whatever is predicated accidentally, is not predicated
substantially, but quantitatively or qualitatively. But the humanity of Christ
is not predicated quantitatively or qualitatively. Therefore it is not
predicated accidentally.
2) Direct proof. It is founded on the arguments defining the faith on this
point, which declare that the union is not natural, which is against Eutyches,
nor accidental, which is against Nestorius, but is subsistential. The two
opinions quoted by the Master of the Sentences in this article may be included
in the error of Nestorius. The argument may be reduced to the following
syllogism.
The union of substantial things that form the composite of one person is not
accidental. But such is the union of the Word incarnate. Therefore the union is
in no way accidental, but substantial, which means that it is subsistential.
This implies more than the expression "in the person," for even
accidents are in the person to whom they are attributed.[599] To understand this
article it must be noted that there are four modes of per se predication, and
that personal union means more than union in the person, as Cajetan
observes.[600]
There are four modes of per se and not per accidens predication, as Aristotle
explains.[601] St. Thomas says in his commentary on Aristotle: In the first mode
of per se predication, definition is predicated of the subject, for instance,
man is per se or essentially a rational animal.
In the second mode of per se predication a property is predicated of the
subject, for instance, man is risible, or has the power of laughing, which
manifests itself on his countenance as an indication of intelligence, and this
power does not belong either to the angel or to the irrational animal.
The third mode of per se predication is more the mode that pertains to
existence, and not to predication, since it signifies something that exists in
itself and not in another as in a subject. Thus first substance, for example,
Peter, is per se or in himself existing, in opposition to accident, and to
second substance, for example to humanity, which is predicated of Peter and is
in him.
The fourth mode of per se predication is according to the notion of
causality, when the proper effect is attributed to its proper cause. Thus the
doctor restores to health, that is, he does this inasmuch as he is a doctor;
strangling kills, light illumines. Contrary to this, it is accidental that the
doctor sings.
It is evident that the humanity is united with the Word neither in the first
mode, nor in the second mode, nor in the fourth mode, but in the third mode,
inasmuch as it exists in the Word not per accidens, but per se,[602] and as
Cajetan says,[603] it is united with the Word not only as in the person or in
the hypostasis, as accidents are so united with substance, but it is united with
the Word hypostatically, which means substantially, according to the third mode
of predication.
Solution of difficulties. Durandus holds that this union is not
predicamentally or physically accidental, because humanity belongs to the
predicamental substance, and not to any of the others. But the union is
predicably or logically accidental, because the predicable accident is defined
as that which can be either present or absent from its subject of predication,
without the corruption of this latter. But the humanity can be either present or
absent from the Word, which remains unchanged.
The principal objections in scholastic form are the following.
First objection. What accrues to anything after the completion of its being,
accrues to it accidentally. But the human nature accrues to the Word after the
completion of the former as a being. Therefore the human nature is united with
the Word accidentally.
Reply. I distinguish the major: if it is not drawn into the same personal
being, I concede the major; otherwise I deny it. I contradistinguish the minor:
that the human nature is drawn into the personal being of the Word,[604] this I
concede; that it is not, this I deny.
But I insist. Even though it is drawn into the same personal being, it is
united accidentally. The accident that accrues to any subject is drawn into the
same being of the subject. But the accident is united with this subject.
Therefore the human nature is united with the Word accidentally.
Reply. I distinguish the major: that it is drawn into the same being of the
suppositum, this I deny; improperly so, I concede; for it has its own being, but
inheres in a subject. It belongs to the being of accident to inhere. I concede
the minor. I distinguish the conclusion: if the human nature were an accident
inhering in the Word, then I concede the conclusion; otherwise I deny it.
The human nature is truly united with the Word not only in the person as
accidents are, but also substantially inasmuch as it is terminated by the
personality of the Word, and has one personal being or one existence with it,
just as body and soul are so united.
Again I insist. Nevertheless the union is accidental at least predicably, if
not predicamentally as Durandus says.
What is not predicated of a subject per se is a predicable accident.
But the human nature is not predicated per se of the Word.
Therefore the human nature is united with the Word as a predicable accident.
Reply. I distinguish the major; what is in no way predicated per se, I
concede; what is at least predicated per se in the third mode or per se as
subsisting, I deny. I contradistinguish the minor, and I deny the consequent and
consequence. The humanity of Christ does not indeed belong to the definition of
the Word or of the Second Person of the Trinity, nor is it a property of the
Word, but the Word subsists in the human nature, and the human nature in the
Word.
Finally I insist. Nevertheless, what can be either absent or present, the
subject remaining intact, is united with the subject accidentally. But the human
nature can be absent from the Word, which remains intact. Therefore the human
nature is united with the Word accidentally.
Reply. I distinguish the major: the subject remaining intact considered as a
composite, this I concede; the subject considered as a mere subsisting form, I
deny. I contradistinguish the minor: the human nature can be absent, the Word
remaining intact considered in Himself, as the eternal person, I concede;
considered as the Word incarnate, I deny.
Thus the body is not united accidentally with the soul, and yet the body can
be separated from the soul, this latter continuing to exist, though the
composite ceases as such. In other words, there can be no separation of the body
from the soul unless there is a cessation of the composite, and so the union is
per se and not per accidens. Similarly the humanity is united with the Word,
although the union between the two is not essential.
Corollary. Hence the hypostatic union differs from an essential union that
would result in one sole composite nature, such as the union between body and
soul. It also differs from an accidental union. It is, however, an absolutely
unique union of its kind, one that is subsistential or hypostatic, or a formally
personal union, and not only a material union in the person, for even accidents,
which accrue to man, are united to him materially in the person, but not
formally as constituting the person.
Therefore Christ's human nature in the Word is neither a predicamental
accident, as, for example, the intellectual faculty is in the rational soul or
in the angel, nor a predicable or contingent accident as, for example, a certain
person may be sitting instead of standing.
Thus is determined the exact meaning of this conciliar expression, namely,
"hypostatic union." We are not concerned here with a theological
conclusion deduced from the dogma, but with a metaphysical explanation of the
dogma. The hypostatic union is not a new truth concerning the Incarnation, but
it is a metaphysical explanation of this revealed truth.
Seventh Article: Whether The Union Of The Divine Nature And The Human Is
Something Created
State of the question. It seems that the union is not anything created, and
this for the following reasons.
1) Because this union is in God, for it is God united to the human nature,
and there can be nothing created in God.
2) The terminus of the union is the uncreated person of the Word. Therefore
the union itself is not anything created.
This question presents considerable difficulty, because there are three
possible meanings to the word "union." It may be understood: (1) as
unitive action; (2) as rather the passive union of some things into one; (3) as
a relation that follows from this union.
1) If we consider the union as meaning the act of uniting the human nature
with the Word, then certainly the action is uncreated, and it is common to the
whole Trinity, for the Father and the Holy Ghost united Christ's human nature
with the Word, although they did not assume it.[605] This action common to the
whole Trinity, inasmuch as it is dependent on the omnipotence that is common to
the three Persons, is formally immanent, but virtually transitive, and hence is
certainly uncreated.
2) If we consider the union as implying a real relation of dependence on the
part of Christ's human nature on the Word, St. Thomas clearly shows it to be
something created, and so it presents no difficulty.
3) But if we consider the union rather as denoting a passive combination of
Christ's humanity with the Word, then theologians dispute whether it is
something real and created that is distinct from the human nature. Scotus,
Suarez, Vasquez, and certain Thomists, such as the Salmanticenses and Godoy, as
also Father de la Taille in recent times, affirm this view.[606] But Scotus
would have it to be something relative that is an extrinsic adjunct, whereas
others say it is a substantial mode and the foundation of the real relation of
which St. Thomas speaks.
On the contrary, Cajetan and several other Thomists, such as Billuart and
Father Billot, deny that the union is something created, remarking that there is
no substantial mode in this case, one that is a quasi-intermediate connection
formally uniting the human nature with the Word, so that it is impossible to
detect any other formal union distinct from the extremes united, except the
relation itself that follows from the passive change effected in the human
nature by the action of the Word uniting to Himself. So says Billuart. Thus
passive creation is merely a real relation of dependence, nothing else, and it
has its foundation in the being of a creature, inasmuch as a creature is not its
own existence. This seems to be the true solution of the difficulty.[607] Let us
see what St. Thomas says.
In the counterargument he observes that this union began in time, therefore
it is something created. In the body of the article, however, he determines what
this something created formally is. St. Thomas speaks only of relation here. His
argument is reduced to the following syllogism.
Every relation between God and the creature is real in the creature and
logical in God. But the relation about which we speak is a certain relation of
Christ's humanity to the Word. Therefore this union is in Christ's humanity as
something real, and created, namely, a real relation of dependence on the Word
assuming this nature, just as creation is a real relation of dependence of the
creature on the Creator.[608]
But what is the foundation for this relation? St. Thomas says in the body of
this article: "By the change effected in the creature such a relation is
brought into being," that is, this foundation is passion that corresponds
to the unitive action. Whether this passion is really distinct from the human
nature passively assumed, is a disputed point among the above-mentioned
theologians.
Let us see whether the replies to the objections define more clearly the
nature of this union.
Reply to first objection. It declares that this union is not anything real in
God.
Reply to second objection. It states that this union is something real and
created in the human nature. It is not apparent from this reply that the union
is anything more than a real relation.
Did St. Thomas speak more explicitly on this point elsewhere? He certainly
did; for in another of his commentaries he says: "We must know that in the
union of the human nature with the divine there can be nothing intervening that
is the formal cause of the union with which the human nature is joined before it
is united with the person. For, just as there can be no intervening entity
between matter and form that would be in the matter prior to the substantial
form, otherwise accidental existence would be prior to substantial existence,
which is impossible; so also between the nature and the suppositum there can be
nothing intervening in the above said mode."[609] Thus there is nothing
intervening between the Word and the humanity. Hence union in the passive sense
or created is nothing else but a real relation of the human nature that is
dependent on the Word as a person, just as creation in the passive sense is
nothing else but a real relation of dependence of the creature on the Creator.
Which is the more probable opinion? An intervening substantial mode between
the Word and the human nature, as Cajetan, Billuart and others show, appears to
be inadmissible.
Proof. The Word is united with the human nature by that whereby the Word
terminates and maintains it. But the Word by Himself or solely by his
personality, every formal connection excluded, terminates and sustains the human
nature. Therefore the Word Himself or His personality is united with the human
nature.
The union of the Word with the human nature means nothing else but the
termination of this latter; thus analogically, in the order of operation, God
clearly seen immediately terminates the beatific vision.
First confirmation. Created subsistence is by itself immediately united with
created nature. Therefore a fortiori uncreated subsistence is so united, as it
is most actual in the notion of terminating.
Second confirmation. Likewise existence, as the ultimate actuality, by itself
immediately actuates the created suppositum; similarly personality by itself
immediately is united with created nature, or terminates it; so also one and the
same point immediately terminates two lines that meet in it, which is a very
faint image of the union of the two natures in the Word.
Doubt. Was the human nature changed in being assumed by the Word?
Reply. In the strictest sense of the term, it was not, because it did not
exist before it was assumed, inasmuch as it did not have its own personality,
but was assumed by another personality. A nature must be first produced before
it can be assumed.
Thus St. Thomas shows[610] that creation is not a change except as we
conceive it, for he says: "Change means that the same something should be
different now from what it was previously."[611] But this cannot be either
in creation, or even in the assumption of Christ's humanity, which did not exist
before its assumption. And St. Thomas says: "When motion is removed from
action and passion, only relation remains."[612] Hence creation in the
passive sense is nothing but a real relation of dependence that has its
foundation in created substantial being. Similarly, in the hypostatic union, the
soul of Christ is created as dependent on the Word as a person. If other authors
wish to affirm that it is something else, namely, a special substantial mode,
let them prove its existence. St. Thomas never spoke about this special mode.
What is therefore the foundation of the relation in the hypostatic union? It
is Christ's humanity, inasmuch as it is not terminated by its own created
personality, and so it can be terminated and possessed by the Word.
Eighth Article: Whether Union Is The Same As Assumption
First conclusion. There is a distinction between union as implying a
relation, and assumption that implies an action; for this relation is in
Christ's humanity and follows the active assumption, which is the foundation for
this relation, just as passive generation is the foundation of the relation of
filiation.
Second conclusion. Hence assumption implies becoming, whereas union implies
having become. Thus we say of what took place, that the Word assumed the human
nature, and even now that it is united with the Word.
Third conclusion. Whereas union implies a relation of quasi-equivalence, and
both the divine nature and the human nature are declared united; but assumption,
which is the action of the one assuming, does not designate the divine nature,
but the agent assuming and the human nature that is assumed.
Fourth conclusion. Who unites and who assumes are not the same absolutely,
for only the Son of God assumed the human nature, but the Father and the Holy
Spirit are said to unite, but not to assume. For union as an action implies only
the conjunction of extremes, whereas assumption as an action means the same as
the taking to oneself, inasmuch as He who assumes unites to Himself personally,
and is the end of the terminating action and not merely its beginning. Every
external action of God is common to the three persons, just as omnipotence is,
from which action derives its power; but one person, such as the person of the
Word, can be separately the terminus of some real relation.[613]
Ninth Article: Whether The Union Of The Two Natures In Christ Is The Greatest
Of Unions
State of the question. St. Thomas, as Cajetan remarks, considers union here
not so much as a relation, but as it is a substantial and immediate conjunction
of the two natures in the person of the Word. And the conjunction is the
foundation of the above-mentioned relation. There are difficulties, as stated in
the beginning of this article.
1) Unity that is the principle of number, seems to be a greater unity than
Christ.
2) It seems that this union is not the greatest, because the divine and human
natures are infinitely apart, and the greater the distance between the extremes
that are united, the less is the union.
3) It seems that the union between body and soul is greater, because from it
there results what is one not only in person, but also in nature.
The counterargument presents a contrary objection, as if the union of the
Incarnation were greater than the unity of the divine essence.
Reply. The hypostatic union is the greatest of unions, not on the part of the
things united, but on the part of the person in whom they are united.
First part. It is proved in the body of this article, and in the reply to the
second objection as follows: The greater the distance between the extremes
united, the less is the union in this respect. But the divine and human natures,
which are the extremes of this union, are infinitely apart. Therefore the union
of the divine and the human natures is the least in this respect.
Second part. It is proved as follows: On the part of the medium in which the
extremes are united, so much the greater is the union as this medium is in more
one and simple, and more intimately united with the extremes. But the medium in
this union, namely, the person of the Word, is most simple in Himself, and
really identical with the divine nature, and substantially united with the human
nature, so that the person of the Word imparts to the human nature both
subsistence and existence.[614] Therefore this union, on the part of the medium
in which it took place, is the greatest of created unions.
This same principle serves as the means of illustrating the mystical body of
Christ. Although the members of His mystical body live far apart from one
another in most distant climes, yet they are most closely united both in Christ
and in the Holy Spirit.
Thus it is that sometimes two saintly persons living far apart according to
their nationality, are more intimately united in Christ than with their fellow
citizens. The principle on which the unity of the mystical body of Christ
depends is, indeed, far more productive of this spirit of unity than that of any
family or nation on this earth.
It is the formal unitive principle that is of greater consideration in union
than the actual distance, however great this may be, which separates the
members. Thus it is apparent that the greatest intimacy is to be found in the
hypostatic union, which evidently far transcends the unity of the mystical body
of Christ. Nevertheless the hypostatic union is not so great as the unity of the
Trinity;[615] for the unity of the Trinity is a unity of an absolutely simple
nature, which is numerically one in the three divine persons and identical with
each of them.
St. Bernard has given us three conclusions in equivalent words in one of his
works, saying: "Among all things that are properly called one, the unity of
the Trinity holds the first place, in which the three persons are one in
substance or nature; conversely, that union holds the second place by which
three substances are present in the one person of Christ,"[616] namely, the
Deity, the soul, and the body.
Reply to first objection. The unity of the divine person in Christ is greater
than numerical unity, which is the principle of number; for the unity of a
divine person is an uncreated and self-subsisting unity, and is incompatible
with the nature of a part.
This union is sublime; for what is extraordinary in the order of the
beautiful is sublime. Beauty is splendor of unity in variety, and the more
distant are the extremes that are united and the more intimately they are
united, the more beautiful is their union. This union of which we are speaking
is unique, and is both a miracle and an essentially supernatural mystery. Its
real possibility is not apodictically proved by reason alone, but it is
persuaded and defended against those denying it.
There remains, however, the principal difficulty.[617] It may be expressed by
the following syllogism.
That union is greater from which results not only one person, but also one
nature. But such is the union between soul and body. Therefore it is greater
than the hypostatic union.
Reply to third objection. On the part of the medium in which it takes place,
the hypostatic union is nobler, for "the unity of the divine person is
greater than the unity of person and nature in us."[618] This is evident,
for the divine person of the Word is absolutely simple, whereas the human person
and the human nature are composite. Thus the human composite is corruptible,
whereas the hypostatic union is incorruptible.
How shall we reply, therefore, to the major of this objection, namely, that
union is greater from which results not only one person but also one nature? I
distinguish: that the union is greater on the part of the extremes, this I
concede; on the part of the medium, this I deny.
Thus the union in the Incarnation is intensively more perfect than the union
between soul and body, and therefore is indissoluble; whereas soul and body are
separated by death, and as long as the soul is separated it is not properly a
person.
This article is most sublime in doctrine. It can be developed so as to
elevate the mind to spiritual things, combining this article with the
above-mentioned principle, namely, "It is a greater dignity to exist in
something nobler than oneself than to exist by oneself."[619] This
principle is very rich in possibilities if closely examined, first as found in
Christ, and then as it applies in a certain extended sense to us in the
operational order. Thus it is better for us to be passive in our relations with
God, by a perfect conformity of our will with the divine will, than following
our own will to rule the world, which is contrary to Satan's doctrine, who, in
seeking to tempt Christ, said: "All these things will I give Thee, if
falling down Thou wilt adore me."[620] Thereupon Jesus says to him: "Begone,
Satan! For it is written: The Lord thy God shalt thou adore, and Him only shalt
thou serve."[621] It is a greater dignity for one to exist in someone
nobler than oneself than to exist by oneself, and to act in conformity with
God's will than to perform great acts by one's own choice. As Cajetan says:
"It is better to obey the king, than to rule over one's
household,"[622] or it is better to be in a passive frame of mind as
regards those superior to us, than to assume an active role as regards those
inferior to us; and although it is better to give than to receive, it is better
to receive from someone superior to us, than to give to someone inferior to us.
Thus the true way of passivity in the spiritual life is nobler than to act,
relying on one's own ability, as Dionysius says of Hierotheus that he was
"passive to the divine operations (patiens divina) "[623]
Tenth Article: Whether The Union Of The Two Natures In Christ Took Place By
Grace
State of the question. The difficulties at the beginning of this article show
clearly the purpose of this question. It seems that the union did not take place
by grace, because grace is an accident inhering in the soul of everyone in the
state of grace; whereas the hypostatic union is substantial, as stated above,
and belongs exclusively to Christ.
Reply. This union did not take place by created grace, which is an accident,
and an habitual gift inhering in the soul, but it took place by uncreated grace,
which is the gratuitous will of God doing something without any preceding merits
on the part of the beneficiary of the gift.
First part. It is evident, because this union is substantial, and not
accidental.
Second part. It is also evident, because this union infinitely transcends the
faculty and exigencies of created nature, even the angelic.[624]
In this article St. Thomas does not speak of a substantial mode that would be
present between the Word that assumes and the humanity that is assumed.
Eleventh Article: Whether Any Merits Preceded The Union Of The Incarnation
State of the question. In a certain sense it seems the Incarnation was
merited, for the just of the Old Testament merited eternal life, to which they
could attain only through the Incarnation. Therefore it seems that they likewise
merited the Incarnation. Also the Church chants of the Blessed Virgin that
"she merited to bear the Lord of all "[625]
On the contrary, St. Augustine teaches that no merits preceded our
regeneration,[626] and he gives St. Paul as his authority.[627] Therefore no
merits preceded the generation of Christ. Moreover, in the above-mentioned work,
St. Augustine shows in his own beautiful way that the predestination of Christ
as man to divine natural sonship, could not have been because of Christ's
foreseen merits, for these merits presuppose His person already constituted.
From this St. Augustine concludes that likewise our predestination, of which
Christ's predestination is the exemplar, is not because of our foreseen merits,
which are the effects of our predestination, as explained by St. Thomas.[628]
Reply. There are three conclusions in the body of the article.
First conclusion. Christ could not merit His incarnation, because every
operation of Christ followed the hypostatic union; for Christ was not first a
mere man, and afterward united to the Word, but at the very moment His human
nature was created, it was personally united to the Word. This conclusion is de
fide against Photinus.[629]
Second conclusion. The patriarchs of the Old Testament and the Blessed Virgin
Mary did not merit and could not merit de condigno the Incarnation, and this for
three reasons.
1) Because the Incarnation transcends the beatitude of eternal life, to which
the merits of the just are ordained as their ultimate reward. The Incarnation
establishes the hypostatic order above the order of grace and glory.
2) Because the principle of grace cannot fall under merit, for it would be
its own cause. Thus the state of grace does not fall under merit, and a fortiori
this applies to the Incarnation, which is the principle of grace, for the Gospel
says: "Grace and truth came by Jesus Christ."[630]
3) Because the incarnation of Christ is for the reformation of the entire
human nature, and therefore it is not on account of the merit of any particular
man. St. John says: "Of His fullness we have all received."[631]
Third conclusion. Yet the patriarchs of the Old Testament merited the
Incarnation congruously or in a broad sense by desiring and beseeching, for it
was becoming that God should hearken to those who obeyed Him. "The Blessed
Virgin," says St. Thomas, "is said to have merited to bear the Lord of
all; not that she merited His incarnation, but because by the grace bestowed
upon her she merited that grade of purity and holiness which fitted her to be
the Mother of God."[632] These are golden words, and in the strictest sense
express what the Blessed Virgin Mary truly merited, for she did not merit the
Incarnation, which is the principle of that plenitude of grace which she
received so as to merit, but she merited an increase of grace by which she
became worthy to be the Mother of God.[633]
There are some doubts that arise concerning this article.
For the solution of these doubts we must recall the division of merit as set
forth in the treatise on grace. Merit is a work performed that is deserving of a
reward, or, more correctly, there is a right to a reward in this work performed.
Hence the foundation for this division is according to the excellence of the
work performed, inasmuch as there is or is not equality of proportion between
the work performed and the reward. There is this proportion in condign merit,
but not in congruous merit.
[diagram page 190]
MERIT
condign
which has its foundation at least in distributive justice, inasmuch as there
is condignity or equality of proportion between the work and the reward
congruous
in the strict sense: is founded on friendship, or a friendly right between
persons, inasmuch as friendship is a potential part of justice
in the broad sense: is founded on God's pure mercy, without implying any
right or obligation to reward because of the work performed
First doubt. Could Christ have merited His incarnation by works that followed
from it?[634]
Some theologians, such as Suarez, Ruiz, Coninck, are of this opinion,
inasmuch as God had decreed the execution and continuance of the Incarnation in
future times because of the foreseen future merits of Christ.
The Thomists deny this view. They defend this first conclusion of St. Thomas
by saying that Christ neither merited nor could have absolutely merited His
incarnation either de condigno or de congruo, not even by works that followed
from it.
The reason for this is that the principle of merit neither falls nor can fall
under merit, for it would be its own cause, as explained in the treatise on
grace.[635]
More briefly, Christ did not merit His own self. Merit is the morally
efficient cause of reward, inasmuch as it is a right to a reward; if, therefore,
the principle of merit were to fall under merit as a reward, then merit would be
its moral cause; and thus it would be its own cause; it would be both cause and
effect in the same genus and in the same aspect, which is absurd.
But the Incarnation is the principle of the whole of Christ's merit because
it is impossible to conceive of any of Christ's operations that does not proceed
from His person as the efficient principle that operates, since actions belong
to the supposita, and operation follows being, and the person of the Word gives
an infinite value to Christ's merits, which will be more clearly explained
farther on.
Hence not even Christ's good works following from the Incarnation could have
merited it either de condigno or de congruo, for these works would have been the
cause of Christ Himself. Similarly the Incarnation would have been both cause
and effect in the same aspect; it would have been both principle and principled,
prior and posterior to itself, all of which are contrary to the principle of
contradiction, that must be preserved in these mysteries, otherwise mysteries
would be nothing but absurdities, not above reason, but contrary to reason.
Confirmation. The Incarnation was decreed even as regards its execution
before the merits of Christ were foreseen. For just as being precedes operation,
so the being of Christ was decreed before His operation.[636] Hence Christ could
not have merited His incarnation at least in its essentials.
Second doubt. Did Christ merit the circumstances of His incarnation?
The Thomists answer by distinguishing between circumstances either preceding
or accompanying the Incarnation, and others that follow from it. They also
subdistinguish the preceding circumstances so far as they either are or are not
necessarily connected with the Incarnation.[637] They say:
1) Christ did not merit the preceding or concomitant circumstances of the
Incarnation that essentially belong to His being or were its necessary
accompaniments.[638]
The reason is that Christ's merits presuppose His incarnation as their
principle, and likewise the aforesaid circumstances that belong to His essence
and individuation in the Incarnation.
Moreover, God cannot infallibly foresee Christ's future merits, unless He
previously foresees that Christ will exist in some moment of time.
Hence Christ did not merit to be conceived of the Holy Ghost, to be born of
the Blessed Virgin Mary, of the Jewish race, in a certain place, at a certain
time, and in a certain manner.
2) Christ merited those circumstances of His incarnation that neither
essentially belong to His being nor were its necessary accompaniments, or those
that did not pertain to His essence and individuation in the Incarnation.
These circumstances are not the cause or principle of merit, nor does
Christ's merit depend on them. Christ merited all that fittingly can be called
merit. Thus He merited what the prophets foretold about Him, what the angel
announced,[639] and more probably the virginity of Mary, for Mary's virginity
does not essentially belong to the Incarnation, any more than that a mother be
of the white race; nor does it seem necessarily connected with the Incarnation.
Likewise Christ merited the Immaculate Conception of the Blessed Virgin Mary.
3) Christ merited the circumstances that followed from the Incarnation;
because these are not connected with the principle of merit, but follow from it.
Thus He merited the multitude of angels singing after His birth, the adoration
of the Magi, the appearance of the star, the care given to Him by the Blessed
Virgin Mary and St. Joseph, to be the judge of the world, the institutor of the
sacraments, His resurrection.[640]
More briefly, as the Salmanticenses say: "Concerning all the
circumstances of the Incarnation, it may be said that Christ did not merit those
that belong to the essence and individuation of the Incarnation, such as to be
conceived of the Holy Ghost, to be born of the Virgin, and so He did not merit
the maternity of the Blessed Virgin Mary; but He merited all the circumstances
that do not belong to the essence of the mystery.
"The reason is, as regards the first conditions, that the principle of
merit, the Incarnation, does not fall under merit; concerning the other
circumstances, the reason is that these are not connected with the principle of
merit."[641] Briefly, Christ did not merit His own self.
[diagram page 193]
CIRCUMSTANCES OF THE INCARNATION
preceding and accompanying it
those pertaining to essence and individuation of Incarnation -
e.g., conceived of the Holy Ghost, born of the Virgin Mary; i.e., Christ did
not merit her virginal maternity (so the Salmanticenses(Christ did not merit
these)
what does not pertain to the essence of the Incarnation—(Christ did merit
these)
what the prophets foretold about Him, what the angel announced, and other
such things—following from it
adoration of Magi, care given to Him by Blessed Virgin and St. Joseph, to
institute sacraments, to rise from dead—(Christ did merit these)
Third doubt. Did Christ merit the continuation of His incarnation? Suarez and
certain other theologians affirm that He did.
The majority of the theologians, especially among the Thomists, say that He
did not. They give as their reason, that the continuation does not differ from
the Incarnation itself, which cannot be the object of merit. The Incarnation is
not a continuation after the manner of successive and divisible things by some
addition, namely, by way of part, degree or help, but it is simultaneously whole
and is measured by an absolutely indivisible duration, which transcends the
continuity of solar time, and also the discrete time in the succession of
thoughts of angels. This duration, that measures the Incarnation, is
participated eternity, participated indeed inasmuch as the Incarnation had a
beginning. The reason is that the hypostatic union is unchangeable, and more
permanent than the beatific vision, which is really measured by participated
eternity on the part of the object, inasmuch as there is neither change nor
succession in it.
Confirmation. Now the continuation of the state of grace until death no more
falls under merit than the beginning of this state, which is the principle of
merit; a fortiori, therefore, the continuation of the Incarnation, which is the
radical principle of all merits of both Christ and baptized persons, does not
fall under merit.
Fourth doubt. This concerns the merits of the patriarchs of the Old Testament
and of the Blessed Virgin Mary.
St. Thomas clearly shows indeed that they could not have merited de condigno
the Incarnation, which is the radical principle of the merits of all men after
the Fall and their regeneration, and which transcends our beatitude or the
ultimate end of our merit. This is the commonly accepted and certain opinion
among theologians, which is expressed in passages of Holy Scripture where it is
stated that the Incarnation is a work of mercy. The canticle that is called the
Benedictus, says: "Through the bowels of the mercy of our God, in which the
Orient from on high hath visited us."[642] St. Paul says: "But when
the goodness and kindness of God our Savior appeared; not by the works of
justice which we have done, but according to His mercy He saved us."[643]
Hence neither the Blessed Virgin Mary could merit de condigno the
Incarnation; but it was the radical principle of all the merits of the Blessed
Virgin Mary, who received the grace of the Immaculate Conception because of the
future merits of Christ, as Pius IX declared.[644]
Therefore the only difficulty that remains is that which concerns congruous
merit. In other words, what does St. Thomas mean by saying toward the end of the
body of this eleventh article: "Yet the holy fathers of the Old Testament
merited the Incarnation congruously by desiring and beseeching; for it was
becoming that God should hearken to those who obeyed Him"?
Is it here a case of congruous merit in the strict sense, a merit that is
founded on friendship, or on an amicable right; or is it merely congruous merit
in the broad sense, which has its foundation in God's pure mercy who hears our
prayers even without their being meritorious either de condigno or de congruo,
as when He hears the prayers of sinners who cannot merit to be heard, since they
are in a state of sin?
Several theologians, even some Thomists, say that congruous merit is here
meant. But they are incapable of solving the objection that immediately presents
itself, namely, that the incarnation of Christ is the principle of the whole
merit acquired by the Blessed Virgin Mary, and by the fathers of both the Old
Testament and of the New.[645] The principle of merit does not fall under merit,
not even under congruous merit in the strict sense, for this merit has its
foundation in friendship or in charity that comes from Christ. St. Thomas says:
"Christ is the Savior of the whole human race,"[646] as the angel
said: "He shall save His people from their sins."[647]
Some theologians reply that in the intentional order the Incarnation is the
principle of merit concerning the fathers of the Old Testament, and in the order
of execution the merits of the fathers prepare for the Incarnation. In other
words, the Incarnation and these merits are mutually causes, though in a
different order; the Incarnation is the final cause, but merits constitute the
moral efficient cause.
This reply is of no value. It would perhaps apply to the merits of Adam in
the state of innocence, but here it is valueless; for the merits of the fathers
are dependent on the future merits of Christ, not only as final cause, but as
moral efficient cause. These causes are mutually causes, though in a different
order. Hence St. Thomas says: "The mystery of the Incarnation is the
principle of merit, because of His fullness we all have received,"[648]
even all the just of the Old Testament. The same must be said of the merits of
the Blessed Virgin Mary. In the present state of man after the Fall, there is no
merit, nor is it possible to conceive of any, which does not derive its value
and power of meriting from the merits of Christ. Merits in Christ are not
conceived as morally efficient cause of our merits, except so far as Christ is
considered as existing, or absolutely will exist in some moment of time, and
consequently actually existing and not merely intending to exist; for actions
belong to supposita that exist, and operation follows being. Hence the principle
"causes mutually interact" does not apply here, for they would be
causes in the same genus of causality, which constitutes a vicious circle.[649]
Hence neither the fathers of the Old Testament nor the Blessed Virgin could
merit strictly de congruo the accomplishment of the Incarnation as foreseen and
decreed by God, nor therefore as taking place in time. If we merit the
attainment of glory in the order of execution, it is because God so willed this
by His eternal and effective decree. This means, as it is commonly said, that in
the intentional order God freely wills to give glory to His elect, but He does
not will to give it freely to the adult elect in the order of execution. This
means that the adult must merit glory to which they have been freely
predestined.[650]
Solution of the doubt. Several Thomists, such as Sylvius and Gotti, say that
the problem concerns congruous merit in the broad sense of the term, which has
its foundation in God's pure mercy hearing our prayers even though they are not
strictly meritorious, such as the prayers of sinners.[651] And this seems to be
the meaning of the following text of St. Thomas: "It was becoming that God
should hear the prayers of those who obey Him."[652] Therefore congruous
merit in the broad sense is the same as impetration.
Otherwise 1. the Fathers would have merited something better than Christ
Himself merited; 2. Christ would be indebted to the fathers for His incarnation;
3. The Incarnation would not be a work of pure mercy.
Thus the principle enunciated by St. Thomas in the body of this eleventh
article, namely, "the principle of merit does not fall under merit,"
remains intact. This principle applies equally to strictly congruous merit,
which is the result of God's love obtained for us by Christ, as to condign
merit. Sacrosanct also is the principle that Christ is the source of the merits
of the regenerated both in the Old Testament and in the New, even of the merits
of the Blessed Virgin Mary.
This interpretation is confirmed by the fact that St. Thomas denies that the
Blessed Virgin Mary merited the Incarnation, for he writes: "The Blessed
Virgin is said to have merited to bear the Lord of all, not that she merited His
incarnation, but because by the grace bestowed upon her she merited that grade
of purity and holiness which fitted her to be the Mother of God."[653]
St. Thomas said practically the same in another of His works, in which he
wrote: "The Blessed Virgin did not merit the Incarnation, but after its
accomplishments she merited to be instrumental in bringing it about, not by
condign merit, but by congruous merit, inasmuch as it was becoming that the
Mother of God should be most pure and most perfect."[654]
Objection. Strictly congruous merit has its foundation in the mutual
friendship prevailing between the one who merits and the one who rewards. But
the holy fathers who desired the Incarnation were God's friends, and a fortiori
the Blessed Virgin was. Therefore the Blessed Virgin and the holy fathers de
congruo merited the Incarnation.
Reply. I distinguish the major; when nothing militates against the notion of
merit, I concede the major; otherwise I deny it. But the obstacle here is that
the Incarnation is the principle of merit for the fathers, and cannot be
merited. Moreover, as already stated, the Incarnation constitutes a special
hypostatic order, which is beyond the scope of merit; for the only purpose of
merit is for the attainment of eternal happiness, and "the union of the
Incarnation transcends the union of the beatified mind with God, and therefore
it cannot fall under merit,"[655] as St. Thomas says.
Twelfth Article: Whether The Grace Of Union Was Natural To The Man Christ
Cajetan remarks that this question concerns Christ, not as God, but as man.
Is the grace of union natural to Him?
Reply. The grace of union is not natural to Christ, if this would mean that
it is caused by the principle of the human nature; but it may be called natural
inasmuch as it was bestowed upon Him together with the human nature, and
moreover, inasmuch as it comes from the divine nature of Christ. Infused
habitual grace in the soul of Christ is also natural in this sense.
The reason is that both graces are substantially supernatural and were given
to Christ at the moment of His conception.
Doubt. Was the Blessed Virgin Mary the instrumental cause of the union of the
human nature with the Word at the very moment of Christ's conception?
Reply. Most certainly no creature was or could be the principal efficient
cause of the Incarnation, for the Incarnation is not only a work that belongs
properly to God, such as creation, but it is His greatest work; for it is a
miracle of the first order surpassing in substance all created and creatable
powers and all exigencies of whatsoever created nature. It is also a mystery
that transcends the mysteries of grace and that constitutes a special order,
known as the hypostatic order.
The Incarnation was a work of the Trinity, by reason of omnipotence, which is
a common attribute of the three persons. Thus, as we stated, the Father and the
Holy Ghost joined in the act of uniting the human nature with the Word, but only
the Son assumes or takes this nature to Himself.
But a doubt arises. Was the Blessed Virgin the instrumental cause of the
Incarnation?
The question is disputed. St. Thomas says that Mary was not, for he writes:
"In the conception of Christ, the Blessed Virgin took no active part, but
was merely the material cause."[656] But the instrumental cause takes an
active part through the power of the principal agent.
Likewise St. Thomas maintains that there is no instrumental cause in
creation,[657] not even in the creation of the souls of infants, which occurs
every day. The parents are not the efficient cause, but merely furnish the
matter or dispose the body for the reception of the soul; a fortiori there is no
instrumental cause in the Incarnation.
The principle on which this a fortiori argument rests may be illustrated by
the following syllogism.
An instrument must dispose the subject for the effect of the principal agent.
But, as in creation, there is no subject from which is produced that which is
created from nothing; so in the Incarnation there is no pre-existing subject to
be disposed, for the Incarnation is the communication of the personality of the
Word to the human nature of Christ. The Word, however, is beyond the scope of
created action, and is not the subject on which created action operates. Matter
cannot be disposed for something uncreated, namely, for the Word that assumes.
Therefore there is no instrumental cause in the Incarnation.[658]
Hence, if the Blessed Virgin is said at times to be the instrumental cause of
the creation of Christ's soul and even of the Incarnation, this must be
understood in a broad sense, inasmuch as she provided the matter which was
formed by the Holy Ghost into the human nature and united with the Word.
CHAPTER V: QUESTION 3: THE MODE OF THE UNION ON THE PART OF
THE PERSON ASSUMING
After the consideration of the hypostatic union in itself, we must now
discuss the nature of this union on the part of the person assuming.
John of St. Thomas observes in the beginning of his commentary on this third
question that St. Thomas divides it into two parts: 1. the person assuming (a.
1-5); 2. the manner of the assumption (a. 6-8).
First Article: Whether It Is Fitting For A Divine Person To Assume
Cajetan says the purport of this title is to show that the question of this
article concerns the divine person as such, so far as we introduce a mental
distinction between person and the divine nature.[659]
State of the question. It is apparent from the first two difficulties
presented at the beginning of the article, namely, that there is no possibility
of any addition to a divine person because this person is in Himself infinitely
perfect. Also incommunicability belongs to the concept of person.
Conclusion. To assume a nature is most properly befitting to a person.
Authoritative proof. St. Augustine, who is quoting St. Fulgentius, says:
"This God, that is, the Only-begotten One, took the form, that is, the
nature of a servant to His own person."
Proof from reason. It may be expressed in syllogistic form as follows: The
word "assume," which practically means to take to oneself, is both the
principle and the term of an act. But only a person can be both the principle
and term of an act. Therefore only a person can assume.
The other articles of this question will bring out more clearly the meaning
of the adverb "most properly."
Proof of minor. It belongs to a person to act, for actions are attributed to
supposita, and a person is that which by itself separately exists and acts.
Moreover a person is the term of this assumption, because the union took place
in the person and not in the nature.
Assumption is properly an action by which the human nature is drawn into the
subsistence of the Son, so that it may subsist by this subsistence. Hence this
action not only produces in the human nature of Christ a relation of dependence
on the Word, but communicates to it the personality of the Word.
Reply to first objection. No addition is made to the divine person, who is
infinite. But what is divine is united to man. Hence not God, but man is
perfected.
Reply to second objection. "A divine person is said to be incommunicable
inasmuch as it cannot be predicated of several supposita, but nothing prevents
several things being predicated of the person.... But this is proper to a divine
person, on account of its infinity, that there should be a concourse of natures
in it, in subsistence."[660]
Doubt. Does the termination of another nature belong exclusively to a divine
person, so that it would be repugnant to every created or creatable personality?
Can an angel, for example, or a devil assume the human nature? Some thought that
St. John the Baptist was an angel incarnate, and that Antichrist will be a devil
incarnate.
Reply. It is the common teaching among theologians that no created person can
assume a nature into union with its suppositum. So say Cajetan, Soto, Alvarez,
Medina, Suarez, Vasquez, Billuart. The reason is that finite personality derives
its limitation and species from the nature whose complement and term it is.
Although subsistence is the mode and term of the nature, it does not specify the
nature, but is specified by it. Thus we speak of the human personality, or of
the angelic personality; hence it implies a contradiction for the same
personality of one nature to terminate another. On the contrary, the divine
personality because of its infinity, as St. Thomas says,[661] is above both
genus and species and contains formally and eminently the power of all possible
personalities.
Second Article: Whether It Is Befitting To The Divine Nature To Assume
State of the question. The meaning of the title is, as Cajetan remarks,
whether de facto it is true that the Deity, or rather God, assumed the human
nature.[662]
It seems not to be true, because the union did not take place in the nature,
but in the person; also because to assume in this manner could be said of the
three persons.
Nevertheless, St. Augustine or rather St. Fulgentius, who is quoted in the
counter-argument, says that the divine nature took our nature.
Conclusion. In the strictest sense a person is said to assume inasmuch as it
is both principle and term of the assumption. In a secondary sense, however, it
can be said that the Deity or God assumed the human nature inasmuch as the Deity
was the principle of the assumptive act but not its term. The whole article must
be read.[663]
All the other articles of this question, on the supposition of the real
possibility, even of the very fact of the incarnation of the Word, examine what
else was either possible or impossible. I say: "on the supposition of the
real possibility of the incarnation of the Word," which, as already stated,
is neither demonstrated by reason alone, nor can be disproved, but is persuaded
and defended against those denying it, and is firmly held by faith.
Third Article: Whether The Nature Abstracted From The Personality Can Assume
State of the question. The meaning of the title is: Can the divine nature
assume a nature different from its own, if by God we understand, in the way the
pagans and Jews imagine Him to exist, without personal relations and without
persons, as our Catholic faith acknowledges to be in Him?
It seems that the divine nature cannot so assume; because, as stated above,
it befits the nature to assume because of the person, and because the union took
place not in the nature, but in the person.
Reply. It is affirmed, nevertheless, that the divine nature can assume our
nature.
Proof. It is taken from the counterargument of this article, from the
argumentative part and from the reply to the second objection. The reasons given
are: 1. In this hypothesis, God's omnipotence, by which the Incarnation took
place, would remain. 2. There would also remain the one personality of God as
the Jews understand, which could be the term of the assumption.[664]
In God, the Deity and God are identical, or in God whereby it is and what is
are the same; for God's essence is His self-existing being.[665]
First doubt. Is it something absolute or something relative that immediately
terminates the human nature of Christ?
Reply. It is something relative that immediately and proximately terminates
Christ's human nature, namely, the personality of the Word, which is constituted
by relative subsistence, or by the subsisting relation of sonship, as explained
in the treatise on the Trinity. The divine relations are subsisting relations,
inasmuch as their inexistence (esse in) is substantial and not accidental as in
created predicamental relations, for example, in created paternity and created
sonship.[666]
Proof. The Eleventh Council of Toledo in its profession of faith says:
"Neither the Holy Spirit nor God the Father, but only the person of the Son
took flesh."[667] But if the Word were to terminate the human nature
formally and proximately by a common and absolute subsistence, then the Father
and the Holy Spirit equally with the Son, would have been incarnate.
Second doubt. Could the triune God assume the human nature primarily on
account of absolute subsistence, and only secondarily on account of relative
subsistences?
Reply. The triune God could have assumed absolutely our human nature, because
this absolute subsistence "could be the principle and term of this
assumption," as stated by St. Thomas in this article.[668] For the reason
why God subsists in His own nature, can be the reason why He subsists in a
different nature. But absolute and common subsistence could be the reason for
His subsistence in a different nature.
Third doubt. What is the difference between the incommunicability of absolute
subsistence and of relative subsistence?
Reply. The first incommunicability is not within the Trinity, but only
external to it. The second incommunicability is both internal and external to
the Trinity. Common and absolute subsistence does not formally attribute
incommunicability internally to the Deity, for the Deity is communicated to the
Son and to the Holy Ghost. On the contrary, the personality of the Father is not
communicated to the Son. But God by reason of His common and absolute
subsistence is incommunicable externally, in this sense that He is by Himself
separately existing, really and essentially distinct from the world. St. Thomas
says: "A person is said to be incommunicable inasmuch as it cannot be
predicated of several supposita."[669]
What the philosopher means by saying that God is personal, is that He is the
separately existing being, distinct from every creature, intelligent and free
and so is externally incommunicable. When theologians speak of the three divine
persons, what they first of all have in mind is internal incommunicability. Thus
the Father communicates the whole divine nature to the Son, but not His
personality, which is the subsistent relation of paternity in opposition to
filiation.[670]
Objection. The Fathers and councils never mention this absolute subsistence,
which seems to have been discovered by Cajetan.
Reply. They never referred to it because there was no occasion of doing so to
refute errors against it such as Nestorianism and Monophysitism, which had not
yet arisen. It sufficed to exclude union in the nature and affirm the union in
the person of the Word, as recorded in revelation. Absolute subsistence was not
discovered by Cajetan, for St. Thomas explicitly refers to it in this third
article.
Fourth Article: Whether One Person Without Another Can Assume A Created
Nature
State of the question. The difficulty, as presented by the first objection,
is that assumption, being a certain external operation, pertains to all three
persons, who operate externally by a common omnipotence. Thus it has been
shown[671] that the Trinity of persons cannot be known from creatures by natural
reason; for "the creative power of God is common to the whole
Trinity."[672]
Reply. Nevertheless it is of faith that only the Son of God became incarnate,
neither the Father nor the Holy Spirit. The Eleventh Council of Toledo says:
"We believe that of these three persons, only the person of the Son... true
man... assumed[our nature]."[673]
The body of the article contains the solution of the difficulty arising from
the definition of assumption, or to assume.
Assumption implies two things: the act of assuming and the term of the
assumption. But revelation says that only the person of the Son is the term of
the assumption. Therefore assumption, considered as the term, applies only to
the person of the Son, although considered as an act, it is common to the three
persons.
Thus we said that the Father and the Holy Ghost united the human nature with
the Word, but They did not assume it in the sense of term.
Fifth Article: Whether Each Of The Divine Persons Could Have Assumed Human
Nature
State of the question. The difficulty is, as stated in the second objection,
that by the divine Incarnation, men acquired the adoption of sons, which is a
participated likeness of natural sonship, which applies only to the Son.
Therefore it seems that only the Son could be incarnate. Moreover, to be
incarnate is to be sent, which cannot apply to the Father, who cannot be sent by
any person, since the other two persons proceed from Him.
Reply. Nevertheless it is affirmed, that each of the persons could have
assumed human nature. For to assume another nature is befitting to God because
of His omnipotence, as the principle of the assumption, and because of His
person, as the term of the assumption. But each of the divine persons is
omnipotent and has His own personality. Therefore each of the divine persons
could have assumed human nature.
Reply to first objection. It was fitting, if the Father became incarnate, for
Him as man to have been the Son of man, for example, the son of David; for this
would be according to difference of natures, and would not result in confusion
of realities, but at most of names.
Reply to second objection. It contains a beautiful scriptural text concerning
adoptive sonship, which is a certain participated likeness of natural sonship.
But if the Father became incarnate, we would have received this adoptive sonship
from Him, as coming from the principle of natural sonship;[674] but farther on
in this question, it is shown that it was more fitting for the Son to have
become incarnate.[675]
Reply to third objection. The Father, who is innascible as to eternal birth,
could have been born temporally as man if He had become incarnate. In such case
the Incarnation would not have been a mission. Thus the Father dwells in the
just, as the Son and the Holy Ghost do, but He is not sent, and so He comes
without being sent; whereas the other two persons are sent by Him. So the pope
sends His legate, but he himself is not sent, but comes.
Sixth Article: Whether Several Divine Persons Can Assume One And The Same
Individual Nature
State of the question. The meaning is: Can the three persons assume this
human nature, terminating it proximately and immediately by their own relations?
The difficulty is that it could not then be said the human nature is assumed
by one man or by several men, because there would be one human nature and three
divine persons who possess it.
Reply. Yet St. Thomas affirms the possibility of the three persons assuming
one and the same human nature. It is the commonly accepted teaching, but it was
attacked by Scotus.
Indirect proof. It is taken from the counterargument of this article, and
proceeds by way of analogy; for just as the divine nature is common to the three
persons, so likewise the human individualized nature can be common to Them.
A more direct and proper proof is found in the argumentative part of this
article. It may be expressed by the following syllogism.
The divine persons do not exclude one another from communicating in the same
nature, since they terminate together the same divine nature.
But in the mystery of the Incarnation, the whole reason of the deed is the
power of the doer, as Augustine says.
Therefore in passing judgment on the act, we must take into special
consideration the condition of the person assuming, who does not exclude the
other two persons from communicating in the same nature.
There is no repugnance on the part of the human nature, because it can be
assumed, not by reason of its natural limited power, but because of its
obediential power, which extends to all that is not essentially repugnant.
What is truly impossible is for a divine person to assume a human person, for
then there would be two persons in one person.
Reply to first objection. It contains the solution of the difficulty proposed
in the objection, namely, that, granting the hypothesis, it would be true to say
that the three divine persons were one man, because of the one human nature,
just as we say that they are one God, because of the one divine nature, which is
one numerically, without any multiplication and division.[676]
Seventh Article: Whether One Divine Person Can Assume Two Human Natures
State of the question. This question is posited, as the preceding questions
are, so as to make it known more clearly in what the mystery of the Incarnation
consists on the part of the person assuming.
The difficulty is that there would be one suppositum for two natures of the
same species, for example, the same divine person would be Peter and John.
Another difficulty is that it could not then be said that the person incarnate
is one man, because He would have two human natures; nor several men, because
several men have distinct supposita. It is not apparent how these two human
natures could be united to each other, one of these natures being perhaps in one
part of the world, and the other in another part.
Reply. St. Thomas affirms, however, the possibility of such an assumption.
Indirect proof. It is taken from the counter-argument of this article, and
may be expressed by the following syllogism.
Whatever the Father can do externally, the Son also can do. But after the
Incarnation, the Father can assume a human nature distinct from that assumed by
the Son. Therefore the Son can assume a human nature distinct from the one He
assumed.
Direct proof. This same principle is again invoked, as in the following
syllogism.
The power of a divine person, both as regards the principle in the assumption
and as regards the term of the assumption, is infinite; nor can it be restricted
to what has been created. But a divine person would be restricted in power if He
could assume only one human nature. Therefore a divine person can assume more
than one human nature.
Some have objected that such two human natures would interpenetrate.
Reply. To establish the truth of this conclusion, it is not necessary for the
divine person to assume these two natures in the same place; for divine
immensity makes it possible for any of the divine persons to assume one of the
human natures in Rome, and the other in some place far away from this city. Such
action involves no absurdity.[677]
Reply to first objection. "There can be a numerical multitude on the
part of the nature, on account of the division of matter, without distinction of
supposita."
Reply to second objection. There would still be one man, and not several,
because there is only one suppositum. In fact, one divine person could assume
many individual human natures, and there would be no pantheism in this for there
would be no confusion of the divine nature with the human nature; but all these
natures would be impeccable. Toletus gave us a good rule to follow, one that is
taken from the teaching of St. Thomas. He says: "For the multiplication of
concrete substantive names both kinds of multitude are required, namely, of
supposita and of forms; the absence of one results in unity."[678]
Eighth Article: Whether It Was More Fitting That The Person Of The Son Rather
Than Any Other Divine Person Should Assume Human Nature
State of the question. It seems that it is not, because the effect of the
Incarnation is a kind of second creation, which befits the Father, inasmuch as
creative power is appropriated to Him. Besides, the Incarnation is ordained to
the remission of sins, which is attributed to the Holy Ghost.
Conclusion. Yet it was most fitting that the person of the Son should become
incarnate, and this for three reasons.
1) Because of the principle of the union. All things were made by the Word,
as by the exemplary cause. Therefore it was fitting that ail things be restored
by the Word. Thus the craftsman, by the intelligible form or concept of his art,
whereby he fashioned his handiwork, restores it when it has fallen into ruin.
2) The end of the union. It was fitting that He who is the natural Son of
God, should make us adoptive sons.[679] He received by eternal generation the
whole divine nature without its being multiplied or divided; but we receive a
participation of the divine nature, or the radical principle of strictly divine
operations, and finally a participation of the beatific vision.[680]
3) Reparation for sin. An inordinate desire for knowledge had resulted in the
sin and spiritual death of man. Hence it was fitting that reparation be made by
Him to whom wisdom is attributed.
St. Paul says: "[God] predestinated[us] to be made conformable to the
image of His Son, that He might be the first-born among many
brethren."[681] St. Thomas in commenting on this text[682] shows clearly
that adoptive sonship is a participated likeness of natural and eternal sonship.
Adoption is generally known as the legal acceptance of an unrelated person as
son.[683] To adopt is to admit someone freely as heir to one's estate.[684] It
befits the whole Trinity to adopt men, "although in God, to beget belongs
to the person of the Father, yet to produce any effect in creatures is common to
the whole Trinity, by reason of the oneness of Their nature; because, where
there is one nature, there must be one power and one operation."[685] The
adopted son of God is not strictly begotten, but made; yet sometimes it may be
said that he is begotten, by reason of spiritual regeneration, which is
gratuitous and not natural. Hence it befits the whole Trinity to adopt men as
sons.
Nevertheless St. Thomas says: "Adoptive sonship is a certain likeness of
the eternal sonship.... Now man is likened to the splendor of the eternal Son by
reason of the light of grace which is attributed to the Holy Ghost. Therefore
adoption, though common to the whole Trinity, is appropriated to the Father as
its author; to the Son as its exemplar, to the Holy Ghost as imprinting on us
the likeness of this exemplar."[686] It is easy to assign similarities and
differences between the divine, natural, eternal sonship and adoptive sonship;
for the Son of God is by nature begotten, not made; He is light of light, true
God of true God; possesses the whole Deity that can neither be divided nor
multiplied. The adopted son is made, not begotten, but he is spiritually born of
God by grace, which is a participation of the divine nature, and this radically
disposes him for strictly divine acts, namely, to see God face to face and love
Him for all eternity.
Recapitulation. What has been discussed in this third question will enable us
to acquire a better understanding of the hypostatic union in all its aspects so
far considered.
Therefore it has been established that in the strictest sense it befits a
divine person to assume a created nature, that is, take it to Himself (a. 1 and
2). Nevertheless, God as conceived by Jews and Monotheists, not consisting of
three persons who are related to one another, could assume a created nature,
because He is omnipotent, and He could terminate this nature by absolute
subsistence, which is common to the three divine persons.
It follows from this, as has been stated, that anyone of the divine persons
could assume the human nature. In fact, the three divine persons could assume
one and the same human nature, just as they have one and the same divine nature.
Finally, one divine person could assume two human natures, because the power
of the person on the part of the principle and the term of the assumption is
infinite. But although these divers hypotheses are possible, it was more fitting
that the Son of God rather than the Father or the Holy Ghost should assume the
human nature of Christ.
CHAPTER VI: QUESTION 4: THE MODE OF THE UNION ON THE PART OF
THE HUMAN NATURE ASSUMED
We must now discuss the mode of the union not on the part of the person
assuming, but on the part of what was assumed; and here two things must be
considered.
1) What the Word assumed:
a) The human nature itself (q. 4).
b) Of the parts of the human nature, which refutes Docetism and
Apollinarianism (q. 5).
c) Of the order of this assumption, for example, whether the soul was assumed
before the flesh (q. 6).
2) What things were co-assumed; (a) of perfections, where the habitual grace
of Christ, His knowledge and power are discussed; (b) of defects, or of those
defects which Christ voluntarily accepted for our satisfaction, such as
passibility of the body, death, in which Christ's impeccability is discussed, as
also His propassions. (q. 7-15)
Thus the treatise on the hypostatic union is complete, since we find
discussed: (a) the union itself (q. 2); (b) the person assuming (q. 3); (c) the
nature assumed, both as to its parts and those things co-assumed (q. 4-15).
Afterward there will be a discussion of the consequences of the union, in
themselves and in their relations both to the Father and to us.
The fourth question contains six articles, treating of the human nature in
itself, both in its relation to human personality, which Christ did not have,
and in its relation to individuals of the human nature.
First Article: Whether Human Nature Was More Assumable By The Son Of God Than
Any Other Nature
State of the question. The inquiry concerns human nature as assumable, not
according to its natural passive power nor according to its obediential
power,[687] but according to its fitness.[688] The more common opinion among
theologians affirms with St. Thomas[689] that according to God's absolute power
any other nature is assumable. The discussion here concerns only its fitness.
This question is of some importance in determining whether besides the
obediential power there is a fitness attached to the nature, but not necessarily
so, for example, a fitness of assumption in the human nature rather than in the
angelic.
First objection. The difficulty is that God's absolute power is not limited
to one nature; for just as there is no such thing actually as the best of all
possible worlds, so there is no created nature that is more fitted for the
hypostatic union.
Second objection. The difficulty is that also in irrational creatures there
is a trace of God's image.
Third objection. In the angelic nature we find a more perfect likeness of God
than in the human nature, and there is need of redemption for angels that are
sinners.
Fourth objection. Finally the whole universe is more capable of assumption
than the human nature.
Conclusion. It was more fitting, says St. Thomas, for the human nature to be
assumed by the Word, than any other nature.
Authoritative proof. This fittingness is intimated in various passages of
Scripture. Thus the Wisdom of God is represented as saying: "My delights
were to be with the children of men."[690] Similarly St. Paul writes:
"For it became Him, for whom are all things, and by whom are all things,
who had brought many children into glory, to perfect the author of their
salvation, by His passion.... For nowhere doth He take hold of the angels, but
of the seed of Abraham He taketh hold. Wherefore it behooved Him in all things
to be made like unto His brethren, that He might become a merciful and faithful
high priest before God, that He might be a propitiation for the sins of the
people."[691] Christ had to be both priest and victim because no other
victim was worthy of fulfilling this role.
Theological proof. It may be reduced to the following syllogism.
This greater fitness may be viewed both according to the dignity and the
necessity or need of the assumable nature.
But the human is more worthy than the irrational nature since it can attain
to union with the Word by knowledge and love.[692] Moreover, it needed
reparation, since it was subjected to original sin, which is not true of the
angels, for all did not sin, and those who did are already confirmed in their
sin and incapable of redemption. Therefore it was more fitting for the human
nature than any other nature to be assumed by the Word. This conclusion must be
understood in the sense given by St. Thomas at the end of the argumentative part
of this article, where he says: "Hence it follows that only human nature
was assumable."
Moreover, as St. Thomas remarks in another of his works,[693] the human
nature is a quasi-compendium of the universe, a microcosm, inasmuch as it
contains within itself being, as in minerals, life as in the lower forms of
living animals, intelligence as in the angels, although in not so perfect a way.
The solution of the difficulties raised in the objections confirms this last
observation of St. Thomas.
Reply to first objection. Here it is shown that besides the obediential
power, which includes everything that is not in itself repugnant to reason,
there can be a certain fitness or congruity in the human nature for its being
assumed by the Word in the hypostatic union, a fitness that is not found either
in stones, plants, a lamb, or a dove. Hence St. Thomas says in this reply:
"Therefore a creature is said to be not assumable, not as if we withdrew
anything from the power of God, but in order to show the condition of the
creature which has no capability for this." Therefore this capability,
which is in neither stone nor dove, is not this obediential power for
assumption, which is in either a stone or in any animal, for example, in the
most spotless lamb.
As Cajetan remarks, St. Thomas did not ask whether the Word can assume the
nature of a stone. There is nothing intrinsically impossible in this according
to God's purely absolute power, but there would be no end or purpose in doing
this. Thus God can by His purely absolute power annihilate the Blessed Virgin
Mary, but there is no reason for doing so on the part of the end in view.
Therefore this is repugnant, if not by God's purely absolute power, at least by
His ordained power, either ordinary or extraordinary.
Yet there is truly in the nature of either a stone, a lamb, or a dove a
non-repugnance or obediential power for the hypostatic union, although there is
no capability in the sense of congruity.
From this reply to the first objection, it seems to follow that the
capability or fitness of our nature to be elevated to the beatific vision is not
this obediential power, which of itself requires nothing else but a
non-repugnance to this elevation, inasmuch as God can do whatever is not
repugnant. In fact, as will be stated farther on, there is in the most holy soul
of Christ the obediential power for a greater degree of the light of glory.[694]
The obediential power of our intellect is in itself unrestricted, because our
intellect by God's absolute power, can always be raised to a higher degree of
the light of glory, and our will to a higher degree of charity.
There remains this obediential power in the nature of the damned for being
raised to the beatific vision, but it is no longer any fittingness in them.
Reply to second objection. "The irrational creature which falls short of
the union with God by operation has no fitness to be united with Him in personal
being."
Reply to third objection. Concerning the reply to this third objection, which
must be real, Cajetan observes against Scotus, that for St. Thomas personality
is something positive and real that is distinct from the individualized nature,
for instance, from Michaelness, because St. Thomas says: "In this way,
nothing pre-existing would be corrupted in it,"[695] if God, by producing a
new angelic nature, were to unite it to Himself.
In this same reply, it is pointed out that the bad angels fell irreparably,
though not indeed absolutely, but according to the way that is consistent with
divine providence, as already explained by St. Thomas, for, when asking whether
the will of the demons is confirmed in evil, he says: "The angel's free
will is flexible to either opposite before the choice, but not after."[696]
This means that the angel's choice elicited by means of intuitive and
simultaneous knowledge of those things that must be considered in the object, is
irrevocable, and thus it participates in the immutability of the divine choice,
which is both most free and absolutely immutable. On the contrary, our choice is
elicited by means of abstractive and discursive knowledge, which only gradually
acquires the knowledge of all those things that must be considered. Hence it is
revocable, inasmuch as after the choice we can consider certain new things not
previously considered.[697]
Hence man is capable of redemption, but not the angel. Moreover, the first
man was tempted by the devil and fell, whereas the devil fell solely by his own
will. Hence the human nature is more worthy of compassion than the nature of the
fallen angel.
First doubt. Can an irrational nature, such as that of a lamb or dove, be
united befittingly with the person of the Word?
Reply. Several theologians give an affirmative answer, just as it was not
unbecoming for the Word incarnate to be scourged, spit upon, and to die. In
fact, during the three days of death, the Word remained hypostatically united to
the corpse, not personally, but subsistentially. But these reasons do not rest
on solid grounds, for the Word was united to the corpse of Christ, only because
it was previously united to His human nature, and, if the Word was scourged and
crucified, this was meritorious for our redemption. Whereas there is no
comparison in the above-mentioned hypothesis, because the dove and the lamb are
incapable of meriting and satisfying.
Second doubt. St. Thomas says in various passages that suppositum and nature
are the same in the angels;[698] yet in his reply here[699] he holds that the
angelic nature is assumable, which cannot be unless it is distinct from the
suppositum.
Reply. Cajetan, Medina, Alvarez, Gonet, and Billuart say that St. Thomas in
the passage cited above[700] means that the angelic nature is not distinct from
its individualizing notes; but he holds that the angel has its own subsistence
or personality that is distinct from its nature, which it would lose if the
angelic nature were united with the Word. On several occasions St. Thomas says
that there is a difference between what is (suppositum), and being
(existence).[701] For it is manifest that Michael has not only his nature or
Michaelness, but also his being and accidents, such as successive intellections
and volitions.
Second Article: Whether The Son Of God Assumed A Person
State of the question. The difficulty is that the Son of God assumed an
individualized nature and thus it appears that He assumed this particular man or
person.
Reply. Nevertheless, the answer is that He did not assume a person, which is
of faith against Nestorius,[702] inasmuch as the Church defined the union to be
subsistential, so that there is only one person in Christ. the counterargument
gives a quotation from St. Fulgentius, under the name of St. Augustine.
The theological explanation is given in the body of the article, which may be
explained by the following syllogism. What is assumed must be presupposed to the
assumption. But a person in human nature is not presupposed to assumption, but
is rather the term of the assumption. Therefore the human person is not assumed;
but the person of the Word assumed to Himself the human nature.
Indirect proof of minor. If the person were presupposed, then it was either
corrupted, in which case its assumption was to no purpose; or it remained after
the union, and then there were two persons in Christ, which is contrary to
revelation, and then the union would not be personal, but accidental, as
Nestorius contended.
Reply to first objection. The Son of God assumed an individualized human
nature, or a singular human nature, namely, this human nature of Christ.
Reply to second objection. It is pointed out that "the nature assumed
did not have its own personality through the loss of anything pertaining to the
perfection of the human nature, but through the addition of something which is
above human nature, which is union with a divine person." Concerning this
difficulty, St. Thomas had said: "It is a greater dignity to exist in
something nobler than oneself than to exist by oneself."[703]
Reply to third objection. St. Thomas says: "The divine person by His
union hindered the human nature from having its own personality." Therefore
St. Thomas considers personality to be something positive, real, and distinct
from the nature. It is not identical with existence, because existence is a
contingent predicate of any created person, whose formal constituent is
personality. No created person, even created personality, is his or its
existence. Thus St. Thomas often says that in every creature there is a
difference between quod est and esse, namely, between suppositum and
existence.[704]
Concerning Cajetan's great commentary, it suffices to note that he shows
there is a distinction even between the individualized nature and subsistence.
He says: "The whole force of the argument consists in this, that the
constituent of a thing, in this respect, is that a being intrinsically and
primarily susceptive of real entity, must be some reality. But this man, in this
respect, differs from this humanity, because he includes in himself something by
which he is primarily and intrinsically susceptive of some real entity that is
repugnant to this human nature. Therefore he includes in himself a reality that
constitutes him in being, by which he differs from this human nature. But he
differs only in personal being, whereby this man is a hypostasis or person,
which this human nature is not. Therefore the person of this man adds some
reality that intrinsically constitutes him a human person, which this human
nature is not."[705] This man is what is, whereas his individualized
humanity is that whereby he is constituted in a certain species.
Wherefore St. Thomas says in the present article: "If created
personality were presupposed to assumption, then it must either have been
corrupted... or there would be two persons." And also in his reply to the
third objection, he also says: "The divine person by His union hindered the
human nature from having its personality." Hence Cajetan's interpretation,
by which he shows that created personality is a substantial mode, truly has its
foundation in this text quoted from St. Thomas.
More briefly, Cajetan's whole argument may be reduced to the following
syllogism. The created suppositum differs from the nature inasmuch as it is what
is, namely, the real subject of existence, which is attributed to it
contingently. But that whereby anything is a real and not merely a logical
subject of existence is something real, distinct from this nature and from
existence, which is predicated contingently of a created person already formally
constituted as a person. Therefore the created suppositum is something real that
differs both from the individual nature and from existence.
Hence the whole of Cajetan's interpretation has its foundation in the
legitimate transition from the common sense notion of personality to its
philosophical notion, namely, from its nominal definition to its real
definition, or from the Christian acceptation to its theological notion, as
Cajetan himself remarks.[706]
Cajetan's opinion asserts only what is required for the verification of the
following three arguments of common sense.
1) This man, Peter, is not his human nature, which is attributed to him as an
essential part, and the part is not predicated of the whole; for the whole is
not the part, but has the part.
2) This man, Peter, is not his existence, which is attributed to him
contingently and not essentially. This means that it constitutes neither the
essence nor personality of Peter, but is really distinct from them. Thus in
every creature there is a real difference between suppositum and existence.[707]
3) This man, Peter, is existing, namely, it is the same suppositum that is
existing. In this judgment the word "is" affirms real identity between
subject and predicate, which means that the predicate is identical with the
suppositum. Therefore subsistence is that whereby anything is what; and as a
substantial mode, it is distinct both from nature, whereby anything is
constituted in a certain species, and from existence, whereby anything is
established outside nothing and its causes.[708]
Likewise, applying this doctrine to Christ, in accordance with revelation, we
say: "This man Jesus is God,"[709] meaning that this man is the same
suppositum that is God, or is the same person. But the divine personality of
Christ is distinct from the human nature He assumed.
Doubt. Could the Word have assumed a nature terminated by its own
subsistence, this latter remaining.
Reply. The answer is in the negative. The reason is that it implies a
contradiction for the same nature to subsist and not to subsist in a suppositum
different from its own.
Objection. The divine nature is terminated simultaneously by the three
personalities. Therefore, in like manner, the human nature could be terminated
simultaneously by two personalities.
Reply. The comparison does not apply, for the three divine personalities are
not foreign to but belong properly to the divine nature,[710] and from several
subsistences that belong properly to the divine nature there follows one effect
which is to subsist and be terminated in itself, although in divers ways. On the
contrary, from a subsistence proper to a person and one foreign to it there
follows a double effect that is repugnant, inasmuch as the person subsists in
itself and not in another, and also subsists in another and not in itself.
Third Article: Whether The Divine Person Assumed A Man
Is it strictly true to say that God assumed a man?
Reply. It is not, because man is the name of a person that signifies the
human nature as subsisting. But God did not assume a created person. Hence, in
the strict sense, it is not true to say that the Word assumed a man. After the
Incarnation, however, it is true to say that the Word is man.[711] Similarly,
the proposition, "God is man," and also the proposition, "man is
God," are true, because of the unity of the person.[712] The word
"is" expresses real identity between subject and predicate, and this
identity is identity of suppositum or person, which means that this man Jesus is
the same being or suppositum that is God.
Reply to first objection. If the Fathers at times said that the Word assumed
a man, this word "man" must not be taken in the strict sense of the
term.
Fourth Article: Whether The Son Of God Ought To Have Assumed Human Nature
Abstracted From All Individuals
This article is inserted here to refute the error of certain Platonists, who
admitted that the Son of God ought to have assumed such a nature.
It is denied that the Son of God assumed a nature abstracted from
individuals, because such a nature has only mental existence,[713] and also
because by the very fact that the nature is assumed by some person, it belongs
properly to this person. Moreover, only common and universal operations can be
attributed to the common nature, by which a person does not merit, because merit
pertains to a particular circumstance and time. Finally, even though the human
nature were to exist apart from sensible things, as Plato contended, the
assumption of this kind of separated human nature would not be fitting, because
the Son of God assumed the human nature so that He could be seen by men.
Reply to first objection. Nevertheless, it remains true that Christ is
"the universal cause of human salvation," for this universality is not
of predication, but of causation.
Fifth Article: Whether The Son Of God Ought To Have Assumed Human Nature In
All Individuals
Reply. It is denied that the human nature should be assumed by the Word in
all individuals: 1. because the multitude of supposita which are natural to
human nature, would thus be taken away; 2. because this would be derogatory to
the divinity of the incarnate Son of God since He is the first-born of many
brethren according to the human nature, even as He is the first-born of every
creature according to the divine nature. Finally, divine wisdom demands this
subordination, for St. Paul says: "For all are yours, and you are Christ's,
and Christ is God's."[714] It must be noted that, if the Son of God had
assumed the individualized nature of all human beings, then all human beings
would have been impeccable.
Sixth Article: Whether It Was Fitting For The Son Of God To Assume Human
Nature Of The Stock Of Adam
The Son of God could, indeed, have assumed the human nature created anew,
just as Adam was created.
Reply. The answer is, nevertheless, that it was fitting for the Son of God to
assume the human nature of the stock of Adam, and this for three reasons: 1. so
that He might satisfy for the race that had sinned; 2. because the conqueror of
the devil should come from the race conquered by the devil; 3. to manifest God's
omnipotence that. raised a weakened and corrupt nature to such virtue and
dignity. God permits evil only for a greater good.
Hence in the Roman Breviary, the Church recites: "That flesh hath
purged, what flesh hath stained."[715] The Scripture says: "Who can
make him clean that is conceived of unclean seed. Is it not Thou who only
art?"[716] Thus there are sinners in Christ's genealogy, although He is
separated from sinners in this respect.
Reply to first objection. Christ's innocence is the more wonderful in this,
that, although He assumed His nature from a mass tainted by sin, it was endowed
with such purity.
Reply to second objection. It was not fitting for the Word to assume the
particular nature of Adam, who was a sinner; because Christ, who had come to
cleanse all sinners, had to be separated from all who sinned.
Third objection. The difficulty is this: "If the Son of God wished to
assume human nature from sinners, He ought rather to have assumed it from the
Gentiles than from the stock of Abraham, who was just."
Reply to third objection. Christ, indeed, had to be like sinners in His
assumed nature, but He also had to be separated from them as regards sin. Hence
it was fitting that between the first sinner and Christ, some just men should
intervene, who were to be in certain respects conspicuous types of Christ's
future holiness, and these began in Abraham.
But why the Jewish race was chosen in preference to any of the Gentile
nations depends on God's absolute free choice, just as the predestination of
Christ, of His Blessed Mother, of Abraham, Isaac, Jacob, and the prophets are so
dependent. The mystery of predestination is apparent in the whole course of
Jewish history, since one is chosen in preference to another, for instance, Abel
to Cain, Noe to those who died in the flood, Isaac to another son of Abraham,
Jacob to Esau; and so it is with other descendants. It must be noted that the
merits of the elect are not the cause of their predestination, because they are
its effects. This is especially evident both as regards Christ's predestination
to divine natural sonship, and the predestination of the Blessed Virgin Mary to
divine maternity.
Supplementary Questions
First doubt. Does the human nature united with the Word still have an innate
desire for its own subsistence?
Reply. The common opinion of the Thomists, especially of Cajetan and John of
St. Thomas, is that it has no such desire as a reflected act (actus secundus),
because it is perfected by a more perfect subsistence, which contains formally
and eminently absolutely whatever there would be in its own subsistence.
Therefore the natural desire of the assumed human nature rests satisfied in the
higher subsistence.[717]
Second doubt. Can incomplete substances and accidents be assumed immediately
by the Word, such as prime matter, non-subsistent forms, for instance, the
substantial form of bread, or of another body?
Reply. The query is denied, because these incomplete realities are
intrinsically incapable of having their own subsistences. Thus prime matter, the
substantial form of bread, and accidents cannot be assumed except mediately,
that is, through the mediation of substance, whose parts they are, or in which
they inhere. But the rational soul separated from the body, which is capable of
having its own subsistence and existence, is assumable.
Corollary. Integral parts of the human body, such as the hand, the head,
feet, so long as they are united to the whole, cannot be assumed unless the
whole is assumed. But if these parts are separated by death, they can remain
united with the Word, because these parts separated from the whole are capable
of having their own subsistence and existence, distinct from the subsistence and
existence of the whole.
CHAPTER VII: QUESTION 5: THE MODE OF THE UNION CONCERNING
THE PARTS OF THE HUMAN NATURE ASSUMED
Since these parts are the body and soul, Docetism and Apollinarianism are
here refuted.
First Article: Whether The Son Of God Ought To Have Assumed A Human Body
It is of faith that the Word assumed a real body, and not a phantom or
shadow. This truth has been frequently defined in such councils as Nicaea,
Ephesus, Constantinople, Chalcedon, and others,[718] against the Marcionites and
Manichaeans, who attribute to Christ the semblance of a body, because they
thought every body comes from the principle of evil, and is evil. Simon Magus,
Saturninus, and Basilides are likewise condemned. This latter heresiarch, says
St. Irenaeus,[719] maintained that Simon of Cyrene was crucified instead of
Jesus, who exchanged external figure and countenance with Simon of Cyrene.
Scriptural proof. In the New Testament we read: "The Word was made
flesh."[720] And again: "Every spirit which confesseth that Jesus
Christ is come in the flesh, is of God. And every spirit that dissolveth Jesus,
is not of God."[721] St. Paul says: "Concerning His Son, who was made
to Him of the seed of David, according to the flesh."[722] Christ speaking
of Himself, says: "Behold we go up to Jerusalem, and the Son of man shall
be betrayed..., and crucified, and the third day He shall rise again."[723]
Finally, after the Resurrection, Jesus said: "Handle and see; for a spirit
hath not flesh and bones, as you see Me to have."[724]
Theological proof. It is taken especially from the arguments proposed by the
Fathers, especially from Tertullian,[725] and from St. Irenaeus.[726]
Three reasons are given in the body of the article. 1. Christ would not be a
true man if He did not have a true body. 2. If Christ is not truly man, then He
did not truly die, as narrated in the Gospels. 3. Jesus did not speak the truth
when He said: "Handle and see; for a spirit hath not flesh and bones, as
you see Me to have."[727]
Second Article: Whether The Son Of God Ought To Have Assumed An Earthly Body
This means: Ought Christ to have assumed flesh and blood, rather than a
heavenly body?
Reply. The answer is in the affirmative, and it is of faith against the
Valentinians, who said that Christ assumed a celestial body and passed through
the Blessed Virgin, as water flows through a channel.[728]
Scriptural proof. In the New Testament we read: "A spirit hath not flesh
and bones, as you see Me to have."[729] St. Paul says of Jesus: "He
was made to Him[Father] of the seed of David, according to the flesh."[730]
And again: "God sent His Son, made of a woman."[731] In Christ's
genealogy, it is said of Him: "Son of David, son of Abraham."[732] The
angel says to Mary: "Behold thou shalt conceive in thy womb and shalt bring
forth a son, and thou shalt call His name Jesus."[733] St. Joseph is also
declared to be "the husband of Mary, of whom was born Jesus."[734]
All these texts would not be true if Christ had come down from heaven with a
celestial body, and had merely passed through the Blessed Virgin, as through a
channel.
Theological proof. 1. If Christ had not assumed our nature, then He would not
be truly man, since flesh and bones are required for a nature to be truly human.
2. Also Christ would not have been really hungry, or have suffered and died, as
recorded in the Gospels. 3. He would have told a lie in presenting Himself to
men as having a body of flesh. If St. Paul says that "the first man was of
the earth, earthly: the second man from heaven, heavenly,"[735] this means
that Christ's body was formed from the womb of the Blessed Virgin Mary by a
heavenly power, namely, by the Holy Ghost.[736]
Reply to second objection. Christ came in passible flesh, "that He might
carry through the work of our redemption." Hence Christ's death was not the
result of original sin, but the consequence of a nature conceived in passible
flesh, and this consequence He offered in submission for our redemption.[737] He
submitted to the penalty of death not for Himself, but for our sake.
That the Word came, however, in passible and mortal flesh, rather than in
impassible flesh, presupposes Adam's sin, although in Christ death was not the
result of original sin, which He did not contract. The same must be said of the
Blessed Virgin, who was preserved from original sin.
Reply to third objection. It pertains to the greatest glory of God that He
raised a most weak and earthly body to such sublimity. It was mercy that moved
God to unite the highest with the lowest for our salvation. St. Thomas has
treated this question more fully in another work.[738]
Doubt. Was Christ's blood hypostatically united with the Word? This question
is of no slight importance, because it concerns the precious blood of Jesus
Christ that was shed in His passion and that is offered daily in the Mass.
This doubt was formerly the subject of much dispute. Durandus denied that the
Word hypostatically united with Himself the natural blood. Alphonsus Tostatus (Abulensis),[739]
Richard,[740] and several Franciscan theologians were of the same opinion. St.
Thomas took the affirmative view both here and in his commentary on the
resurrection of Christ.[741] The Thomists, Cajetan and Capreolus, and almost all
theologians are in agreement with St. Thomas on this point. Since this question
gave rise to bitter contention between the Franciscans and Dominicans, the
latter defending the doctrine of St. Thomas, Pius II (1464) issued a decree[742]
putting an end to these disputes, until it was defined what must be believed.
Later on, however, as Suarez observes, the Franciscan view was eliminated from
their schools of theology, as being neither pious nor safe teaching.
There are three proofs for this affirmative view, which is the one most
commonly held.[743]
Scriptural proof. St. Paul says: "Therefore because the children[i. e.,
men] are partakers of flesh and blood[i. e., are composed of flesh and blood],
He Himself[Christ] in like manner hath been partaker of the same."[744]
This same teaching is confirmed in other passages of Sacred Scripture, in
which our redemption is attributed to the blood of Christ, His Son, as in the
following text: "The blood of Christ, His Son, cleanseth us from all
sin."[745]
Authoritative proof. The Council of Trent, in its discussion on the Holy
Eucharist, affirms the natural union of the body and blood of Christ in these
words: "The body itself is under the species of bread, and the blood is
under the species of wine, and the soul under both, by the force of that natural
connection and concomitance, whereby the parts of Christ our Lord... are united
together."[746] Therefore the blood is a part of Christ.
Similarly Clement VI affirmed that the blood of Christ was united with the
Word, saying: "The innocent and immaculate lamb is known to have shed His
blood, a single drop of which, on account of its union with the Word, would have
sufficed[for our redemption].[747]
Theological proof. Blood is a necessary part of the human body because it is
required for its life and for the nutrition of its various parts, as also for
the natural process of combustion by which natural heat is generated.
Hence theologians maintain that there will be blood in glorified bodies,
inasmuch as this pertains to the integrity of the body.[748]
Confirmation of proof. From the definition of the Church on the Holy
Eucharist.
If the Word did not assume hypostatically the blood, then the Word is not by
concomitance under the species of wine. For that is by concomitance in the
sacrament which is united really and substantially with the primary term of the
consecration and conversion. But, if the Word did not assume hypostatically the
blood, the Word is not really and substantially united with the blood, which is
the primary term in the consecration of the chalice. Therefore, in this case,
the Word would not be by concomitance present under the species of wine, which
is contrary to the teaching of the Council of Trent.
Objection. Those holding the opposite opinion have said that blood is not
animated, and is not actually a part of the body. The Thomists contradict this
assertion, remarking that the blood is a fluid that contributes to the nutrition
of the other parts of the body.
Again the opponents object, saying: What the Word once assumed, remained
always united with Him. But He severed His union with the blood.
Reply. In answer to this, we say with St. Thomas:[749] I deny the minor; for
the blood of Christ, just as His corpse, although it was no longer animated,
remained hypostatically united with the Word during the triduum of death because
it had to be reassumed.[750] And if, during the triduum of death, there had been
the consecration of the wine in the chalice, the divinity would have been
present by concomitance under the species of wine, as the Council of Trent
declares.[751] This cannot be said of Christ's blood that was shed at the
circumcision, because it was not intended to be reassumed.
It must be observed that when St. Thomas says: "All the blood which
flowed from Christ's body, belonging as it does to the integrity of human
nature, rose again with His body,"[752] this must be understood of all the
blood shed in a moral sense, but not of absolutely all the blood in a physical
sense. As Pius II says, it is not contrary to faith for one to assert that a
portion of the blood that was shed by Christ on the cross, or at the crowning of
thorns, was not reassumed; but then this portion of blood, if it was not
reassumed, was not hypostatically united with the Word, because, just as in the
case of the blood shed at the circumcision, this blood was not indeed intended
to be reassumed in the resurrection for the integrity of Christ's body. What has
been said suffices, in our days, for the solution of this doubt that was
formerly disputed.
Third Article: Whether The Son Of God Assumed A Soul
State of the question. The next two articles are written in refutation of
Apollinaris and Arius, who first of all denied that Christ had a soul; then,
retracting this former opinion, they granted that He had a soul, but it was not
an intellectual soul, saying that the Word took the place of the intellect.
The Council of Ephesus defined against these heretics that the Word assumed
an intellectual soul.[753]
Scriptural proof. Our Lord says of Himself: "My soul is sorrowful even
unto death."[754] And again: "Father, into Thy hands I commend My
spirit."[755]
St. Thomas explains in the body of the article that these words cannot be
taken metaphorically, especially because the Gospel says that Jesus wondered,
was angry, and hungry. These acts belong to a soul that is both intellectual and
sensitive.
Theological proof. The principal reason given in the theological proof is
that Christ would be neither truly man nor the Son of man as declared in the
Gospel, unless He had a soul; and thus there would be no more any truth to the
Incarnation.
Reply to first objection. If St. John says in his prologue, "And the
Word was made flesh," flesh is taken for the whole man, just as sometimes
in Sacred Scripture we read such assertions as, "All flesh shall see that
the mouth of the Lord hath spoken."[756]
Reply to second objection. The Word is the effective cause of Christ's human
life, the soul is its formal cause, and hence it is not useless. Moreover, the
Word cannot be the formal cause of the human body, because the formal cause is
the intrinsic cause and therefore is a part of the composite, not so perfect as
the composite. But this cannot be said of the uncreated Word.
Fourth Article: Whether The Son Of God Assumed A Human Mind Or Intellect
Reply. That the Son of God assumed an intellect has been defined against the
Arians and Apollinarians as belonging to the faith.
Scriptural proof. Jesus says: "Learn of Me because I am meek and humble
of heart."[757] Christ was also obedient and merited, which was possible
only if He had a human intellect and a human will; for the divine intellect and
the divine will cannot be the principle of an act of obedience as regards a
higher will.
Theological proof. The principal reason in this proof is that, if Christ did
not have a human intellect, then He was not truly man, which is contrary both to
what He Himself said and to Scripture.
CHAPTER VIII: QUESTION 6: THE ORDER OF ASSUMPTION
State of the question. This question is inserted here especially because of
Origen's error that was condemned by Pope Vigilius in the following canon:
"If anyone says or thinks that our Lord's soul existed and was united with
God, the Word, prior to His incarnation and birth from the Virgin, let him be
anathema."[758]
Origen said that Christ's soul was created at the beginning of the world, and
by the performance of good works merited to be united hypostatically with the
Word, and was de facto united with the Word, before it was united with the body
in the womb of the Blessed Virgin. Hence Vigilius declared: "If anyone says
or thinks that the body of our Lord Jesus Christ was first formed in the womb of
the Blessed Virgin, and that afterward God the Word and the soul were united
with it, as if He had already existed, let him be anathema."[759]
Hence the teaching of the Church as defined against Origen is that Christ's
soul and body, or His entire humanity, was at the same moment assumed by the
Word. St. Thomas explains this teaching of the Church especially in the third
article of this question. In the other articles, however, especially in the
fifth, he considers what was assumed by priority of nature, both on the part of
the agent assuming and according to his intention, and thus the entire human
nature of Christ was first assumed; and also he considers what was first assumed
on the part of the subject assumed in the order of execution, and thus the parts
were assumed before the whole, and so the soul was first assumed, and the body
through the soul as intermediary, and finally the whole as resulting from each,
or the complete human nature.
Thus this distinction being established between priority of time and priority
of nature together with the aforesaid subdistinction, the whole of this question
will be understood.
First Article: Whether The Son Of God Assumed Flesh Through The Medium Of The
Soul
State of the question. In this article soul and body are compared in
accordance with the natural order, and thus this article is distinct from the
third, although for the benefit of the doctrine St. Thomas begins by
distinguishing between the temporal order and the natural order.
There are two conclusions.
First conclusion. In the order of time the Word united the whole human nature
of Christ to Himself simultaneously, at the very moment of the creation of
Christ's soul.[760]
This conclusion is defined to be of faith against Origen.[761] It will be
explained more fully farther on,[762] when St. Thomas, discussing Christ's
conception, shows that it is contrary to the faith to say that Christ's flesh
was first conceived and afterward was assumed by the Word of God. This assertion
is against Photinus who said that Christ was first a mere man and afterward by
the sanctity of His life came to be considered the Son of God.[763] In such a
case, the Blessed Virgin would not be the Mother of God.
St. Thomas gives us the reason for this conclusion in these words: "If
Christ's flesh had been conceived before being assumed by the Word, it would
have been at some time a hypostasis other than that of the Word of
God,"[764] and so there would have been two hypostases in the Word
incarnate, or one would have been destroyed, which is not fitting. Hence
Christ's entire humanity was simultaneously assumed.
Second conclusion. In the natural order, however, the Word instantaneously
united the flesh with Himself, through the intermediary of the soul, since the
soul is mediating link by reason of its dignity and causality. There is clearly
here a distinction between priority of time, which is denied, and priority of
nature which is affirmed, inasmuch as the very moment that Christ's soul was
created, the Word assumed the flesh through the mediation of the soul; otherwise
the flesh would not be human.
Third objection. It must be noted that St. Thomas says that, if the medium is
taken away, then the extremes are separated. But the soul is taken away by
death, though the union of the Word with the flesh still remains; for "what
is bestowed through God's grace is never withdrawn except through
fault."[765] Therefore the Word was not united with the flesh through the
mediation of the soul.
Reply to third objection. The soul, before its separation from the body,
rendered the latter apt for assumption, though it did not sever the union of the
Word with the flesh; just as the loss of a woman's beauty, though this beauty
contributed to her fittingness for marriage, does not sever the marriage bond.
Second Article: Whether The Son Of God Assumed A Soul Through The Medium Of
The Spirit Or Mind
The purpose of this article is to explain the following text of St.
Augustine, quoted in the counter-argument: "The invisible and unchangeable
Truth took a soul by means of the spirit, and a body by means of the soul."
Conclusion. The Word assumed by means of the mind the other parts of the
soul, just as He assumed the body by means of the soul, on account of the
dignity of the order and the congruity of the assumption; for mind is the
highest part of the soul in its relation to the sensitive soul.[766] What is
meant by mind is the essence of the spiritual soul from which the higher
faculties are derived, those that are purely spiritual, namely, the intellect
and will.
Third Article: Whether The Soul Was Assumed Before The Flesh By The Son Of
God
This article is strictly concerned with priority of time, for the purpose of
denying such priority against Origen, and thus it differs from the first
article. Origen not only maintained that all immortal souls were created in the
beginning along with the angels, before they were united to bodies, but he also
said this especially of Christ's soul, inasmuch as it is nobler than the angels.
Reply. The answer is that Christ's soul was not created prior to its union
with the Word, and it is of faith, as evident from the condemnation of Origen by
Pope Vigilius.[767]
In the counter-argument St. Thomas quotes the authority of St. John
Damascene, who most clearly is against Origen's opinion.
Theological proof. It shows the unfittingness of Origen's view. It is
derogatory to Christ's dignity to suppose that His soul was created before its
assumption, because then it would have had its own subsistence, and hence there
would be two subsistences in Christ, and two supposita, or else one subsistence
would have been destroyed, which is unbecoming to Christ, as well as being a
mere assertion without any foundation.
Likewise it is derogatory to Christ's dignity to suppose that His soul was
created and simultaneously assumed before His body was formed, because then this
soul of Christ would not seem to be of the same nature as our souls, which are
created at the same time that they are infused into our bodies, inasmuch as it
is the very nature of the soul to be the form of the body, and thus it differs
from the angels.
As St. Thomas says in this article, quoting St. Leo: "Christ's soul
excels our soul not by diversity of genus, but by sublimity of power."[768]
Doubt. Is St. Thomas speaking only of sublimity of supernatural power, that
is, of plenitude of grace, whereby Christ's most holy soul excels the sanctity
even of the first and second highest among the choirs of angels, namely, the
seraphim and cherubim; or has he in mind the natural and individual nobility of
the soul, whereby Christ's soul excels in nobility the soul of any human being?
Reply. The holy Doctor admits inequality of power among human souls in the
same species.[769]
Since matter and form are mutually causes, and "since the form is not
for the matter, but rather the matter for the form,"[770] Providence made
Christ's body more apt for its union with the nobler part, which is the soul,
just as He made the body of the Blessed Virgin Mary more fitting so that she
might be worthy of becoming the Mother of God.
St. Thomas says: "It is plain that the better the disposition of a body,
the better the soul allotted to it. This clearly appears in things of different
species, and the reason thereof is that act and form are received into matter
according to the capacity of matter. Thus, because some men have bodies of
better disposition, their souls have a greater power of understanding, wherefore
it is said that it is to be observed that 'those who have soft flesh are of apt
mind.’[771] Secondly, this occurs in regard to the lower powers of which the
intellect has need in its operations; for those in whom the imaginative,
cogitative, and memorative powers are of better disposition, are better disposed
to understand."[772]
St. Thomas applies this teaching to Christ, showing that the body was
miraculously formed from the most pure blood of the Blessed Virgin Mary.[773]
On the one hand, the soul, although it is created and not educed from matter,
thus depends materially, but not intrinsically, on the body, and therefore it
can continue to exist after its separation from the body.
On the other hand, the body is better disposed, inasmuch as it depends
finally and formally and in some way in the evolution of the embryo efficiently
on the better disposed soul. Hence St. Thomas says: "What is received in
anything can be considered both being and perfection. According to its being it
is in the one in which it is received, after the manner of the recipient;
nevertheless, the one that received it is drawn to its perfection."[774]
Thus heat is received in water, light in the air, the soul in the body, grace in
the soul, and the subject that receives is made conformable to the perfection
received.
So there is a mutual transcendental relation between matter and form, body
and soul, which therefore remains individuated after its separation from the
body by reason of this transcendental relation to the body, which will be again
informed by the soul on the day of the resurrection of the dead.
Father Gredt correctly remarks that "one human soul differs from another
in perfection substantially, of course, though not essentially but accidentally,
taking the word 'accidentally' as a predicable accident,"[775] but not as a
predicamental accident, which is an operative faculty that is really distinct
from substance. Thus the soul of Christ, even as a substance, is individually,
although not specifically, nobler than the soul of any other human being, just
as His body, which was miraculously formed in the womb of the Blessed Virgin
Mary, was better disposed than any other human body whatever. It is also evident
that the souls of great doctors of the Church, in which there are signs of great
genius, are individually nobler than many other souls.
Thus we have a beautiful verification of the principle that causes mutually
interact, but in a different genus; for the form determines the matter, and the
latter is ordained for the form, as also the agent attains the end which
attracts it.
Fourth Article: Whether The Flesh Of Christ Was Assumed By The Word Before
Being United With The Soul
State of the question. This article concerns priority of time. The purpose of
this article, as stated in the first and second difficulties, is that, according
to the teaching of the ancient philosophers, in the conception of other men,
living flesh is found in possession of vegetative life, and already of the
sensitive life, before the rational soul, which is created by God, comes to it.
Thus in the first two objections of this article, disposition of the matter
precedes the coming of the form, and in human beings, the body is conceived
before the rational soul comes to it.
But, on the other hand, as we stated in the first article, it is evident,
concerning the condemnation of Origen's teaching, that the Word assumed
simultaneously the flesh and soul of Christ, for flesh is not human before the
soul comes to it.
This question presupposes another, namely, whether Christ's flesh was
conceived or formed, at least in accordance with its remote natural
dispositions, before it was united with the rational soul. The solution of the
present article depends on this query, but this point concerns the question of
Christ's conception, and is therefore explained farther on.[776]
In the passage quoted above, St. Thomas shows that it is against the faith to
say that Christ's flesh was first conceived, and afterward was animated and
assumed by the Word. This is evident from what the Church has declared against
Origen and against Photinus.[777]
Reply. Christ's flesh ought not to have been assumed before the soul.
Authoritative proof. St. John Damascene says: "At the same time the Word
of God was made flesh, and flesh was united to a rational and intellectual
soul."[778] This means to say that Christ's flesh was conceived, animated,
and assumed simultaneously. This is what the Church declares against Origen and
against Photinus.[779]
Theological proof. It is expressed briefly in the last line of the
argumentative part of the article. Flesh is not strictly human before it
receives the rational soul. But the Word assumed only strictly human flesh.
Therefore flesh ought not to have been assumed before the soul.
This is well explained in the body of the article. For human flesh is
assumable by the Word according to the order it has to the rational soul. But it
has not (at least this immediate) order, before the rational soul comes to it;
because the moment that the matter is ultimately disposed for the form, it also
receives the form. The whole article must be read.[780]
But how is the difficulty that is presented in the first objection to be
solved. It states that our bodies are conceived before they are animated by the
rational soul. St. Thomas admits this statement as at least probable in fact,
inasmuch as the body first has the vegetative life, then the sensitive life,
before it is ultimately disposed for the rational soul, which is created by God
instantaneously from nothing, and is not educed from matter.
St. Thomas replies to the first objection of this article, saying that it is
certainly so with us, remarking that "before the coming of the human soul,
there is no human flesh," but there is in the body a previous but not
ultimate disposition for human flesh. He goes on to say: "In the conception
of Christ, the Holy Ghost, who is an agent of infinite might, disposed the
matter and brought it to its perfection at the same time." Likewise, he
says farther on: "Christ's body, on account of the infinite power of the
agent, was perfectly disposed instantaneously. Wherefore at once and in the
first instant it received a perfect form, that is, the rational soul."[781]
Farther on he says: "Christ's conception must be said to be entirely
miraculous (on the part of the active power), and in a qualified manner natural
(on the part of the matter contributed by the mother)."[782]
Thus in the miraculous conversion of water into wine at Cana, the matter of
water (without any previous dispositions) is disposed to receive the form of
wine. So also, in the operational order, the conversion of St. Paul was
instantaneous; similarly the sanctification of the Blessed Virgin Mary took
place at the very moment of her conception, inasmuch as, when her soul was
created, it instantaneously received a plenitude of grace, and was preserved
from original sin through the merits of Christ. So too, in the natural order,
men of great genius solve problems, but, at times, they do not sufficiently
prepare their pupils to understand their teaching, which is then understood in a
wrong sense, and thus these pupils fall into error.
Different from Christ's conception, St. Thomas does not admit that the
rational soul of the Blessed Virgin Mary was created at the moment of her
conception, for he distinguishes between this moment and the moment after the
animation of her flesh. In this he distinguishes between the virginal conception
of Christ and that of the Blessed Virgin Mary, which was not miraculous,
inasmuch as her conception was not virginal, but natural; for she was born in a
natural way from a father and mother. St. Thomas asks whether the Blessed Virgin
Mary was sanctified before animation, which is distinct from the passive
conception of the body. But complete passive conception of the body, inasmuch as
it is distinct from the beginning of this conception, took place in the Blessed
Virgin at the same time as animation, which is the usual procedure in human
beings.[783]
Reply to third objection. The conception, animation, and assumption of
Christ's body were instantaneous. But by priority of nature the body was
preserved by the Word as a being, before its animation, because the body is
first a being, and then a body.
Nevertheless, as regards the personal union, Christ's body was, in accordance
with nature, first united with the soul, before it was united with the Word,
because it is from its union with the soul that it is capable of being united
with the Word in person; especially since a person, as such, is found only in
the rational nature. So it was that during the three days in which our Lord's
body was separated from the soul, the Word was not united personally but only
subsistentially with Christ's corpse. The entire reply to the third objection
should be read.
A question that deserves special attention is: When is the rational soul
created? Does this take place at the moment of conception or afterward? Father
Gredt says: "The ancient philosophers taught that, first of all, ... the
merely vegetative soul that is imperfect and transitory would be educed, and
this soul by a process of evolution would become corrupt and would be
substituted by another that is imperfect, the sensitive soul, which also becomes
corrupt, and forty days after conception the rational soul would finally be
created and infused into the body." "Nevertheless," says Father
Gredt, "it is better to say with modern philosophers that from the very
beginning the germinal cells are united, and there is present a special
organization and proximate disposition for the infusion of the rational soul,
which is therefore created and infused by God, without the intervention of any
other soul.[784]
On the contrary, Father Barbado, O. P., says: "It is not our purpose to
decide this question that is so much disputed among Scholastics. However, we
must point out that experience shows the foundation for this traditional view,
which the ancient philosophers took from embryology, is strongly supported by
present-day investigations.... For the egg, in the segmentation process and the
follicles in the blastodermic process do not possess actually but only
potentially the future organization, and it is only much later that the organs
come to perfection."[785]
Moreover, after death or the separation of the rational soul from the body,
facts seem to attest that for some time the vegetative soul remains, since the
hair and nails still grow. If such be the case after the separation of the
rational soul from the body, why not before the creation of the soul?
Fifth Article: Whether The Whole Human Nature Was Assumed Through The Medium
Of The Parts
This title is not concerned with the order of time, but with that of nature.
State of the question. The purpose of the article is to explain what St.
Augustine means when he says, as quoted in the first objection: "The
invisible and unchangeable Truth assumed the soul through the medium of the
spirit, and the body through the medium of the soul, and in this way the whole
man." We stated in the first article that the Word assumed flesh through
the medium of the soul. But the whole human nature results from the union of the
parts.
Conclusion. The Word of God assumed the human nature through the medium of
the whole. This means the body and the soul, because of their relation to the
whole. Evidently the article is concerned only with the order of nature and not
with that of time.
Authoritative proof. It is taken from St. John Damascene, who is quoted in
the counter-argument.
Theological proof. The order of nature, which concerns us here, is of two
kinds. It may be considered either on the part of the agent assuming, or on the
part of the subject assumed. In the Incarnation, however, our attention must be
given especially to the first kind, because the whole idea of the deed is
estimated from the omnipotence of the agent.
But on the part of the agent, that is absolutely first which is first in
intention, which is to assume the entire human nature. Therefore the Word of God
assumed the parts of the human nature through the medium of the whole, or on
account of the whole that was first intended.[786]
Sixth Article: Whether The Human Nature Was Assumed Through The Medium Of
Grace
This article is inserted here because of the necessity of explaining the
threefold meaning of the word "grace."
1) There is a certain grace that is the uncreated will of God freely doing or
donating something. In this sense, it is called effective grace, but not formal
grace.
2) In Christ there is the grace of union which is formally in Him, and it is
the very personal being of the Word, which terminates, possesses, and sanctifies
the human nature of Christ.
3) Habitual grace is also formally in Christ, inhering in His soul' as an
accident, which will be more clearly explained in the following question.
Two conclusions follow from this distinction.
1) The hypostatic union did not take place through the medium of the grace of
union or through the medium of habitual grace. For the grace of union is the
very personal being of Christ, which is the term of the assumption. Habitual
grace, which inheres in the soul of Christ, is the consequent effect of the
hypostatic union, and this will be made clearer in the following question.
2) The hypostatic union took place by grace that is God's uncreated will, not
as a medium, but as efficient cause.
Thus St. Thomas, speaking of the grace that predestines the elect, inquires
whether predestination places anything in the predestined, and he replies:
"Predestination is not anything in the predestined, but only in the person
who predestines.... But the execution of predestination, which is the calling,
the justification, the magnification, is in the predestined."[787]
Doubt. Is there a created actuation produced by the uncreated act in the
hypostatic union by the very fact that Christ's human nature began to be
actuated terminatively by the Word, as Father de la Taille contends? Is the
grace of union in Christ anything created, as St. Thomas maintains?
This question is about the same as that concerning the substantial mode
whereby Christ's humanity is united with the Word.[788]
Reply. Both parts of the question are denied. St. Thomas says in the present
article: "The grace of union is the personal being that is given gratis
from above to the human nature in the person of the Word," and therefore it
cannot be understood in the sense of a created medium, a created actuation that
is produced by the uncreated act. The grace of union is not something created,
but it is the very Word that terminates the human nature, both possessing and
sanctifying it.
Likewise, when St. Thomas inquires about the union of the two natures in
Christ, as to whether it was effected by grace, he replies: "If grace be
understood as the will of God gratuitously doing something, ... then the union
of the Incarnation took place by grace, ... but not as though there were a
habitual grace by means of which the union took place."[789] It would have
been so, however, if there were a created and indeed supernatural actuation
produced by the uncreated act.
St. Thomas says, too, in the present article: "Grace is an accidental
perfection of the soul, and therefore it cannot ordain the soul to personal
union, which is not accidental."[790]
We have already quoted the passage in which St. Thomas says: "It must be
known that in the union of the divine nature and the human nature, there can be
no medium that formally causes the union, to which the human nature is
previously joined before it is united with the divine person; just as there can
be no mediating being between matter and form, which would be previously in the
matter before the substantial form, otherwise accidental being would be prior to
substantial being, which is impossible. So also, between nature and suppositum
there can be no medium in the above-mentioned manner, since each conjunction is
for substantial union."[791] But it is shown that the union, as a real
relation of the human nature with the Word, is the consequent or resulting
effect; for St. Thomas says: "This relation follows, which is called union;
hence union is the medium, not as causing the assumption, but as following
it."[792]
St. Thomas also shows elsewhere that the union is declared to be something
created since it is a real relation of Christ's human nature to the Word, but it
is only a logical relation of the Word to the human nature. Thus creation in the
passive sense is a real relation of the creature to the Creator.[793]
As we remarked above,[794] it cannot properly be said that the human nature
undergoes a change in its assumption by the Word, and that this change is the
finite actuation produced by the uncreated act.
St. Thomas shows that we look upon creation as a change, whereas in reality
it is not a change, saying: "Change means that the same something should be
different now from what it was previously."[795] But this is impossible in
the case of creation, and even in the assumption of Christ's humanity, because
the subject that is to undergo the change is not as yet in existence. As Thomas
says, "When motion is removed from action and passion, only relation
remains."[796] Hence passive creation is simply a relation of dependence,
which is likewise the case with Christ's hypostatic union. This means that
Christ's human nature is dependent on the Word.
Likewise the formal effect is not distinct from the form that is received in
the subject. Thus the formal effect of whiteness is to make a thing white, and
it is only by this whiteness that anything is white. Similarly man is made
pleasing to God by habitual grace.
Matter is also actuated by form, and there is no distinction between this
actuation and its substantial form, otherwise, as St. Thomas stated above,
"accidental being would be prior to substantial being, which is
impossible."[797]
But if the actuation of prime matter is the same as the formal act that it
receives, so also the actuation produced by the uncreated act cannot be anything
created, because then there would be a real and infinite distinction between it
and the uncreated act.
Thus we terminate the metaphysical questions concerning the mode of the union
of the human nature with the Word, first in itself, and then on the part of the
person assuming, and of the human nature that is assumed together with its
parts, as also the order in which these parts are assumed. Let us pass on now to
consider questions that are not so much metaphysical as psychological and
spiritual, and that concern the co-assumed parts, such as Christ's grace,
knowledge, power, His sensitive nature or His propassions. But metaphysical
questions will again arise, when we consider the consequences of the hypostatic
union,[798] namely, the truth of the propositions because of the personal unity
in Christ, and when we come to inquire whether there is unity of being in
Christ, just as there is unity of person in Him.[799]
It is already to some extent apparent that the answer will be in the
affirmative.
CHAPTER IX: QUESTION 7: THE THINGS CO-ASSUMED THE GRACE OF
CHRIST
Having considered the nature that was assumed, we pass on to n treat of what
pertains to the perfection of Christ's human nature, namely, His grace,
knowledge, and power; then we shall discuss His passibility together with His
sensitive nature. The thirteenth question is concerned with Christ's human will,
namely, with those things that pertain to the conformity of the two wills in
Christ. There are two questions on Christ's grace, namely: (1) Christ's grace as
an individual man (q. 7); (2) Christ's grace as the head of the Church (q. 8).
Theologians generally distinguish between two graces in Christ: (1) the grace
of union, that is, His personal being that is gratuitously given by God to His
human nature; (2) His habitual grace, as an individual man and as head of the
Church.
In the seventh question St. Thomas, in discussing Christ's habitual grace as
an individual man, includes the whole organism of the supernatural life in
Christ's most holy soul, namely, the grace that is called "the grace of the
virtues and of the gifts"; in that the virtues and the gifts belong
properly to this grace. He also treats of the graces gratis datae and of the
plenitude of Christ's grace. Some might object to the order followed in these
questions, and say that the present problem, just as the question concerning the
union of wills in Christ, ought to be relegated to the latter part of this
treatise, when the consequences of the union are discussed.
The answer must be, in all probability, that the proper place to discuss the
things co-assumed on the part of the human nature is here; whereas, on the
contrary, from the sixteenth to the twenty-sixth questions inclusive, those
things consequent to the union of the two natures are discussed, namely,
Christ's unity as regards being, will, and operation, as also His relation to
the Father, and to us, for example, that Christ must be worshiped as God.[800]
Hence the proper place to discuss the things co-assumed is here, this being
the truly logical order, after the consideration of the nature that was assumed.
Hence, after consideration of the nature that was assumed, the truly logical
order is to discuss the things that were co-assumed, from the seventh question
to the fifteenth question.
There are three parts to this seventh question.
First part. It discusses habitual grace, the virtues and gifts in Christ (a.
1-6).
Second part. It treats of the graces freely bestowed upon Christ by His
heavenly Father.
Third part. It is concerned with the plenitude of Christ's grace (a. 9-13).
All these articles pertain to Christ's sanctity. But after the time of St.
Thomas, Christ's sanctity was discussed more in detail by way of a preliminary
question, which is usually inserted here by way of a preliminary by the
Thomists. The precise purport of this question is to settle the doubt whether
the substantial grace of union sanctifies formally or merely radically Christ's
human nature.
This question must be examined here since it serves as an introduction to the
articles of the seventh question, enabling us to understand them better, for the
substantial grace and uncreated grace of union is, so to speak, the radical
cause of habitual grace, or the grace of the virtues and gifts in Christ.
Preliminary Question: Christ's Substantial Grace Of Union As The Source Of
His Sanctification
State of the question. Gonet observes: "It is a question of three kinds
of grace, to which St. John briefly and indirectly alludes. For concerning the
substantial grace of union, he says: 'The Word was made flesh.’[801]
Concerning Christ's habitual grace as an individual person, he adds: 'We saw His
glory full of grace and truth.’ Finally, there is indirect allusion to
Christ's grace as head of the Church when, farther on he says: 'And of His
fullness we have all received.’ "[802]
Cajetan observes in his commentary at the beginning of this seventh question
that St. Thomas already discussed the grace of union, not under the name of
grace, however, but inasmuch as it is the hypostatic union of Christ's human
nature with the Word. But when the question arose, whether Christ's human nature
is formally sanctified by the substantial and uncreated grace of union, then
Durandus[803] and the Scotists said that Christ's human nature is not formally
but only radically sanctified by the grace of union. The affirmative opinion
prevails as the more general one among, Thomist theologians and those of other
schools, which is the conclusion we come to from the teaching of the councils
and the Fathers of the Church, and there is more than an indirect reference to
this opinion in the passages we shall quote from St. Thomas. Of this opinion are
John of St. Thomas, Godoy, Soto, Salmanticenses, Gonet, Billuart, and more
recent Thomists, as also Suarez, de Lugo, Valentia, Vasquez, Franzelin, Billot,
Hurter, and Pesch. It is the common and certain doctrine.[804]
Thesis. Christ's human nature is not only radically, but also formally
sanctified by the substantial and uncreated union of the Word with the human
nature.
In other words, Christ's sanctity is not accidental, but it is also
substantial and uncreated, because it began at the very moment of His virginal
conception. To understand this doctrine we must recall what sanctity is. St.
Thomas says that sanctity is steadfast union with God, which implies
"stainless purity."[805]
This steadfast union is unchangeable in heaven or among the blessed. The just
have not as yet in this life attained to this unchangeableness, but, as St.
Thomas says,[806] the holiness of the wayfarer causes him to direct his thoughts
and actions toward God or is firmly turned to Him.
There is a twofold acceptation of sanctity as thus defined.
1) It may mean the proximately operative virtue of good, and in this sense
there is no difference between it and the virtue of religion that is commanded
by the theological virtues and that firmly directs all our actions to the
worship of God.
2) It may be regarded as the foundation for this union with God, and thus in
us it is habitual grace, which for this reason is called sanctifying grace, or
the grace that unites us with God and makes us pleasing to Him.
All admit that Christ, as God, possesses essential and uncreated sanctity.
But the question is whether the uncreated and substantial grace of union
sanctifies Christ's human nature radically, namely, in that it is the source of
habitual grace, or whether it sanctifies His human nature formally, that is, in
the true and strict sense of the word, independently even of habitual grace.
Likewise, farther on there will be a question of whether the grace of union
suffices for the negative effect of sanctity, namely, impeccability; and the
answer will be in the affirmative.
1) Teaching of the Fathers on Christ's sanctity. The passages commonly quoted
are as follows:
St. Cyril: "Christ was anointed not as other saints and kings are; but
because the Word is flesh,"[807] that is, because the Word was made flesh.
St. Gregory Nazianzen: "Christ is so called because of His divine
nature; for that is the unction of His human nature, which is not effected by
operation, as in others that are anointed, but Christ is sanctified by the
presence of the whole divine unction."[808]
St. John Damascene: "He[Christ I anointed Himself, which means that as
God, He anointed His body by His divine nature; He was anointed, however, as
man.... Moreover, the divinity is the unction of His humanity."[809]
St. Augustine, commenting on this scriptural text, "that they also may
be sanctified in truth,"[810] says: "The Son of man was sanctified
from the beginning of His creation, when the Word was made flesh; because one
person became Word and man. Therefore He was sanctified by Himself in Himself;
because the one Christ, who is Word and man, sanctifies the man in the
Word."[811]
In another work St. Augustine says likewise: "Christ... was known to be
anointed by that mystic and invisible union, at the time when the Word was made
flesh, namely, when the human nature, without any previous merits because of
good works, was united with the Word of God in the womb of the Virgin so as to
become one person with the Word."[812]
2) St. Thomas says in a similar manner: "The grace of union is the
personal being that is given gratis from above to the human nature in the person
of the Word, and it is the term of the assumption, whereas the habitual grace
pertaining to the spiritual holiness of the man is an effect following the
union."[813] But the effect, inasmuch as it is a consequent accident,
presupposes substantial sanctity.
Likewise St. Thomas,[814] in proving the necessity of habitual grace in
Christ, does not seek the reason for it in His already established sanctity by
the grace of union, but he explains it: (1) because of the union of His soul
with the Word; (2) because it had to be the connatural principle of knowledge
and love in the supernatural order; (3) on account of Christ's relation to the
human race, since He is its head.
Hence St. Thomas does not say that Christ's habitual grace is sanctifying
grace. In fact, he says farther on that Christ's human nature during the Passion
had "the actual holiness of a victim, from the charity which it had from
the beginning, and from the grace of union sanctifying it absolutely."[815]
St. Thomas speaks in similar terms when discussing the plenitude of Christ's
grace. After having said that by habitual grace man is united to God by love, he
adds: "There is another kind of union of man with God, which is not only
accomplished by love or the indwelling of the Holy Spirit, but also by the unity
of the hypostasis.... And this belongs properly to Jesus Christ...and makes Him
most pleasing to God, so that it may be said of Him as an individual: This is my
beloved Son in whom I am well pleased."[816]
Again, when St. Thomas asks whether Christ can be called the adopted Son of
God, he replies: "The sonship of adoption is a participated likeness of
natural sonship; nor can a thing be said to participate in what it has
essentially. Therefore Christ, who is the natural Son of God, can nowise be
called an adopted Son."[817]
He also shows that Christ, as man, was predestined primarily and principally
for natural and divine sonship, or for the grace of union, and secondarily and
consequently for habitual grace and glory, as the effects of the grace of
union.[818] St. Thomas, in his comment on the scriptural text, "Whom the
Father hath sanctified and sent into the world,"[819] referring to St.
Hilary, likewise says: "He precedes the rest by this, that He was
sanctified as the Son."[820] Hence St. Thomas taught even explicitly the
doctrine of the present thesis, and, though he did not use the same terminology
as nowadays, yet he expressed himself in equivalent terms.
Theological proof. This proof from reason that is proposed in various ways by
the Thomists, may be clearly expressed by the following syllogism.
Formal sanctity which the just possess by reason of sanctifying grace,
includes but four requisite conditions. But these four requisite conditions are
found in Christ solely because of the grace of union, even independently of
habitual grace. Therefore the substantial grace of union is what formally
constitutes sanctity in Christ. Therefore His sanctity is innate, substantial,
and increate. Accidental sanctity, which results from habitual grace is derived
from this grace of union.
Proof of major. Formal sanctity about which we are concerned, is not a
proximately operative virtue that is really distinct from the virtue of
religion, but it is that union with God which the just have by reason of
habitual or sanctifying grace. This formal sanctity, however, includes but four
necessary conditions, so that the just person be formally holy. These conditions
are the following.
1) That the person be united with God and somehow drawn into union with the
divine being.
2) That the person be constituted the son of God, heir of His kingdom,
pleasing to Him and loved by Him.
3) That the person be radically disposed to perform supernaturally good
works.
4) That the principle of life is in such a person, which principle is
incompatible with mortal sin.
All these four conditions are fully explained in that part of the treatise in
which habitual or sanctifying grace is discussed, or that grace which makes us
pleasing to God.
Minor. But Christ possesses these four conditions in a much higher degree by
reason of His substantial and increate grace of union, even independently of
habitual grace. For 1) by the grace of union, Christ's human nature is more
perfectly drawn to and united with the divine nature than by habitual grace. For
Christ's human nature is drawn to the divine nature as it is in Itself, and not
merely to a participation in the divine nature. It is also united with the
divine nature not merely accidentally and lovingly, but substantially and
personally.
2) By the grace of union, Christ as man becomes the natural Son and heir of
God, most pleasing to Him and loved by Him, whereas by habitual grace man
becomes merely the adopted son of God. St. Thomas shows that love on God's part
is the diffusion of good, and He could not confer a greater good on the human
nature than to give Himself substantially to it.[821]
3) The grace of union makes Christ the principium quod[822] of theandric
operations that are infinitely meritorious, whereas Christ has need of habitual
grace only so that these supernatural operations be elicited connaturally by His
human faculties.
4) Finally, the hypostatic union implies greater incompatibility with sin
than habitual grace does, for, as will be stated farther on, not only is this
union incompatible with mortal sin, but even with the slightest sin, and it
makes such a man not only sinless, but absolutely impeccable.[823]
Therefore the conclusion follows that the substantial grace of union is what
makes Christ formally holy, and this holiness is not accidental, but
substantial, increate, and also innate.
Confirmation. By the grace of union, Christ is the natural Son of God. To be
the natural Son of God means the maximum of sanctity, or the greatest of union
with God and of supernatural union with Him, in accordance with what the Father
said: "This is My beloved Son, in whom I am well pleased."[824]
Objection. The grace of union cannot make a man formally blessed. Therefore
it cannot make him formally holy.
Reply. I deny the consequent. The difference between the two is that formal
blessedness is a vital act consisting in the vision and love of God; formal
holiness, however, with which we are here concerned, consists in habitual union
with God, which is ordered to right action; and just as habitual grace gives one
a right to eternal happiness, provided this grace be not lost by mortal sin, so
a fortiori does the grace of union..
Again I insist. But if the Word were to assume an irrational nature, for
example, a dove or a lamb, such a creature would not be sanctified by the Word.
Reply. The reason for this lack of sanctification would be that such subject
or nature that is assumed is incapable of it; in fact, the Word would not give
personality but only subsistence to such a nature. Likewise during the three
days of Christ's death, the Word remained united with Christ's corpse, not
because it was a person, but because it was a suppositum.
Another objection. The divine nature can formally sanctify Christ's human
nature only by intrinsically perfecting it and really changing it as its
intrinsic form. But the divine nature cannot be in relation to Christ's human
nature as its intrinsic form. Therefore the divine nature cannot formally
sanctify Christ's human nature. This means that Christ's human nature would be
holy only by extrinsic denomination.
Reply. I distinguish the major: unless the divine nature intrinsically
perfected the human nature as the intrinsic form that terminates it, or rather
as the act that intrinsically terminates it, this I concede; that the divine
nature could formally sanctify it only as its intrinsic form that informs it,
this I deny. And I contradistinguish the minor.
For just as Christ's human nature is really and intrinsically perfected, not
because it is a nature, but because it is a suppositum, inasmuch as it is
terminated by the Word, so it is really and intrinsically sanctified by its
personal union with the Word.
But I insist. There can be no holiness without the intrinsic form that
excludes sin. But this intrinsic form must inform, just as sin is an inherent
privation; so also blindness is removed only by the inherent power to see, and
not as proposed by reason of the terminating object.
Reply. I concede the major. I deny the minor, for sin is absolutely
impossible in Christ's human nature solely because this human nature is assumed
by the Word. The reason is that sin is a privation that introduces disorder in
the entire suppositum, and the divine suppositum cannot be subjected to
disorder. On the contrary, blindness is only the privation of some particular
accident, namely, the power to see, and hence this blindness is removed only by
the restoration of the inherent visual faculty.
Final objection. But in such a case, Christ's human nature is sanctified by
the increate sanctity and consequently would be God or the Godhead. Confusion of
the nature would follow the form.
Reply. I distinguish the consequent as in the previous objection. That
Christ's human nature would be God or the Godhead, if it were sanctified by the
divine nature, as the informing form, this I concede; as the act that properly
terminates the nature, this I deny. Therefore Christ's sanctity is substantial,
increate, and also innate.
Doubt. Is Christ's human nature formally and substantially sanctified by the
divine nature that is included in the personality of the Word, or is it
sanctified by His relative personality, because of what this adds to the
absolute perfections, or even by the very mode of the union?
Reply. Gonet, Billuart, and several other Thomists say that Christ's humanity
is substantially sanctified by the divine nature that is included in the
personality of the Word, but not in the other two ways. There is authoritative
proof for this affirmation from the quotations of the above-mentioned Fathers,
especially St. Gregory, who says: 'Christ[anointed] is so called because of His
divine nature, for that is the unction of the human nature."[825] But what
anoints the human nature is formally what sanctifies it. Therefore the human
nature is formally sanctified by the divine nature.
Theological proof. Christ's human nature is formally sanctified by the divine
sanctity. The divine sanctity, however, is the divine nature as such, which is
included in the personality of the Word, and therefore the three divine persons
are holy by the same essential holiness.[826]
Confirmation. Habitual grace formally sanctifies inasmuch as it is a
participation of the divine nature, and thus it is the source of strictly divine
operations and ultimately of the beatific vision. Therefore, in like manner,
what formally sanctifies Christ's human nature is precisely the divine nature
that is included in the personality of the Word.
Hence the other two modes are rejected. First of all, it is clearly evident
that Christ's human nature is not formally sanctified by the mode itself of the
union, because, in our opinion, there is no such mode of union; and if there
were, it would not formally sanctify the nature, because it would not be the
sanctifying form, but merely the application of the nature to the form. Thus the
just person is not said to be sanctified by the mode of union with habitual
grace, but by habitual grace itself.
Finally, Christ's human nature is not formally sanctified by the relative
personality of the Word because of what this personality adds to the absolute
perfections of the divine persons, for, according to the more probable opinion
of several Thomists as explained in the treatise on the Trinity, the divine
personalities considered as such or because of the notion of reference to the
opposite correlative in the order of divine relations (esse ad), which they add
to the divine essence, do not declare a new perfection, and therefore sanctity,
but rather they abstract, as the free act of God does, from both perfection and
imperfection. Otherwise we should have to say that the Father is lacking in a
certain perfection since He does not have sonship, or that subsistent relation
which constitutes the person of the Son. Hence the subsistent, divine relations,
that are opposed to one another and God's free act, are not absolutely simple
perfections at least in the strict sense; for an absolutely simple perfection is
defined as a perfection the concept of which implies no imperfection, and which
is better to have than not to have. Thus the Father has all absolutely simple
perfections, otherwise He would not be God, but He does not have the correlative
opposite relation of sonship. It is also not better for Him to have the free act
of creating than not to have it. For God is not better because He created the
universe.
Objection. Some say that Christ's nature is formally sanctified by that with
which it is immediately united. But it is more immediately united with the
subsistence of the Word than with the divine nature. Therefore Christ's nature
is formally sanctified by the subsistence of the Word.
Reply. I distinguish the major. If this to which the human nature is
immediately united is the sanctifying form, then I concede the major; otherwise
I deny it.
It is not unbefitting Christ's human nature to be united with the divine
nature through the medium of the personality of the Word, because this union
cannot be effected in the nature, but only in the person. Likewise it is only
through the medium of the person of the Word that the human nature is united
with the one and only divine nature.[827] Similarly habitual grace sanctifies
the whole being of man, although it is not united immediately with the whole of
his being.
Thus it remains true that Christ's human nature is formally sanctified by the
substantial and increate grace of union, but with a union not by participation
with the divine nature, but with the divine nature itself, in the person of the
Word. Thus, as already stated, Christ's sanctity is not only a transport of joy
experienced in His intellect and will, but it is also the transport of joy that
is felt in His whole being.
This preliminary article does not give the complete teaching of St. Thomas on
this question, but it covers a particular phase of it, for this is what he had
already said in equivalent words.
Having discussed Christ's substantial sanctity, we must now consider the
question of His accidental sanctity, which consists in habitual grace that was
infused into His soul at the moment of His conception. St. Thomas treats of this
grace throughout the whole of this seventh question.
First Article: Whether In The Soul Of Christ There Was Any Habitual Grace
State of the question. Paludanus asserts[828] that some theologians were of
the opinion that there was no habitual grace in Christ, because they thought it
to be entirely superfluous in Him. Their reasons are given by St. Thomas in the
objections placed at the beginning of this article, and are as follows:
1. Grace is a certain participation of the divine nature; but Christ is God
not by participation, but in truth.
2. By the mere fact that Christ was the natural Son of God, He had the power
of doing all things well in the supernatural order, and eternal life was His by
right.
What is true about these arguments, as will at once be evident, is that,
absolutely speaking, Christ could have acted freely, and, by way of transient
help that functions instead of habitual grace, be elevated to elicit
supernatural and even meritorious acts, but these would not have been connatural
to Him.[829] It is difficult to deny this statement, which is admitted by
several Thomists, such as Gonet, Godoy, Billuart, and others.
Let us suppose that Christ or the Word incarnate had not received habitual
grace and, nevertheless, had offered Himself for us on the cross; this oblation
would not only be salutary, as our acts are that precede justification and
dispose us for it, but by virtue of the grace of union this oblation would also
be meritorious, in fact, of infinite value.[830] Nevertheless, as we shall
immediately show, this oblation would not have been connatural, as it must be,
nor would it have been connatural merit de condigno.
Conclusion. We must say that Christ's soul was endowed with habitual grace.
It is the common opinion among theologians, which the Scholastics hold along
with the Master of the Book of Sentences[831] and the commentators of St. Thomas
on this article. This conclusion is at least theologically certain which is
correctly deduced and commonly admitted, so that it belongs at least to
"the science of theology," which is subordinate to faith and above
theological systems.
For the purpose of reconciling the various theologians who do not attach the
same note of censure to the opposite opinion, Francis Sylvius made the following
distinctions.
In his opinion: (1) It is certainly of faith that Christ even in His human
nature was holy and pleasing to God.
2) It is probably of faith that Christ was sanctified by habitual grace that
was infused into His soul, especially because, as Sacred Scripture attests,
Christ had charity and the other infused virtues, which presuppose habitual
grace.
3) Christ in His human nature was sanctified in two ways: first by the grace
of union; secondly by habitual grace. The first sanctity is substantial, the
second is accidental. Hence the opinion of those who said that Christ's habitual
grace must be denied as superfluous, because He was sanctified by the grace of
union, must be rejected, as at least temerarious.
Scriptural proof. St. Thomas quotes in the counterargument, the following
text: "The Spirit of the Lord shall rest upon Him[i. e. Christ, or the
Messias] : the spirit of wisdom and of understanding, the spirit of counsel and
of fortitude, the spirit of knowledge and of godliness, and He shall be filled
with the spirit of the fear of the Lord."[832]
This text from Isaias proves directly the presence of the gifts of the Holy
Ghost in the soul of Christ and consequently the presence of created habitual
grace, from which the gifts proceed as explained in the treatises on grace and
the gifts. Thus grace is called by theologians the grace of the virtues and
gifts, because these are derived from it.
The Evangelist explains these words of Isaias as referring to Christ,[833]
and the interpretation of St. Thomas on these words is the one generally
followed.
There is another text that must be quoted concerning this grace. The
Evangelist writes: "And the Word was made flesh... and we saw His glory as
it were of the only-begotten of the Father[which is the grace of union or
natural divine sonship], full of grace and truth"[834][where the fullness
of habitual grace is implied]. The Evangelist likewise says: "And of His
fullness we have all received, and grace for grace."[835] We have
confirmation of this grace from those texts of Scripture attributing to Christ
virtues that presuppose habitual grace, such as charity, humility, and other
virtues.
The meaning of these texts of Sacred Scripture is made clearer by the
testimony of tradition, which is the living commentary of Scripture.
Patristic proof.[836] St. John Chrysostom says: "The full measure of
grace has been poured out over that Temple[Christ] : for the Spirit does not
measure this grace out to Him.... We have received of His fullness, but that
Temple has received the complete measure of grace.... In Him is all grace, in
men but a small measure, a drop of that grace."[837]
St. Cyril of Alexandria says: "Christ sanctifies Himself, since as God
He is holy by nature; but according to His human nature He is sanctified
together with us."[838]
St. Augustine says: "The Lord Jesus Christ Himself not only gave the
Holy Spirit as God; but also received it as man, and therefore He is said to be
full of grace[839] and of the Holy Spirit.[840] And it is still more plainly
written of Him, 'Because God anointed Him with the Holy Spirit.’[841]
Certainly, not with visible oil, but with the gift of grace, which is signified
by the visible ointment wherewith the Church anoints the baptized."[842]
St. Bernard, commenting on these words of the Evangelist, "And therefore
also the Holy that shall be born of thee,"[843] says: "He[Christ] was
undoubtedly and particularly holy through the sanctification by the Spirit and
assumption by the Word."[844] These last words contain two distinct
assertions. Evidently, the words "and through the assumption by the
Word" signify the increate grace of union; hence the preceding words,
"through the sanctification by the Spirit," imply created or habitual
grace.
We do not find, however, that the Fathers distinguish so clearly between the
increate grace of union and created habitual grace as the Scholastics do and
especially as St. Thomas does. Yet the Fathers distinguish more explicitly
between the Word and charity that is infused into Christ's soul, because the
Gospels and epistles frequently refer to Christ's charity and His other virtues
that always presuppose habitual grace. The Fathers spoke more in the concrete,
that is, they spoke of Christ's acts and were not so much concerned with the
abstract question of habitual grace. Such is always the case, inasmuch as our
intellect gradually makes the transition from the concrete to the abstract and
then returns to the concrete for a better understanding of the question. We find
this to be the method of procedure in all treatises.
Theological proof. Three proofs from theological reasoning are given in the
body of this article.
1) On account of the principle which is the hypostatic union.
2) In view of the end, or the purpose of the supernatural operations in
Christ's soul.
3) Because of Christ's relation to the human race.
The article must be read.
1) The reason on the part of the principle, which is the hypostatic union, is
reduced to the following syllogism.
The nearer any recipient is to an inflowing cause, the more does it partake
of its influence. But Christ's soul is most closely associated with the Word of
God, the Author of grace, since it is united with the Word in the person, and
there cannot be a closer union. Therefore Christ's soul receives the maximum
influx of grace from God.
It follows from this that Christ's habitual grace, though it is not a
physical property, is at least a moral property of the hypostatic union,
inasmuch as the Word incarnate was connaturally entitled to it. It is not,
however, a physical property, for the Word does not constitute with Christ's
human nature one nature, but only one person.
A similar reason, all due proportions being observed, prevails for the
fullness of grace in the Blessed Virgin Mary.
2) The reason, because of the end of Christ's operation in His soul, may thus
be expressed: That the operations of the soul, namely, knowledge and love, may
attain to God the Author of grace, who is to be loved above all things, the soul
and its faculties must be elevated by habitual grace as by a second nature. But
it was necessary that operations of Christ's soul should most closely and
therefore connaturally attain to God the Author of grace, by knowledge and love.
Therefore Christ's soul and its faculties had to be elevated by habitual grace.
The major is evident, inasmuch as habitual grace is necessary so that these
operations be elicited connaturally. For the agent operates connaturally when it
has in itself the nature or permanent form by which it is inclined to its act.
But Christ's soul could be inclined intrinsically and permanently to vital
supernatural acts only by habitual grace. Therefore, that Christ's soul be
inclined intrinsically and permanently to vital supernatural acts, it had to
have habitual grace.[845]
The nature itself of the soul did not suffice nor did the grace of union.
For the soul by nature is entitatively natural and hence it is intrinsically
incapable of eliciting vital supernatural acts; but with merely actual grace it
could indeed elicit such acts, just as a sinner elicits a salutary act before
justification; but such an act is not connatural to the soul, as it is generally
admitted to be in the case of a just person.[846]
The grace of union likewise did not suffice, because this grace is, as
already stated by St. Thomas: "the personal being that is given gratis from
above to the human nature in the person of the Word."[847] Thus this grace
was the principium quod of the operations, but not the principium quo. That by
which Christ's soul is intrinsically, permanently, and connaturally inclined to
supernatural acts, must be in the soul by way of a second nature, as the radical
principium quo of operations, just as the infused virtues are the proximate
principium quo.
It is evident from this that habitual grace in Christ was not superfluous,
but it was necessary for the eliciting of connatural supernatural and
meritorious acts.[848]
We must insist upon the word "connatural" because, absolutely
speaking, Christ, in virtue of the grace of union, and with a transient help,
could have elicited supernatural and even meritorious acts. But that He should
elicit these acts connaturally, His soul had to be endowed with habitual grace
as a second nature, which is a participation of the divine nature. Otherwise His
soul would be imperfect, which is absolutely unbefitting Him.
3) The reason of Christ's relation to us confirms the preceding proofs, and
may be expressed by the following syllogism.
The mediator between God and man must have grace overflowing upon others. But
Christ, as man, is the mediator between God and man, for the Scripture says:
"Of His fullness, we have all received, and grace for grace."[849]
We shall see farther on that Christ's grace as head of the Church is not
precisely the grace of union, but it is habitual grace as presupposing and
connoting the grace of union. For St. Thomas says: "Everything acts
inasmuch as it is a being in act..., hence the agent is nobler than the
patient.... And therefore from this pre-eminence of grace which Christ received,
it is befitting to Him that this grace is bestowed on others."[850]
Truly Christ is the head of the human race inasmuch as He merited and
satisfied for us, and He could not connaturally elicit these meritorious and
satisfactory acts without habitual grace, as already stated. But the grace of
union is presupposed so that these acts may be of infinite value on the part of
the principium quod of these operations.
For a more complete understanding of this article, the following three
conclusions taken from Gonet, with whom several other Thomists such as Godoy and
Billuart agree, must be noted. However, the Salmanticenses differ from the
others concerning the third conclusion.
1) Habitual grace was required in Christ's soul for the completion and
perfection of His sanctity. Such is the opinion of all theologians except
Vasquez.
2) Habitual grace was required in Christ's soul for His supernatural acts to
be connatural.
3) It was necessary for Christ to have habitual grace so that He could merit
connaturally a supernatural reward. By Christ's absolute power, however, without
this grace He could have merited a supernatural reward with intrinsically
supernatural help by way of a transient light of glory.
So say several Thomists, such as Godoy and Billuart.
Objection. The argument raised against this third conclusion is that St.
Thomas says: "Although there is a certain note of infinity in Christ's
merit because of the dignity of the person, yet His actions are meritorious
because of habitual grace, without which merit is impossible."[851]
Gonet replies as follows: "I answer that the purpose of St. Thomas in
the passage just quoted is to point out that without habitual grace there can be
no question of connatural merit. It does not follow from this, absolutely
speaking, and according to God's absolute power that Christ's soul solely with
the grace of union and an actual help in the supernatural order could not merit
a supernatural reward, but only that He could not do so connaturally."[852]
John of St. Thomas is of about the same opinion, saying: "Habitual grace
is not absolutely necessary for the validity of Christ's merit and satisfaction
that transcends the former and that is derived from the value of the
person."[853]
The conclusion of St. Thomas is confirmed from the solution of the objections
in this article.
Reply to first objection. "The soul of Christ is not essentially divine.
Hence it behooves it to be divine by participation, which is by grace."
Reply to second objection. In Christ's soul "the beatific act and its
fruition could not be without grace."
Reply to third objection. "Christ's humanity is the instrument of the
Godhead, not indeed an inanimate instrument, which nowise acts, but is merely
acted upon, but an instrument animated by a rational soul, which is so acted
upon as to act." For Christ's soul to act supernaturally by the love of
charity, it was at least the normal requisite for His soul to have habitual
grace. It would have been something absolutely abnormal for Christ not to have
this habitual grace.
Another objection. If Christ had habitual grace, He would be the adoptive son
of God, for adoptive sonship is the formal effect of habitual grace. We shall
see further on that Christ cannot be called the adopted son of God, because He
is already the natural Son of God in His own right.
Reply. I deny the consequence, for adoptive sonship is not the primary effect
of habitual grace, but only its secondary effect, and even if it were the
primary effect, it would not be communicated to Christ, because He is already
the natural Son of God and hence is incapable of being an adopted son of God.
Adopted sonship applies to anyone by reason of the suppositum, or person, and
hence the person who is the natural Son of God, cannot be called the adopted
son. Hence the Blessed Virgin Mary is the first of the adopted children of God.
First doubt. When did Christ receive habitual grace?
Reply. He received this grace at the moment of His conception, because
habitual grace is the connatural consequence of the hypostatic union.[854]
Second doubt. Did Christ at the first moment of His conception dispose
Himself by an act of free will for the habitual grace that was then infused?
St. Thomas answers this question in the affirmative, because this mode of
sanctification by one's own disposing act, as in adults, is more perfect than to
be sanctified by the disposing act of another as an infant.[855]
St. Thomas holds that "Christ's intellect in regard to His infused
knowledge, could understand at the first moment of His conception, without
turning to phantasms."[856] Many doctors admit this truth as applicable to
the Blessed Virgin Mary. So also the angels; Adam and Eve, who were created as
fully grown, by receiving habitual grace at the moment of their creation
disposed themselves for it by actual grace.
Objection. Some say that this act of free will comes from habitual grace and
therefore cannot dispose one for it.
Reply. Several Thomists, such as Gonet and Serra rightly maintain in their
treatises on grace, when discussing the justification of adults, that the free
act that ultimately disposes in the order of material cause for habitual grace
follows it in the order of formal cause and hence is the effect of habitual
grace, in accordance with the principle: causes mutually interact, though in a
different order.
Likewise the due organization of the human body disposes it for the reception
of the human soul; however, the body has this ultimate disposition only from the
soul, as St. Thomas teaches.[857]
Other Thomists, such as Goudin, say that the free act which is the ultimate
disposition for habitual grace in adults proceeds effectively from the virtue of
charity that is not as yet permanently communicated as a habit but is of the
nature of a transient actual help. The former answer seems the more profound.
St. Thomas solves this question, saying: "Because the infusion of grace
and the remission of sin regard God who justifies, hence in the order of nature,
[instantaneously] the infusion of grace is prior to the freeing from sin.
But if we look at what takes place on the part of the man justified, it is the
other way about, since in the order of nature, the being freed from sin, is
prior to the obtaining of justifying grace."[858] But the being freed from
sin is the ultimate disposition for the attainment of habitual grace, and this
takes place in the adult only by an act of free will (as stated in the body of
the article); this movement of the free will to God proceeds from the actual
infusion of habitual grace and follows it in the orders of formal, efficient,
and final causes, although it precedes this grace in the order of material
cause, as the ultimate disposition in the body in its relation to the soul.
Second Article: Whether In Christ There Were Virtues
State of the question. We are concerned with virtues that are so called in
the strict sense, such as the theological and cardinal virtues. Afterward, in
discussing Christ's knowledge, we shall devote a question exclusively (q. 9) to
the consideration of the intellectual virtues, which are not virtues in the
strict sense inasmuch as they do not make a person absolutely good, but only in
a qualified manner, such as when we say a person is good in metaphysics or
mathematics.
We are concerned not only with directly infused moral virtues, but also with
moral virtues of the natural order, which are acquired by our individual acts.
Conclusion. Christ had all the virtues. This means that He had all virtues
that do not in their notion imply any defect in the soul of Christ, who was both
wayfarer and comprehensor, as will be pointed out farther on. Thus in the
following articles we shall have occasion to remark that Christ did not have
either faith or hope or penance.
Scriptural proof. The Gospels authoritatively represent Christ as the
exemplar of all virtues. Rationalists, such as Renan, acknowledge this to be
true. We must insist upon this truth for the better manifestation of Christ's
sanctity, which is the motive of credibility that leads to faith in Him.
There is negative evidence of this truth inasmuch as Christ was sinless, so
that He could say to the Jews who sought to kill Him: "Which of you shall
convince Me of sin?"[859] And nobody dared to contradict Him. Truly,
indeed, as the Gospel narrates: "The chief priests and the whole council
sought false witness against Jesus that they might put Him to death, and they
found not."[860] But it was only because Jesus confessed that He is Christ,
the Son of God, that "the high priest rent His garments, saying: 'He hath
blasphemed. "[861] Even Judas confessed, saying: "I have sinned in
betraying innocent blood";[862] and Pilate said: "I am innocent of the
blood of this just man, look you to it."[863]
Moreover, Christ had all virtues and even most different kinds of them which
He practiced in a heroic degree. Love and dutiful submission to God are
especially evident in the life of Jesus, His love and mercy for men, perfect
self-denial, humility and utmost magnanimity, most perfect meekness as also
fortitude and patience on the cross, as when He prayed for those who tortured
Him. We find wonderfully reconciled in Christ that holy rigor of justice toward
the impenitent Pharisees and that immensity of mercy toward those sinners who do
not resist God's grace.
In fact, as shown in apologetics, this harmony and perseverance that prevails
between such vastly different virtues practiced in a heroic degree is a moral
miracle. For this sublime and profound harmony between the virtues or holiness
of life is impossible without God's special intervention, for it consists in an
inseparable union with God which can come only from God, inasmuch as the order
of agents must correspond to the order of ends. Apologetical arguments founded
not on revelation but on reason make this already evident.
In fact, Christ's sanctity is not only eminent, but is manifestly
extraordinary in that it unites in itself vastly different heroic virtues. We
have seen indeed that a person is at times naturally disposed or is by force of
habit ready to perform acts requiring fortitude of soul, who, nevertheless, is
not ready to perform acts that call for meekness of soul, for by nature such a
person is determined one particular way. But that anyone may have all the
virtues and also excel in them, even those so vastly different, such as supreme
fortitude and supreme meekness, perfect love of truth and justice and also the
greatest of mercy toward those that err and fall into sin, this is impossible
without God's special help, who alone in the simplicity of His nature contains
formally and eminently vastly different perfections, and who can unite these in
the human soul, so as to make it a perfect image of God. Thus the soul of Christ
is that most sublime image in which it is possible to contemplate the Deity.
Theological proof. It can be proved by theological reasoning that Christ had
all the virtues. This reasoning of St. Thomas is valid for the infused virtues,
and may be expressed as follows:
As the faculties of the soul stem from its essence, so the infused virtues
stem from habitual grace, and in a proportionate degree. But Christ's soul was
endowed with habitual grace from the moment of His conception, and indeed in the
highest degree of perfection, as will be more clearly explained farther on.[864]
Therefore Christ had all the infused virtues and in the highest degree.[865]
We are concerned with virtues which, in what they mean, imply no defect in
the soul of Christ, who was both wayfarer and comprehensor. Thus faith, hope,
and repentance must be excluded.[866] The reason given by St. Thomas holds good
for charity and all the infused moral virtues.
Reply to first objection. Habitual grace performs supernatural acts only
through the medium of the virtues.
Reply to second objection. Christ had the virtues most perfectly, beyond the
common mode. In this sense Plotinus gave to a certain sublime degree of virtue
the name of virtue of the purified soul, as Macrobius says.[867]
Reply to third objection. "Christ showed the highest kind of liberality
and magnificence by despising all riches." For these virtues, just as
wittiness which has to do with joking, can be either made use of or despised for
the sake of a higher end. But Christ had no evil desires whatever, as will be
shown farther on.[868] Thus Christ had perfect temperance, but not continence,
which St. Augustine says is not a virtue but something less than the virtue of
chastity, for the continent person, strictly speaking, has evil tendencies, but
resists them by will power. Cajetan[869] remarks, taking the name
"continence" in the more common acceptation of the word, that there is
nothing that prevents us from calling Christ continent.
First doubt. Did Christ have all moral virtues that of themselves can be
acquired? Theologians generally give an affirmative answer to this question..
The reason is that the sensitive appetite in Christ was no different from
ours, which is an inclination to sensible delectable good; that it may
completely and perfectly tend to its natural and fitting good, it requires a
superadded form, that can be nothing else but a moral virtue that is directly
acquirable. Infused moral virtues did not suffice, because the direct purpose of
these is to incline the will to supernatural acts. The correlative moral and
acquirable virtues, although they are in themselves in their own order truly
virtues, are related to the virtues as dispositions from which there arises an
extrinsic facility for the practice of the infused virtues, for they exclude
inordinate inclinations resulting from repetition of acts.[870] The acquired
moral virtues are in their relation to the infused virtues somewhat like
dexterity in manipulating the harp is to the art that is in the practical
intellect of the musician. Hence it is certain that Christ had moral virtues
that are of themselves acquirable; otherwise He would have been morally
imperfect, just as beginners in the Christian life who, by the very fact that
they are in the state of grace, have infused prudence, which scarcely manifests
itself, however, because they lack the virtue of acquired prudence, without
which it is difficult to practice the virtue of infused prudence.
Confirmation. Christ's will must be perfected as regards good, just as much
as His intellect is as regards truth. But there was acquired knowledge in
Christ's intellect, as will be made clear farther on.[871] Therefore, likewise
in His will and sensitive appetite there was the possibility of acquiring moral
virtues.
First objection. To perform a most perfect act is to act from a supernatural
motive. But Christ always had to perform most perfect acts. Therefore He always
acted from a supernatural motive or by acts of the infused virtues and not by
acts of virtues that of themselves were acquirable.
Reply. I distinguish the major: to perform a most perfect act is to act from
a supernatural motive, when this motive is the end in view of the person acting,
this I concede; that the deed performed must always be in itself supernatural,
this I deny. Hence, just as Christ performed not only acts of charity, but also
acts of the infused virtues, so also He performed natural acts that as regards
the object and end of these acts were good and fitting, though they were
subordinated to the supernatural end of charity as being the end in view of the
person acting. Thus Christ said: "Render to Caesar the things that are
Caesar's...."[872] These are natural obligations, just as even pagans know
that commutative justice requires the payment of debts.
As grace does not destroy nature but perfects it, so also the infused virtues
neither destroy nor render the acquired virtues useless, but perfect them,
directing them to be performed for the love of God, not that the acts themselves
are supernatural, but that the end in view of the agent is supernatural. Thus
the act of the acquired virtue of temperance is modally supernatural, whereas
the act of the infused virtue of temperance is substantially supernatural. Thus
the acquired moral virtues are subordinated to the infused moral virtues in some
way just as the imagination and sensitive memory are subordinated to knowledge,
philosophy to theology, and theology to the doctrine of faith that transcends
the science of theology. There is a normal hierarchy of functions in this
subordination.
Second objection. But the acquired virtues are required to restrain the
immoderate tendencies of the passions, which Christ did not have, for, as will
be mentioned farther on,[873] Christ was free from concupiscence. Therefore He
had no need of the acquired virtues.
Reply. I distinguish the antecedent: that the acquired virtues are necessary
in a secondary sense so as to check the immoderate tendencies of the passions,
this I concede; that they are primarily necessary, this I deny. For the primary
and special purpose of these virtues is to enable the faculties to act properly,
promptly, and with facility in the natural order. It is in this way that
chastity operates, for example, even when there are no temptations to be
overcome or passions to be curbed. Thus humility in Christ did not check the
first movements of pride, but it completely subjected His will to the divine
majesty.
Thus Adam in the state of innocence had those virtues that are of themselves
capable of attainment, and they remain in the blessed, as St. Thomas
teaches.[874]
Second doubt. Did Christ have these moral virtues that can be acquired of
themselves by infusion, or did He acquire them by His own acts?
It is difficult to give a definite answer to this question.[875] The more
probable opinion of several Thomists is that they were infused, just as Adam in
the state of innocence had them from the moment of his creation. However, Adam
was created in the adult state, whereas Christ as man gradually grew up to
manhood.
The principal reason for this answer is that Christ was never without these
virtues, for to be deprived of them for any time is in itself something evil,
and no defect is admissible in God, except those that are not contrary to the
end of the Incarnation, such as the privation of the glorification of His body
for a time. But such is not the case with the temporary privation of these
virtues. It would be more derogatory to Christ's dignity that He should be for a
time without these virtues, than increase in perfection by acquiring them, which
cannot be instantaneous, but only a progressive process. Moreover, the Church
declared in the Second Council of Constantinople: "Christ was not subjected
to passions, nor did He become better by the repetition of virtuous
acts."[876]
Objection. But the Gospel says: "Jesus advanced in wisdom and age, and
grace with God and men."[877]
Reply. The answer of St. Thomas is: "Christ advanced in wisdom and grace
as also in age (not by an actual increase of the habits but), because as He
advanced in age He performed more perfect works."[878]
Another objection. St. Thomas says farther on[879] that Christ advanced in
acquired knowledge. Therefore He also advanced in moral virtues that of
themselves can be acquired.
Reply. There is not parity of argument. (1) The natural sciences do not make
man absolutely good, such as the moral virtues do, but good only in a qualified
sense, such as good in mathematics or in physics. (2) If the natural sciences
were infused in Christ, then His active intellect would be in a state of
continual idleness as regards its first function, which is to abstract
intelligible species from the senses. Therefore it is more probable that Christ
had moral virtues that of themselves can be acquired from the time of His
conception.
Third Article: Whether In Christ There Was Faith
The general opinion of theologians is that Christ did not have faith. Such is
the opinion of St. Thomas.
The reason given in the counterargument does not absolutely prove this
assertion, for the words of Peter quoted here, namely, "Thou knowest all
things,"[880] were spoken after Christ's resurrection. Hence these words
prove to some extent that at least after the resurrection Jesus did not have
faith concerning mysteries in the strict sense, but the beatific vision.
The body of the article presupposes what must be proved farther on,[881]
namely, that Christ from the first moment of His conception completely saw God
in His essence. But the clear vision of God excludes the notion of faith, which
is of things not seen.
In other words, a virtue cannot be in a subject to whom its primary act is
derogatory. But the primary act of faith refers to God not seen. Therefore
Christ could not have had faith, since from the moment of His conception He
clearly saw God in His essence. This is the common opinion among theologians. No
theologian holds that an act of faith is simultaneously compatible with the
beatific vision, because the scriptural text of St. Paul is clear on this point:
"Faith[882]... is the evidence of things that appear not." Durandus
thinks that the habit of faith, however, if not its act, can remain in the
blessed. Scotus holds this to be possible, but useless. St. Thomas and St.
Bonaventure are of the opinion that the habit of faith cannot co-exist with the
beatific vision. Thus St. Thomas says: "The object of faith is a divine
thing not seen. But the habit of virtue... takes its species from the object.
Hence, if we deny that the divine thing was not seen, we exclude the very
essence of faith."[883]
At least the permanence of the beatific vision excludes both act and habit of
faith. The beatific vision as a transient act, which St. Augustine and St.
Thomas think St. Paul had on this earth, excludes the act of faith concerning
this object, but not the habit of faith.
Reply to first objection. The moral virtues, although they are inferior to
faith, were and are always in Christ because they imply no defect as regards
their subject matter.[884]
Reply to second objection. St. Thomas does not teach that Christ had the
merit of faith, but He had what constitutes the reward of our faith, which is
perfect obedience to the loving commands of God.
But Christ was faithful to His promises, and this is sometimes called faith
in Sacred Scripture.[885] Thus the prophet says of the Messias: "Faith
shall be the girdle of His loins."[886]
Therefore the maximum of faith that any intellectual creature had was the
theological faith of the Blessed Virgin Mary, for her faith was proportionate to
her plenitude of grace. From this we conclude how sublime must have been the
acts of faith and hope made by the Blessed Virgin Mary, especially on Mount
Calvary, not in the least doubting that her Son, who seemed to be conquered, was
the Son of God, the conqueror of the devil and sin, and the proximate victor of
death.
Fourth Article: Whether In Christ There Was Hope
State of the question. There is some difficulty, for the Psalmist, speaking
in the person of Christ, says: "In Thee, O Lord, have I hoped."[887]
Moreover, Christ awaited or hoped for the glorification of His body and the
building up of His mystical body.
Conclusion. St. Thomas, with whom the majority of theologians agree,
maintains that Christ did not have the virtue of hope but had a certain act of
hope or rather of desire concerning things He did not yet possess.
Scriptural proof. St. Paul says: "What a man seeth, why doth he hope
for?"[888] But Christ did not have faith, as was said above,[889] because
from the beginning (of the hypostatic union) He enjoyed the vision of the divine
essence. Therefore, too, He did not have the virtue of hope.
Theological proof. The reason for this proof is taken from the formal or
primary object of hope, for hope, considered as a theological virtue, has God
Himself as its primary object, whose fruition is expected. But Christ from the
beginning of His conception had the complete fruition of the divine essence, as
will be stated farther on.[890] Therefore He did not have the theological virtue
of hope.
The principle of the preceding article applies equally here, namely, a virtue
cannot be in a subject to whom its primary act is derogatory.
However, at the end of the argumentative part of this article, St. Thomas
admits that Christ had a certain act of hope or rather of desire as regards some
things, so that He could expect the glorification of His body and the building
up of the Church. Thus the Psalmist, speaking in the person of Christ, says:
"In Thee, O Lord, have I hoped."[891] But these things do not
constitute the primary object of the theological virtue of hope, and thus it
remains true that Christ did not have this theological virtue of hope.
Therefore of all intellectual creatures, the hope of the Blessed Virgin Mary
was the most sublime especially on Mount Calvary, when all the apostles, with
the exception of St. John, did not have the courage to witness the death of
Christ. Hence it is said of her: "Grant that I may carry the cross of
Christ."[892]
First doubt. To what virtue must we attribute this act of desire in Christ
for the glorification of His body and the building up of the Church?
Reply. This act must be attributed to the virtue of charity, as its secondary
act, whereby Christ loved Himself and the Church, for God's sake, as the
Evangelist says: "Greater love than this no man hath, that a man lay down
his life for his friends."[893]
Thus the love of concupiscence by which we desire eternal life for the glory
of God, is attributed to us as a secondary act of charity.
Second doubt. Was there penance as a virtue in Christ?
Reply. There was no penance, as a virtue, in Christ, because it implies in
the strict sense sorrow for one's own sins. But Christ was impeccable, as will
be explained farther on. The Sacred Congregation of the Holy Office forbade such
invocations as: "Heart of Jesus, penitent for us, Jesus penitent, Jesus
penitent for us."[894]
The truth of this reply is clearly established since it agrees with the
generally accepted teaching of St. Thomas, which declares that penance is a
special virtue that is distinct not only from the virtue of religion, but also
from the virtue of vindictive justice and of all the other virtues.[895]
Thus the primary and specific act of penance is sorrow for one's own sins
with the motive of amendment, and the intention of performing salutary acts in
satisfaction for one's past offenses.
But a virtue cannot be in a subject to whom its primary act is intrinsically
repugnant. But the act of penance is intrinsically repugnant to Christ's human
nature, because it was united to the Word.[896] But Christ had a perfect
detestation for sin inasmuch as it is an offense against God, arising from the
intensity of His love for God offended and for souls that are dead to God
through mortal sin.
Fifth Article: Whether In Christ There Were The Gifts
State of the question. The difficulty is that gifts are given to help the
virtues. But the virtues were most perfect in Christ. Therefore He did not need
this help.
Moreover, Christ had already on this earth the contemplation of heaven as
explained farther on. But the gifts of wisdom, knowledge, and understanding seem
to belong to contemplation in this life, and apparently these are useless in a
soul that already enjoys the beatific vision.
Conclusion. It is commonly admitted, however, that the soul of Christ had
these gifts in a pre-eminent degree.
Gonet maintains that this conclusion is a certainty of the faith, because of
the text of Isaias quoted in the proof.
Scriptural proof. The prophet says: "The Spirit of the Lord shall rest
upon Him: the spirit of wisdom and of understanding, the spirit of counsel and
of fortitude, the spirit of knowledge and of godliness. And He shall be filled
with the spirit of the fear of the Lord."[897]
Instead of the words, "the spirit of knowledge and of godliness,"
the Hebrew text reads, "the spirit of knowledge and of fear." Thus
fear is mentioned twice. The Greek version and the Vulgate give
"godliness," which is about the same in meaning as reverential
godliness. The Old Testament does not distinguish so clearly between. godliness
and fear as the New Testament does, which is not the law of fear, but of
love.[898]
The Fathers and Scholastics are generally agreed that this text concerns
Christ's human nature.
Theological proof. Although it has been revealed that Christ had gifts and
still has them, this assertion can also be proved from higher revealed
principles, namely, from the definition of gifts. St. Thomas says in this
article: "The gifts, properly, are certain perfections of the soul's
powers, inasmuch as they have a natural aptitude to be moved by the Holy
Ghost," according to St. Luke, who says: "And Jesus being full of the
Holy Ghost returned from the Jordan and was led by the Spirit into the
desert." Hence it is manifest that the gifts were in Christ in a
pre-eminent degree.
The thesis is confirmed by the fact that the gifts of the Holy Ghost follow
from habitual grace and are connected with charity, as St. Thomas teaches.[899]
But Christ had habitual grace in the most perfect manner and the highest degree
of charity. Therefore He also had pre-eminently the gifts.
The thesis is also confirmed from the solution of the objections.
Reply to first objection. It points out that as a man, however perfect he may
be, needs to be helped by God, so also, no matter how perfect the virtues are,
they need to be helped by the gifts, which perfect the powers of the soul,
inasmuch as these are not controlled by reason illumined by faith, but by the
Holy Spirit. This reply confirms the teaching of St. Thomas as set forth in a
previous passage[900] where he shows that the infused virtues, even the highest
degree, are specifically distinct from the gifts as regards their formal object
quo or their rule or motive;[901] for to be ruled by right reason even though
illumined by the light of faith differs from being ruled by the Holy Spirit,
which means to be ruled by His special inspiration, which transcends the
discursive process of reasoning. Thus there is a manifest difference between
being ruled by infused prudence, which proceeds from living faith, and being
ruled by the gift of counsel.
Reply to third objection. It states that the gifts were not useless in
Christ, for He also had earthly knowledge, as will be stated farther on;[902]
for Christ was both wayfarer and comprehensor. He was comprehensor as regards
the higher part of the soul, and wayfarer inasmuch as His soul still was
passible and His body passible and mortal, so that He looked forward to
beatitude in all those things which were wanting to Him of beatitude. Moreover,
as explained elsewhere,[903] the gifts remain in heaven.
As stated in this last citation, this doctrine of the permanence of the gifts
in heaven is affirmed by St. Ambrose,[904] and the reason is that the gifts of
the Holy Spirit perfect the human mind to follow the prompting of the Holy
Spirit, which is especially the case in heaven. But in heaven, evil and
temptation being no more, by the gifts of the Holy Spirit we are perfected in
good, not entirely as regards the same material object but the gifts will
preserve in us intact the same formal objects both quo and quod of the virtues
by which latter they are specified; for as theologians in heaven will see the
object of theology, either in the Word if in this life they studied it out of
love for God, or outside the Word; so also all the blessed in heaven will
receive special inspirations from the Holy Spirit to know something special by
means of experimental knowledge, according as it is connaturally related to
divine things, for instance, to know for what wayfarers they must especially
pray. The beatific vision precedes beatific love, whereas the knowledge obtained
by the gifts follows this love. Finally, there is neither succession in
knowledge nor acquisition of anything new, whereas by the gifts it is possible
for the blessed to acquire additional knowledge.
But obscurity and similar imperfections that now actually belong to the
gifts, either of wisdom or counsel, or of other such gifts, do not belong to the
state of glory, nor were these defects in Christ.
Thus the gift of wisdom disposed Christ so as to be moved with facility by
the Holy Spirit to pass certain judgment on divine things by the highest of
causes, in accordance with a connaturalness that is founded on charity for
things.
But the gift of understanding attributed to Him correct and immediate
penetration of those things that pertain to the kingdom of God.
The gift of counsel likewise attributed to Christ the power of immediately
finding out the motive for action.
The gift of knowledge so that even in the consideration of inferior motives,
He might judge with absolute certainty about things that happened.
The gift of fortitude expelled from Him the fear of death and its attendant
tortures.
Gonet says these conclusions are admitted by all theologians as being certain
and beyond dispute.
Sixth Article: Whether In Christ There Was The Gift Of Fear
State of the question. There are two difficulties: (1) It seems that hope is
stronger than fear, for the object of hope is good, whereas the object of fear
is evil. If, therefore, Christ did not have the virtue of hope, a fortiori He
did not have the gift of fear. (2) The gift of fear makes one afraid either of
being separated from God, or of being punished by Him. But these two were
impossible for Christ, because He was impeccable.
Reply. Christ had the gift of fear.
Scriptural proof. The testimony of the prophet, quoted in the preceding
article, is: "He shall be filled with the spirit of the fear of the
Lord,"[905] which also in the Hebrew text refers to the spirit of fear.
Moreover, the Church condemned the following proposition of Abelard: "The
spirit of the fear of the Lord was not in Christ."[906]
Theological proof. This assertion of Sacred Scripture is not so much proved
as explained by the following syllogism.
God is feared by an act of reverential fear, not only inasmuch as He can
inflict punishment but on account of His pre-eminence, who cannot with impunity
be resisted. But the soul of Christ was moved by the Holy Spirit toward God b;
certain reverential affection. Therefore Scripture attributes to Him the
fullness of the gift of fear, not indeed of the fear of punishment, or sin, but
of reverential fear.
Confirmation. This gift of fear, understood as reverential fear, remains in
the blessed, for the Psalmist exclaims: "The fear of the Lord is holy,
enduring forever and ever."[907] It is said of the angels, especially of
those called Powers: "The Powers tremble."[908] For every creature
that is not self-existent trembles in the sight of Him who alone is and can be
the self-subsisting Being. But Christ's human nature is not His being, although
it exists by the very being of the Word, inasmuch as there is one being in
Christ, just as there is one person.[909]
Doubt. What is the primary object of the gift of fear?
It is God's pre-eminence, who cannot with impunity be resisted; and its
primary act is reverence for this divine pre-eminence, and so this gift can be
both in Christ and the blessed. The secondary object of the gift of fear, or of
filial fear, is the evil of sin that must be avoided.
In contrast to this, the primary object of fear, considered as a passion, is
terrifying sensible evil, and the primary act of this fear is flight from this
evil. Finally, the primary object of servile fear is the evil of punishment to
be inflicted on account of the offense committed.
Thus it remains true that the habits of the virtues and the gifts properly
and directly refer to good, but to evil as a consequence.
Seventh Article: Whether The Graces Gratis Datae Were In Christ
State of the question. By placing the article about the graces gratis datae
here, it is evident that St. Thomas draws a complete distinction between them
and the gifts as he has already shown.[910] The seven gifts, which are connected
with charity, belong to the organism of the supernatural life, but the graces
gratis datae do not.
The difficulty is that the graces gratis datae are freely given by way of a
transient act. But Christ had permanently the fullness of grace. Hence He did
not need these secondary graces. The Gospel does not say that He had the gift of
tongues.
Reply. Nevertheless the answer is that all the graces gratis datae were
pre-eminently in Christ as the first and chief teacher of the faith.
Authoritative proof. St. Augustine says: "As in the head are all the
senses, so in Christ were all the graces."[911] St. Augustine is also
expressly referring here to the graces gratis datae in Christ.
The Master of the Book of the Sentences is precisely of the same
opinion,[912] and it is commonly admitted by the scholastic theologians.
Theological proof. Graces gratis datae are ordained for the manifestation of
faith and spiritual doctrine, because the manner of their enumeration makes this
evident,[913] and also the explanation of St. Thomas.[914] But Christ is the
first and chief teacher of the faith and of spiritual doctrine. Therefore the
graces gratis datae were in Christ.
This means that the graces gratis datae were most excellently in Christ,
being ordained for the benefit of others. They may be expressed by the following
schema.
[diagram page 281]
GRACES GRATIS DATAE that are ordained for the instruction of others in divine
things
to acquire complete knowledge of divine things
faith concerning principles,[915]
word of wisdom concerning the principal conclusions,
word of knowledge concerning the examples and effects
to confirm the divine revelation
by doing: grace of healing working of miracles
by knowing: prophecy, discerning of spirits
to convey fittingly to the hearers the divine message
kinds of tongues, interpretation of speeches
Christ had to have in the most perfect degree all these graces that were
bestowed on others; for they denote no imperfection that is repugnant either to
the beatific vision or to the hypostatic union. They are also becoming to the
dignity of the head of the mystical body, as St. Augustine says in the
counter-argument of this article.
Reply to first objection. St. Thomas points out that these graces are called
"diversities of graces,"[916] inasmuch as in the saints these graces
are divided; but Christ had these graces all at once and in their plenitude just
as He had and always has the plenitude of habitual grace.
Reply to second objection. It was fitting for Christ to have habitual grace,
not according to His divine nature, but according to His human nature.
Reply to third objection. It is pointed out that, although we do not read of
Christ having had the gift of tongues, because He preached only to the Jews,
"yet a knowledge of all languages was not wanting to Him, since even the
secrets of hearts, of which all words are signs, were not hidden from
Him."[917]
Christ likewise had the grace gratis datae of faith. This grace is a certain
pre-eminence of knowledge concerning the revealed mysteries whether such
knowledge be clear or obscure;[918] it is also a facility given by the Holy
Spirit of proposing the things of faith simply and in a way adapted to all, so
that they can be understood even by the ignorant, as explained by St.
Thomas.[919] It is evident from the Gospel that Christ had both kinds of
excellence.
There is no doubt about Christ's powers concerning either the grace of
healing or the discernment of spirits, for the Evangelist says: "And Jesus
seeing their thoughts[of the Pharisees], said: 'Why do you think evil in your
hearts?'"[920] Again he says: "Jesus knowing their thoughts.[921]
Finally, Christ had pre-eminently the grace of interpretation of speech for
explaining the Scriptures in the true and most exalted sense. Hence the
Evangelist relates that the disciples going to the town called Emmaus said:
"Was not our heart burning within us, whilst He spoke in the way, and
opened to us the Scriptures?"[922]
Eighth Article: Whether In Christ There Was The Gift Of Prophecy
State of the question. St. Thomas posited this special article about
prophecy, because this grace gratis data presents a particular difficulty. For
the first objection of this article remarks that prophecy implies a certain
obscurity. But Christ already enjoyed on this earth the beatific vision. Also
prophecy concerns distant things or those that are far off, and seems to imply
an essential imperfection, as faith and hope do. Moreover, the Apostle says that
in heaven, "prophecies shall be made void."[923]
Reply. The answer is in the affirmative.
Scriptural proof. Moses announced to the Israelites: "The Lord thy God
will raise up to thee a Prophet... of thy brethren... Him thou shalt
hear."[924] Jesus applied to Himself what Moses foretold of Him, saying:
"He wrote of Me."[925] Likewise Jesus said of Himself in the synagogue
at Nazareth: "A prophet is not without honor, save in his own
country."[926]
Theological proof. He is a prophet who knows and announces what is distant
both from himself according to his state and from his hearers. But Christ, who
was not only comprehensor but also wayfarer, knew and announced very many things
which were distant from Him according to His state as wayfarer, such as His
betrayal, death, and resurrection,[927] as also the destruction of Jerusalem,
the signs preceding the end of the world, the denial of Peter, and several other
events. Therefore Christ was a prophet.
Reply to first objection. Prophecy, as usually communicated, is obscure and
enigmatic not in itself, but because of the imperfection of the hearer. Its
clarity or obscurity, that it be communicated transiently, or permanently, are
of themselves a matter of indifference. But in Christ prophecy was clear and
permanent because of the union of His human nature with the Word.
But if the Apostle says that in heaven "prophecies shall be made
void,"[928] he has in mind complete beatitude, which is incompatible with
the state of wayfarer.
Ninth Article: Whether In Christ There Was The Fullness Of Grace
State of the question. The third part of this question begins here. After the
consideration of the grace of the virtues and of the gifts and of the graces
gratis datae in Christ, St. Thomas treats of the fullness of grace. He asks
whether Christ was simply full of grace, both intensively and extensively.
This article and those that follow are therefore concerned with the
perfection of Christ's grace.
Conclusion. Christ had fullness of grace, both intensively, that is, as
regards its perfection, and extensively, that is, as regards the various effects
it can produce.
Scriptural proof. The Evangelist says: "We saw His glory... full of
grace and truth.... And of His fullness we have all received, and grace for
grace."[929] Likewise St. John the Baptist testified concerning Christ, and
the Evangelist says; "He whom God hath sent, speaketh the words of God; for
God does not give to Him the spirit by measure. The Father loveth the Son, and
He hath given all things into His hand."[930]
The Fathers of the Church have often explained these texts by showing that
Christ, who is most full of grace, had every kind of holiness.[931]
Theological proof. It is simply discursive and explanatory, explaining the
above quoted text.[932]
This proof may be reduced to the following syllogism.
Fullness of grace is of two kinds, namely, intensive and extensive.
But Christ had each kind. Therefore Christ had absolutely or completely
fullness of grace.
Major. It is thus explained. There is intensive fullness of any quality in a
being, for instance, of whiteness, when the being has as much of this quality as
it can naturally have. Thus it appears that a lily has the highest possible
degree of whiteness; so also snow.
Hence intensive fullness is estimated from the degree and radication of any
quality in the subject. But extensive fullness of any quality is estimated from
the relation to the various effects that any operative principle is capable of
producing; for example, the irrational animal has not extensive fullness of
life, because it has not intellectual life, but only the vegetative life and
sensitive life.
Minor. Its parts are proved. Christ had intensive fullness of grace, that is,
in the highest degree that it can be had, for two reasons.
1) Because His soul, which was united to God by the most exalted of all
possible unions, which is the hypostatic union, received the greatest influx of
grace, just as the air that is nearer to the fire is warmer and more luminous.
2) Because grace was given to Christ, as the head, from which it was to be
poured out upon all others; just as in this world nothing is brighter than the
sun, which illumines all other things. Hence the Evangelist quotes Jesus as
saying: "I am come to cast fire on the earth, and what will I but that it
be kindled?"[933] The reference is to fire that purifies, illumines, and
kindles spiritually.
From these proofs it is apparent that intensive fullness of any quality is
estimated from its intrinsic perfection inasmuch as it is pure and free from all
imperfection. Thus snow is perfectly white; it has whiteness in all its
intensity or purity, containing no element that is not white.
If there is reference to some operative habit, since this habit determines
the faculty to operate, it is all the more perfect intensively, the more it
determines the faculty with reference to the formal object of the operation to
be elicited, that is, it actuates the faculty and is radicated in it. There is
something similar in the case of habitual grace, which is an entitative habit,
which is received in the essence of the soul, and is radically operative,
inasmuch as the virtues are derived from it, just as the faculties are derived
from the essence of the soul. Thus intensive fullness of habitual grace is
estimated from its intrinsic perfection free from all imperfection, and its
radication in the soul, which it especially determines radically to operate most
holily free from all imperfection. This intensive fullness of grace would apply
to Christ even if His soul were ordered solely to the performance of acts of the
love of God.
Likewise Christ had extensive fullness of grace, which is estimated from its
relation to the various effects it can produce.
The reason is that, as St. Thomas says: "Christ had grace for all its
operations and effects, and this because it was bestowed on Him, as upon a
universal principle in the genus of such as have grace... just as the sun is the
universal cause of generation."[934]
This twofold fullness, intensive and extensive, is called absolute on the
part of the grace itself, which by God's ordinary power cannot be received in a
more perfect manner. It is not merely relatively perfect or according to the
exigencies of the state or dignity of the subject. In fact, this most exalted
dignity of head and redeemer of the human race demands absolute fullness of
grace.
Doubt. Is this plenitude of grace more perfect intensively than extensively?
Reply. It is the common opinion among theologians that intensive plenitude is
the more perfect, just as quality is to be preferred to quantity, although
positivism is inclined to the contrary view; for indeed intensive plenitude is
immediately estimated from the intrinsic perfection of the quality, and is the
foundation of extensive plenitude. This is especially evident in knowledge, for
its intensive plenitude results from the deeper penetration of its first notions
and principles, whereas its extensive plenitude, both habitual and actual, is
estimated according to the number of conclusions that are deduced from the
principles. There are certain physicists who know all the conclusions of their
own science in its actual state of development, and who have read all the books
of any importance belonging to this science. This does not mean, however, that
they have penetrated more deeply into the principles of this science; for the
scientific habit is not yet, perhaps, established in their intellect as a sort
of second nature. On the contrary, another physicist knows more from on high the
principles of this particular science, and their subordination to the other
sciences, even though he may have forgotten certain conclusions. The perfection
of a science is not estimated according to the number of its conclusions, for
although science may make use of many subordinated ideas, it is a simple quality
that perfects the intellect in its relation to some formal object and to certain
first principles, which virtually contain all the conclusions of this particular
science.
Thus there is a great difference between Aristotle and the author of a
textbook on peripatetic philosophy. Although the author of such a textbook may
perhaps succeed in giving to this science new conclusions, yet he has not the
genius of Aristotle, nor could he be the author of such works as the Organon,
Physics, Metaphysics, and Ethics of the Stagirite. There is also a similar
difference between St. Thomas and his commentators, although the latter may
succeed in giving to the science new conclusions.
Likewise those historians Who Write a critical estimate of the life of
Napoleon have a more extensive knowledge perhaps than the ambassadors and
soldiers of his time, but they generally do not penetrate so intensively and
vividly into the mind of such a genius as Napoleon.
Similarly those historians who insist on giving us a critical evaluation of
the Gospels, certainly have a less intensive knowledge of Christ's preaching
than the apostles had who heard Him. Thus St. John the Evangelist had a better
knowledge of Christ's teaching than a theologian would have who would know all
the condemned propositions contained in Denzinger's Enchiridion.
Therefore, a fortiori, there was in Christ intensive plenitude of habitual
grace and hence of the virtues and gifts.
Tenth Article: Whether The Fullness Of Grace Is Proper To Christ
State of the question. The reason for inserting this article is that Sacred
Scripture attributes at least a certain fullness of grace to some others. Thus
the angel says to the Blessed Virgin Mary: "Hail, full of grace."[935]
The Scripture also says: "Stephen, full of grace and fortitude."[936]
In fact, St. Paul writing to the Ephesians, thus expresses his desire to them:
"That you may be filled unto all the fullness of God."[937] Moreover,
for all the blessed in heaven, beatitude is the fullness of all good, which
presupposes a certain fullness of grace in this life. What is therefore the
fullness of grace that is proper to Christ?
First conclusion. Absolute fullness of grace, but not relative fullness,
belongs to Christ alone.
Scriptural proof. The Evangelist says: "We saw His glory, the glory as
it were of the only-begotten of the Father, full of grace and truth."[938]
But to be the only-begotten of the Father, belongs to Christ alone. Therefore,
too, does fullness of grace.
Theological proof. Absolute fullness of grace is attained when there is as
much grace as can be had, at least according to God's ordinary power. But Christ
alone had grace in the highest possible degree of excellence and intensity that
can be had, at least according to God's ordinary power. Therefore Christ alone
had absolute fullness of grace, both in its intensity and extent, as was stated
in the preceding article.
Second conclusion. Relative fullness of grace does not belong to Christ
alone, but is communicated to others through Him.
There is, indeed, relative fullness of grace when it is of such a nature and
extent as demanded by the condition and office of the person to whom it is
attributed.
But several saints, especially the Blessed Virgin Mary, had grace that was
perfectly proportioned to the state and duty assigned to them. Thus the Blessed
Virgin is declared to be "full of grace."[939] Therefore relative
fullness of grace does not belong to Christ alone.[940]
Corollary.[941] Christ's habitual grace, from the very moment of His
conception, excelled in both intensity and extent all grace, even the ultimate
grace of angels and men combined. The reason is that the grace in Christ is in
proportion to the hypostatic union, and is in Him as the source from which it
flows even to the angels; for, as will be stated farther on, Christ is the head
of the angels at least as regards accidental grace and glory, inasmuch as the
angels are His ministers in the kingdom of God. Jesus said, "The Son of man
shall send His angels, and they shall gather out of His kingdom all scandals,
and all them that work iniquity, and shall cast them into the furnace of
fire."[942] He likewise said: "He shall send His angels and shall
gather together His elect."[943]
From these texts it is evident that Christ has a higher degree of grace than
all angels and men combined, including the blessed, just as in a way the sun is
brighter in its intensity than any lesser light whatever, and iron is of more
value than a huge pile of common stones. Moreover, it is also said of the
Blessed Virgin Mary that her first fullness of grace excelled in intensity the
final degree of grace, though not the glory of angels and men combined, and so
it is said: "The holy Mother of God has been raised above the choirs of
angels to the heavenly kingdom."[944]
It even appears to be true that the grace received by the founders of
religious orders excels, as regards the founding of the order, the grace of
their combined associates, in this sense, that these associates, unless their
founder had been especially inspired by God, would not have started this order,
whereas, contrary to this, the founder, deputed by God for this work, could have
done it with other companions. Thus the grace, either of St. Benedict or of St.
Dominic or of St. Francis, seems to excel the grace of his companions. Likewise,
the degree of grace in St. Thomas is greater than that of all his commentators
combined. This is more readily understood in that grace is a quality and hence
its perfection is qualitative but not quantitative. Consequently, grace that is
equivalent for ten talents is of a higher degree than ten graces each of which
is equivalent to one talent. Thus a saint, such as the saintly parish priest of
Ars, has a greater degree of grace and accomplishes more than many of the
faithful and even priests whose charity is of a less degree.
Thus St. Thomas shows[945] that charity—and he says that the same applies
to habitual grace—is not increased in intensity by the addition of charity to
charity; for this would be a multiplication of charity, but not an increase of
it. It is increased, however, by becoming more firmly rooted in the recipient
or, not using metaphysical language, by a greater actuation or determination of,
and inherence in the recipient; for it is the nature of an accident to inhere.
All these statements are but one and the same way of expressing the
intensification of qualities. A new degree of charity, and a more perfect
actuation of this charity and of its inherence in the recipient, mean the same
thing.
If, then, a higher degree of grace is taken in a qualitative sense and not in
its quantitative sense, it is easy to see that Christ's habitual grace excels in
intensity even every ultimate grace of men and angels combined. From the moment
of His conception it excelled their glory.
St. Thomas teaches that this fullness of grace is of three kinds. He says:
"There is sufficient fullness by which anyone has sufficient grace to
perform meritorious and excellent acts, as St. Stephen did. There is likewise
redundant fullness by which the Blessed Virgin excelled all the saints on
account of the eminence and abundance of her merits. There is also efficient and
affluent fullness, which applies to Christ alone as man, as to the quasi-author
of grace. Thus there was an outpouring of grace on us by the Blessed Virgin, yet
she was by no means the author of grace.... Christ's fullness of grace is the
cause of all the graces in all intellectual creatures."[946]
St. Thomas says in this text, "of all graces" in general; he does
not, however, determine the kind, and he does not say "even of essential
grace and glory" in the angels, which elsewhere he denies.[947]
Objection. There would be great disproportion in the natural body if the head
were larger than the rest of the body. Therefore, for a similar reason, there
would be disproportion in the mystical body if the grace of Christ as its head
were in intensity to exceed or equal all the grace of those that constitute His
mystical body.
Reply. Gonet answers this objection by conceding the antecedent and denying
the consequence, because, as he points out, a distinction must be made between
quality and quantity, and there is by no means parity of argument between the
mystical body and the natural body. There is indeed similarity of comparison
between the two bodies as regards the influx of the head in the members and its
pre-eminence over them. But in the natural body the substantial form demands a
determinate quantity, both in the head and in the members, that the body may be
able to perform its vital operations: and so it is necessary that our head be
smaller than our body. Moreover, since habitual grace is the form that vivifies
the mystical body of the Church, it does not demand a determinate intensity, but
can be increased indefinitely.[948] Hence in the head of the mystical body there
can be a greater intensification of grace than in all other persons, and this
even pertains to the dignity of the head. Finally, there is in no way any vital
dependence of the mystical body on the members, whereas, on the contrary, the
head of the physical body depends on the heart, lungs, and other parts.
Eleventh Article: Whether The Grace Of Christ Is Infinite
State of the question. This article is evidently not strictly concerned with
the increate grace of union, for St. Thomas said: "The grace of union is
the personal being that is given gratis from above to the human nature in the
person of the Word."[949] This increate grace of union is infinite inasmuch
as it is identical with the very Word of God that terminates the human nature.
But it is strictly a question here of habitual grace which is "an effect
following the union."[950]
Theologians are not all agreed on this point. Major[951] asserts that
Christ's grace is absolutely infinite in intensity. Maldonatus[952] and
Hurtado[953] afterward said the same. St. Bonaventure, Durandus, Scotus,
Ricardus, and the Thomists Cajetan and Nazarius are of the same opinion, since
they taught that Christ's grace could not be increased by God's absolute power.
But the opposite opinion seems far more probable and more in conformity with the
teaching of St. Thomas, and it is commonly held by theologians, not only of the
Thomist school of thought, but also of other schools.
St. Thomas splendidly presents the difficulty of the question at the
beginning of this article, where he remarks that Christ's grace appears to be
infinite, because the Gospel declares it to be measureless or immense, saying:
"God doth not give His Spirit by measure";[954] whereas, contrary to
this, St. Paul says of others: "To every one of us is given grace,
according to the measure of the giving of Christ."[955] Moreover, Christ's
grace extends to the whole human race. Finally, if Christ's grace were finite,
then some other person's grace might increase so much as to equal Christ's
grace. These objections consider in habitual grace, not only the being of grace,
but also the nature of grace.
Nevertheless it is evidently true to say that Christ's habitual grace,
inasmuch as it is distinct from His grace of union, is something created. But
everything created is finite, as stated in the counter-argument of this article.
Therefore Christ's habitual grace must be finite.
How is this question to be solved? The article must be read.
First conclusion. The grace of union is infinite, because it is the very
person of the Word, who terminates Christ's human nature, as stated above.[956]
Second conclusion. Christ's habitual grace, inasmuch as it is a being, or
considered as an entity, is not physically infinite, because it is in Christ's
soul, as an accident is in its subject. But Christ's soul is a certain creature
having finite capacity. It will be made clear in the following article that
grace can always be increased, but considered as a being, since it is something
created, it can never be physically and actually infinite.
Third conclusion. Christ's habitual grace, not considered as a being, but
according to what strictly pertains to the notion of grace, can be termed
infinite.[957] Almost all Thomists understand this conclusion in this sense,
namely, that Christ's grace is in its notion of grace morally infinite, though
not physically so.[958] For St. Thomas says: "As stated above (q. 7, a. 12)
there cannot be a greater grace than the grace of Christ with respect to the
union with the Word; and the same is to be said of the perfection of the divine
vision; although, absolutely speaking, there could be a higher and-more sublime
degree by the infinity of the divine power."[959] He says the same in the
reply to the second objection of the next article of this question.[960] Neither
does St. Thomas say, concerning this third conclusion of ours: "We must say
that Christ's grace, considered as grace, is infinite," but he says
"it can be termed infinite," which means, if interpreted in some good
sense.
Hence this third conclusion thus understood of grace that is morally infinite
viewed in its specific nature of grace, is easily proved.
Two proofs are given in the body of this article, inasmuch as this grace is
considered both intensively and extensively.
Intensive proof. Christ's habitual grace is intensively infinite because it
has whatever can pertain to the nature of grace, and it is not bestowed "in
a fixed measure," just as we may say that the light of the sun is infinite,
not indeed in being, but in the nature of light, inasmuch as it has whatever can
pertain to the nature of light.
This means that Christ's habitual grace is according to its intensity in the
highest degree of its excellence capable of being bestowed on others, at least
according to God's ordination and His ordinary power.[961]
We shall see that it can be increased by God's absolute power.[962] Moreover,
it must be noticed that the three objections placed at the beginning of the
present article conclude that Christ's grace, considered in its specific nature,
is also infinite, and that this is denied in the counter-argument.
Something of very great importance must be added here which is implied in the
present article,[963] namely, that this habitual grace of Christ, by reason of
its union with the Word, is the principle by which Christ performs meritorious
and satisfactory acts that are intrinsically and absolutely infinite in value.
This infinity, although it comes from the divine person as the principle that
operates, nevertheless redounds in moral value and worth on the habitual grace
that is the principle by which Christ performs meritorious acts that are
strictly and intrinsically infinite in value. Farther on we discuss the commonly
accepted thesis of Thomists and almost all theologians, with the exception of
Scotists, namely, that Christ's operations were not only extrinsically accepted
by God, but they were also intrinsically "absolutely infinite in value both
for meriting and for satisfying."[964]
All these things considered, it is no wonder that St. Thomas says in this
article, concerning Christ's habitual grace taken in its intensity, that it can
be termed infinite, viewed in its specific nature of grace, though he afterward
adds that it can be increased by God's absolute power.[965]
Extensive proof. Christ's habitual grace is at least morally infinite
because, as St. Thomas says in this article, it is bestowed on Christ's soul, as
on a universal principle for bestowing grace on human nature. St. Paul says:
"He hath graced us in His beloved Son."[966] This means that Christ's
habitual grace extends to all effects that pertain to the nature of grace, even
to those that are syncategorematically infinite. Thus we shall see that this
habitual grace is called the grace of headship, inasmuch as by it there flows
from Christ upon the members of the Church (through the influx of His merits)
grace and glory; but glory is without end, since it is eternal life.[967]
But if Christ's grace does not extend so far as to merit the essential grace
of Adam in the state of innocence and of the angels, this is not because it did
not have the power, but because these were not included in the divine ordering.
Hence Christ's grace viewed in its specific nature of grace is morally infinite,
both in intensity and extent.
The answer of St. Thomas, as understood in the sense stated above, receives
its confirmation in the solution of the objections.
First objection. The Gospel declares: "God doth not give the Spirit by
measure[to the Son]."[968] Therefore Christ's grace is infinite.
St. Thomas replies that the words of the Baptist as recorded by St. John can
refer: (1) either to the eternal and infinite gift, namely, to the divine nature
which the Father from all eternity communicated to the Son; (2) or to the grace
of union that is infinite inasmuch as the Word terminates the human nature; (3)
or to habitual grace inasmuch as it extends to all that pertains to grace,
namely, to the word of wisdom or to the word of knowledge, or to other such
gifts.
Hence St. Thomas does not concede the conclusion of the objection, that
Christ's habitual grace is absolutely and physically infinite, so that it cannot
be greater by God's absolute power.
Reply to second objection. "The grace of Christ has an infinite
effect," which means that it includes the salvation of the whole human race
"both because of the aforesaid infinity of grace," which for this
reason is called the grace of headship, and because of the unity[969] of the
divine person, to whom Christ's soul is united. Thus, as we said, Christ's
habitual grace, because of its union with the Word, is the principle by which
His meritorious and satisfactory acts for us were intrinsically of absolutely
infinite validity, and He could have merited eternal life for an ever greater
and vast number of human beings, even though, for example, the generations of
human beings were to continue even after the end of the world.
By this reply St. Thomas shows that he does not concede the conclusion of
this second objection, which is that Christ's habitual grace viewed in this
sense is absolutely and physically infinite, so that it cannot by God's absolute
power be increased.
Third objection. It states that, "if Christ's grace were finite, then
the grace of any other man could increase to such an extent as to reach to an
equality with Christ's grace." The Beghards were condemned for saying:
"If one could always advance in perfection, then someone more perfect than
Christ could be found."[970]
Reply. St. Thomas does not say that Christ's habitual grace is physically and
absolutely infinite viewed in its specific nature of grace, but he says:
"The grace of any man is compared to the grace of Christ as a particular to
a universal power." By way of illustration, the light of the moon, no
matter how much it may increase in intensity, cannot equal in intensity the
light of the sun from which it receives its light. For the moon does not have
its own light, but transmits the light it has received from the sun. St. Thomas,
in accordance with the physics of ancient times, made use of another example
because he thought the stars were incorruptible, and the light and heat of the
sun were of a kind different from the heat of terrestrial fire. Spectral
analysis, however, has established the fact that the stars are not
incorruptible, but that the same chemical combinations take place in these as on
this earth.
Therefore Christ's habitual grace is a finite being, and viewed in its
specific nature of grace, if it is not physically infinite, is at least morally
infinite, both in its intensity and in its extent, inasmuch as it concurs with
the grace of union to produce merit that is intrinsically of infinite validity.
Cajetan, in his commentary on this article, adverting to the fact of his
recent elevation to the cardinalate, considers this all the more a reason why
the mysteries of Christ should be examined and made known to all. His purpose is
to show that Christ's habitual grace is in Him in all the perfection that grace
as such can have. In other words, this grace is in Christ "as in the whole
that is equivalent to it as such," just as heat is not in the air but in
the fire; just as a line could be infinite in length, viewed as a line, although
finite as a being, just as whiteness, which is finite indeed, as a being, since
it is an accident, is intensively infinite in its nature of whiteness, since
there could not be a more perfect whiteness.
Nevertheless Cajetan maintains[971] that Christ's habitual grace, as well as
that of others, is of the same most particular species, as regards its essence;
the difference is only as regards the mode of its being, just as heat differs in
its mode of being as found in terrestrial fire and in the air.[972]
Let us see in what Cajetan agrees and disagrees with other Thomists.
Cajetan[973] maintains, indeed, with other Thomists, that charity can always
be increased in this life, and that charity in itself has no ultimately possible
degree, because it is a participation of infinite charity and so it differs from
heat and from whiteness. But Cajetan is not in agreement with other Thomists
when he says that charity in itself does not exclude the highest possible degree
of this virtue, especially so if it is ordered to the greatest possible union,
namely, the hypostatic union, for then it has, as proportionate to this union,
the highest possible degree of this virtue, as heat in fire, and whiteness in
snow.
Other Thomists justly reply to him by saying that there is a greater
difference between habitual grace or charity and natural qualities, such as heat
in fire and whiteness in snow.
First difference. These natural qualities have their own intrinsic and finite
specification, and are not defined with reference to something else; whereas
habitual grace is defined as a formal and physical participation in the divine
nature, the possibility of this participation being infinite. Thus of itself
there is no limit to it, but it even excludes this, which means that it seeks
intrinsically to have syncategorematically no limitation, which means that the
highest possible degree of habitual grace, or of charity or of the light of
glory, is intrinsically repugnant, just as the absolutely swiftest motion is a
contradiction in terms, for it is always possible to conceive a swifter motion,
accomplished in a shorter time, that is however distinct from the indivisible
instant of time.
Second difference. Natural qualities, such as heat in fire—a better
illustration is whiteness in snow—are natural properties of some natural and
finite substance; whereas habitual grace is not a natural property of the
created intellectual substance, not even of Christ's soul as united with the
Word, because it flows in a certain measure not necessarily, but freely from the
Word, a point that will be more clearly explained in the following article.[974]
Third difference. Natural qualities, such as heat and whiteness, are received
in the subject according to its passive and finite natural power, whereas
habitual grace is received in the subject not according to its natural power,
but its obediential power. And St. Thomas says: "The obediential power,
inasmuch as it can receive something from God, is not limited in this respect
because, whatever God does in the creature, there still remains in it the power
to accept something from God."[975]
Finally, grace is something freely given that is dependent in its measure on
the divine good pleasure.
Cajetan seeks to defend his opinion and says: "It is possible for one to
have a higher degree of the vision of God (than the degree granted to the soul
of Christ) from a more sublime intellect equally illumined,"[976] in other
words, if to an equal degree of the light of glory an angel were assumed by the
Word of God into unity of person.
Other Thomists reply that then the degree of the beatific vision would not be
formally more sublime but only materially; in fact, not even materially, because
this angel would not have a clearer vision of the divine essence, which is an
essentially supernatural object that absolutely transcends the power of
whatsoever created intellect, as Alvarez remarks.[977]
Cajetan likewise sets forth his same view in his treatise on charity.[978] He
maintains especially in his great commentary, that charity in this life can
always be increased and in itself this virtue is not found in the highest
possible degree, though it does not exclude this degree, as it excludes mortal
sin. In fact, for it to be proportionate to this union, then charity must be in
the highest possible degree.
Cajetan, seeking to magnify Christ's habitual grace, minimizes the sublimity
of absolutely assumed grace, as we shall see in the explanation of the following
article.
So far, Cajetan asserts but he does not prove that Christ's habitual grace is
not in the highest possible degree. We shall see in the explanation of the
following article what he adds in confirmation of his special opinion.
Twelfth Article: Whether The Grace Of Christ Could Increase
State of the question. St. Thomas clearly sets forth the difficulty of this
problem, for he says:
1) To every finite thing addition can be made. But Christ's habitual grace,
as we said, considered as a being, is finite. Therefore it can be increased.
2) Also considered as grace, it seems that it can be increased, for increase
of grace is effected by divine power; and since this power is absolutely
infinite, there are no limits to it.
3) The Evangelist says that "Jesus advanced in wisdom and age. and grace
with God and men."[979]
Conclusion. Christ's habitual grace could not be increased after the first
moment of His conception, either on the part of the grace itself, or on the part
of the recipient of this grace. Thus Christ differs from all others, even from
the Blessed Virgin and the angels, who were wayfarers and not comprehensors.
Let us first of all examine the proofs of this article; afterward we shall
consider Cajetan's interpretation; finally we shall discuss the interpretation
of other Thomists.
Scriptural proof. The Evangelist says: "We saw His glory, the glory as
it were of the only-begotten of the Father, full of grace and truth."[980]
"But nothing can be or can be thought greater than that anyone should be
the begotten of the Father. Therefore no greater grace can be or can be thought
than that of which Christ was full."[981] Thus we said in the preceding
article that Christ's grace is at least morally infinite inasmuch as it is the
principle by means of which He performed meritorious and satisfactory acts that
are of absolutely infinite value. Thus Christ's habitual grace absolutely excels
the grace of all men and angels combined.
Moreover, the Second Council of Constantinople defined: "If anyone
defends the assertion that Christ... as He advanced in the performance of good
works became better... let him be declared anathema."[982] This means that
Christ did not either become more perfect, or was subjected to passions, or
offered sacrifice for Himself.[983] In this Christ differs from all the just,
even from the angels in heaven, who became more perfect in the second instant of
their creation, since they were wayfarers and merited, and after this they were
only comprehensors. But if St. Luke says that "Jesus advanced in wisdom and
age, and grace with God and men,"[984] St. Thomas replies in this article,
along with the whole of ecclesiastical tradition: "Christ did not increase
inasmuch as the very habits of wisdom and grace were increased in Him..., but as
regards the effects, ... since in the course of time He did more perfect works,
to prove Himself true man, both in the things of God and in the things of
man."[985] The Greek and Latin Fathers generally take this view when they
speak of the fullness of Christ's grace.[986]
Theological proof. There are two subdivisions to this proof.
a) On the part of the recipient of this grace, Christ's grace could not be
increased from the beginning, because as man He was from the first moment of His
conception truly and completely comprehensor, as will be made clear farther
on.[987] But in comprehensors, or in the blessed, there can be no increase of
grace, subjectively speaking, for they have already reached their final end to
which they were eternally predestined. Therefore, subjectively speaking, there
can be no increase in Christ's grace.
b) On the part of grace. Christ's grace from the beginning could not be
increased, because Christ as man was from the beginning personally united with
the Word, and He already received, as St. Thomas says in this article, "the
highest measure of grace."
This consequence is proved by one syllogism on which Cajetan very much
insists.
It is in reference to the end that a measure is prefixed to each form; for
example, in accordance with the physics of the ancients, there is no greater
gravity than that of the earth because there is no lower place than that of the
earth. Or, as we now can say, in our solar world there is no greater light and
heat than the light and heat of the sun, which is the center of attraction of
this solar world.
But the end of grace is the union of the rational creature with God, and
there cannot be a greater union than the hypostatic union of Christ's human
nature with the Word.
Therefore, from the moment of His conception, Christ's grace attained its
highest degree of grace, and there was no possibility of its future increase;
whereas, on the contrary, the first fullness of grace in the Blessed Virgin
always received an increase of this grace until it acquired its consummate
fullness when she entered heaven.
St. Thomas determines more clearly the force of this conclusion in his
replies to the objections placed at the beginning of this article.
Reply to first objection. To the proposed difficulty that "to every
finite thing addition can be made," St. Thomas replies by making the
following distinction: that addition can be made to every finite mathematical
quantity, namely, to every line, to every number, I concede; that addition can
be made to every natural quantity I deny, for example, the quantity or height of
a dog or a horse, or an elephant, or a man cannot always be increased. St.
Thomas concludes at the end of his reply by saying: "Hence it is not
necessary that addition should be capable of being made to Christ's grace,"
although it is finite in its essence, which means that it is finite as having
reached "the highest measure of grace" as stated toward the end of the
argumentative part of this article.
Second objection. "It is by divine power that grace is increased and,
since this power is infinite, it is confined by no limits."
Reply. St. Thomas answers by saying: "Although the divine power can make
something greater and better than the habitual grace of Christ, yet it could not
make it to be ordained to anything greater than the personal union with the
only-begotten Son of the Father; and the measure of grace corresponds
sufficiently (not adequately) to this union, in accordance with the definition
of divine wisdom." This text is of great importance. Similarly farther on
it is stated that, "absolutely speaking, there could be a higher and more
sublime degree[of the beatific vision] by the infinity of the divine
power."[988]
Concerning the interpretation of this second reply and of what is said in the
body of this article, Cajetan and Nazarius differ from the rest of the Thomists,
both ancient and modern. Let us consider each interpretation.
Cajetan's interpretation.
Cajetan gives the following interpretation to this article. He himself says:
"What is substantially for the end must be commensurate with the end (as
the shape of the saw for the cutting of wood), ... wherefore, since the tendency
of a heavy object is to fall down, ... the lowest point to which an object can
fall must be governed and measured only by the maximum influence exerted on it
by the law of gravitation. Thus the greatest union of the rational creature with
God must be measured only by the greatest grace."[989] Farther on Cajetan
remarks: "Therefore Christ's grace is finite and at the same time it
excludes addition."[990]
In the reply to the second objection, when St. Thomas says that "God can
make something greater and better than the habitual grace of Christ,"
Cajetan introduces the following distinction: that God can make something
greater and better inasmuch as it is a being, this I concede; inasmuch as it is
ordained to its proper end, which is the hypostatic union, this I deny.[991]
Criticism. Cajetan does not sufficiently explain the words of St. Thomas in
his reply to the second objection, when he says: "To this[hypostatic] union
such measure of grace is correspondingly sufficient, according to the definition
of divine wisdom" or the divine ordination. He also does not explain the
similar and clearer text of St. Thomas concerning the higher degree of the light
of glory that is possible by God's absolute power.[992]
It is of no avail to say that God can produce something better than Christ's
grace because this is an accident, and God can produce substance or even give to
an angel the same degree of the light of glory.
In these considerations Cajetan, who almost always views problems in their
formal aspect, seems to understand the reply to the second objection of this
article in a material sense, as well as the other reply similar to this.[993]
He seems to stress too much the quasi-material aspect in the subject of grace
and the fact that grace is an accident, and not a substance.
Now indeed, as St. Thomas says: "The good of grace in one is greater
than the good of nature in the whole universe"[994] that is, than all
created and creatable creatures. Hence, when St. Thomas says, "The divine
power can make something greater and better than the habitual grace of
Christ,"[995] his purpose is not to speak of substance God can produce. Nor
does it seem true, as stated above, that an angel, who would have the same
degree of the light of glory as the soul of Christ, would have a clearer vision
of the divine essence, because the divine essence is an essentially supernatural
object, which does not seem to be seen more clearly because of the keener
penetration of a material and created intellect.
Common interpretation of Thomists.
Such are Capreolus, Bannez, John of St. Thomas, Salmanticenses, Gonet,
Billuart, and others.
To understand this interpretation, we must bear in mind the division commonly
admitted by the Thomists about the divine power. It may be expressed by the
following schema.[996]
[diagram page 303]
DIVINE POWER
absolute
ordained
extraordinary
ordinary
according to hypostatic order
ascending to order of grace
according to natural order
spiritual
corporal
The merely absolute divine power is the divine power considered apart from
the ordination of divine wisdom, and so considered it refers to all things not
intrinsically repugnant even though they may be extrinsically repugnant on the
part of the end.[997]
Thus God, by His merely absolute power, could annihilate all the blessed in
heaven, even the Blessed Virgin and Christ's human nature, since He freely
preserves these in being. This annihilation is not intrinsically repugnant but
extrinsically repugnant on the part of the end, for on the part of the end there
can be no purpose in this annihilation. Hence this annihilation is repugnant to
God's power as regulated by divine wisdom.
The ordained divine power is that which refers to the ordaining of divine
wisdom, and it concerns everything that is neither intrinsically repugnant, nor
extrinsically repugnant on the part of the end.
It is divided into ordinary and extraordinary. The ordinary ordained divine
power is that which operates in accordance with the laws as established by God,
either in the natural order, or in the supernatural order, or even in the order
of the hypostatic union.
It is called extraordinary, when it is called into action and reaches beyond
the above-mentioned laws either of the natural order (as when miracles of the
physical order are performed) or of the supernatural order (such as a sudden and
miraculous conversion as in the case of the conversion of St. Paul) or of those
that pertain to the hypostatic union. Thus the question is put, whether Christ's
habitual grace could have been greater by God's absolute power, and also by His
ordained power and His extraordinary power, so that the Incarnation could have
taken place without Christ suffering. There seems to be no doubt that the
fullness of even the grace acquired by the Blessed Virgin Mary at the time of
her death could have been intensively greater not only by God's absolute power
but even by His ordained power and also His extraordinary power.
These principles established, Thomists almost unanimously hold that by God's
absolute power Christ's habitual grace could have been increased in intensity,
although He actually had the highest possible degree of such grace by God's
ordained and ordinary power. So say Capreolus,[998] Bannez, Medina, John of St.
Thomas, Alvarez, Suarez, Vasquez, and others, against the Scotists and Cajetan.
John of St. Thomas says that this opinion is more probable and undoubtedly
more according to the mind of St. Thomas. This seems to be proved when he says:
"As stated above, there cannot be a greater grace than the grace of Christ
with respect to the union with the Word; and the same is to be said of the
perfection of the divine vision; although, absolutely speaking, there could be a
higher and more sublime degree by the infinity of the divine power."[999]
So says St. Thomas in this passage, and he is plainly speaking of God's absolute
power and he cites and explains what he had said previously about Christ's
grace.[1000]
To be sure, Cajetan says that Christ's beatific vision could increase, not
because of a greater light of glory but because of a greater natural power, for
example, if the Word were to assume an angelic nature.
Reply. The beatific vision is regulated and measured only according to the
elevating power which is the light of glory; for the vision itself is an
essentially supernatural act, specified by an essentially supernatural object,
which infinitely transcends the natural vigor of any created or creatable
intellect whatever.
Doubt. Is it possible to conceive a grace and light of glory of a higher
species, and can Christ's grace be of a higher species than ours?
Reply. The answer is, No, for the following reasons. (1) Because grace, as in
the just and in Christ is already a formal and physical participation in the
Deity, having in each case the same definition, and there cannot be anything
capable of participation that is higher than the divine nature or the Deity as
it is in Itself, or in other words, God's intimate life; this view is against a
certain thesis of Father Billot.[1001]
2) Because otherwise Christ would not contain in Himself all the effects of
grace if He did not have a certain species of grace. Therefore the only possible
conception of a higher beatific vision is that resulting from a greater
penetration of the divine essence and from an increase in the intensity of
habitual grace and of the light of glory in the same species.
This same interpretation is also proved from the previous reply of St. Thomas
to his query about the possibility of charity being increased infinitely. He
says: "In no way, either on the part of the form or of the agent or of the
subject is a limit to be set to the increase of charity in this life. For there
is no limit to the increase of charity in what properly belongs to it in its
species, for it is a certain participation of infinite charity, which is the
Holy Spirit. Similarly also the causal agent of charity is infinite in power,
for it is God. Similarly, too, on the part of the subject, there can be no
pre-assigned terminus set to this increase since the greater the increase, the
greater the aptitude for further increase."[1002] because as St. Thomas
also says here, "by it[charity] the heart expands."[1003] As we
already remarked, St. Thomas says: "The obediential power, inasmuch as it
can receive something from God, is not limited in this respect, because whatever
God does in the creature, there still remains in it the power to receive
something from God";[1004] for the obediential power in the creature has
immediate reference not to some object that must be known or loved, or to some
act that must be elicited, but it has reference to the absolutely free agent,
who is infinite in power, whom it obeys and from whom it can always receive
something.
Hence we must conclude, as St. Thomas says in this article: "By the
purpose of divine wisdom, the measure of grace is sufficient for this[hypostatic]
union."[1005]
John of St. Thomas remarks: "Clearly St. Thomas signifies that the end
in view of that grace is union with the Word, not in the absolute sense, but as
it serves the purpose of divine Wisdom, who assigned such measure of grace to
Christ. Hence we conclude that by another purpose of divine Wisdom, there is
nothing repugnant in a different measure and increase of grace being given to
Christ."[1006]
Solution of objections.
Objection. St. Thomas says in his counter-argument to this twelfth article:
"Therefore no greater grace can be or can be thought than that of which
Christ was full."
Reply. That St. Thomas says this about Christ's grace with reference to its
extrinsic end, which is the hypostatic union, of which he speaks in the
preceding article of this question, and as it serves the purpose of divine
Wisdom, with which his reply to the second objection of this article is
concerned, this I concede; that he says this about Christ's grace taken in the
absolute sense of the term and independently of the purpose of divine Wisdom,
this I deny.
Thus Christ's grace on account of the union of His human nature with the
person of the Word, was the greatest in this order in which it is produced; that
is, it is connaturally the greatest, for the purpose or ordination of divine
Wisdom that pre-assigned the connatural limits to all forms, according to the
connatural order in which these were established by this Wisdom. As God, who
gave to St. Peter, to St. John, and to St. Paul, also to St. Augustine, and to
St. Thomas a fitting degree of wisdom and charity, could have given them a
higher degree, so He gave Christ a higher degree of grace, but on absolute
consideration He could have given Christ a higher degree, because the highest
possible degree cannot be conceived. Thus the final argument fittingly
terminates the best sermon, although, absolutely speaking, there could still be
another exhortation.
Another objection. St. Thomas said in the preceding article: "Christ's
grace has whatsoever can pertain to the nature of grace."
Reply. This must be understood from the immediate context and from other
texts of St. Thomas in this same question, because we cannot suppose that He
contradicted himself. In other words, he meant that Christ's grace has whatever
pertains to the nature of grace, considered in its moral aspect and with
reference to its union with the Word.
Finally, God's power would be exhausted if He could produce nothing more
perfect by His absolute power, and even by His extraordinary ordained power.
Final objection. If a higher degree of grace were possible, then Christ would
have merited this grace, for His merits were of infinite value.
Reply. That Christ would have merited a higher degree of grace if He had not
already been a comprehensor and beyond the condition of wayfarer, let this pass
without comment; but although the comprehensor, by means of grace performs many
good works, this neither increases grace nor merits an increase of it in the
comprehensor, as is evident in the blessed, who in this respect are like to God,
inasmuch as God's works can in no way increase His perfection. God did not
become better by the fact that He created the universe or sent His Son into the
world for our salvation.
If Christ merited the glorification of His body, the reason is that the
temporary lack of this glorification of the body was conducive to the end of
redemption; whereas, on the contrary, He had from the beginning grace in the
highest degree according to His connatural state both as comprehensor and as
wayfarer, and thus He absolutely transcended all the just, both angels and men.
The Second Council of Constantinople declared that Christ was not made better by
advancing in the performance of good works.[1007] On the contrary, the Blessed
Virgin, by her continuous and uninterrupted performance of meritorious acts
until death, was made better.
Corollary. Hence Christ adored God's supreme good pleasure by which He
simultaneously freely willed the Incarnation and determined the degree of
habitual grace befitting the Word incarnate. In this also Christ could say:
"I confess to Thee, O Father, Lord of heaven and earth... for so hath it
seemed good in Thy sight."[1008] God's most free decrees must be adored and
they are infinitely good, since they are decrees that are the result of infinite
wisdom and of infinite love. From this the sublimity of the Deity and of grace
taken in the absolute sense, which by God's absolute power can always be
increased, is more clearly seen since it is a participation of the divine
nature, which is always capable of participation in a more sublime way.
Thirteenth Article: Whether The Habitual Grace Of Christ Followed After The
Union
Reply. The grace of union precedes the habitual grace of Christ, not in order
of time but by nature and in thought, and this for three reasons.
1) Because of the principles of both graces. For the mission of the Son by
the Incarnation precedes by nature the mission of the Holy Spirit by habitual
grace and charity, just as in the order of nature the Holy Spirit proceeds from
the Son.
2) Because of the relation of grace to its cause. For Christ's habitual grace
is caused by God's presence in Him through His personal union with the Word just
as the brightness of the sun comes from the sun.
3) Because of the end of grace. For the purpose of grace is good action, and
actions belong to the suppositum and presuppose the suppositum constituted in
being. Therefore Christ's habitual grace, since the purpose of it is good
action, presupposes the union of the human nature with the Word.
Reply to second objection. "Habitual grace is not understood to have
preceded the union but to have followed it, as a natural property";
however, as already stated, the degree of this habitual grace does not flow of
necessity from the Word, but "the measure of grace is sufficient to this
union by the purpose of divine Wisdom."[1009]
This terminates the question of Christ's grace inasmuch as He is a certain
individual man. This question presents to us a sublime illustration of the
definition of grace, inasmuch as now we see more clearly that there cannot be a
nobler species of habitual grace than ours, or a more exalted species of the
beatific vision than that which the blessed possess.
CHAPTER X: QUESTION 8: CHRIST'S GRACE AS HEAD OF THE CHURCH
There are two parts to this question.
First part. It treats of grace which befits Christ as head of the Church (a.
1-6).
The first article considers the meaning of the expression, head of the
Church. Then there is a discussion of the grace of headship as it extends to men
and angels (a. 2-4).
Finally whether to be head of the Church is proper to Christ.
Second part. It concerns the devil and Antichrist. Is the devil the head of
all the wicked? (a. 7.) Can Antichrist be called the head of all the wicked? (a.
8.)
It must first of all be noted that this whole doctrine has its foundation in
the epistles of St. Paul, in which Christ is often spoken of as the head of the
Church. Christ indeed had already said, as reported by the Evangelist: "I
am the true vine, and My Father is the husbandman. Every branch in Me that
beareth not fruit He will take away; and everyone that beareth fruit He will
purge it that it may bring forth more fruit.... I am the vine, you the branches;
He that abideth in Me, and I in Him, the same beareth much fruit; for without Me
you can do nothing. If anyone abide not in Me, he shall be cast forth as a
branch, and shall wither, and they shall gather him up and cast him into the
fire, and he burneth."[1010]
This same doctrine is developed under another analogy, namely, of the head
and mystical body of Christ, in whom the faithful must gradually be
incorporated, by participating in the hidden life of Christ, His public life,
His sorrowful life, and finally His glorious life. As St. Paul often says in the
following text and in others: "He[God]... hath made Him[Christ] head over
all the Church, which is His body, and the fullness of Him who is filled all in
all."[1011]
First Article: Whether Christ Is The Head Of The Church
State of the question. We are concerned with the Church, though the title of
the article does not as yet determine whether we are concerned only with the
Church militant, or also with the Church triumphant, for this will be determined
farther on. We are also concerned with Christ as man.
The difficulties are these: (1) The head imparts sense and motion to the
members, and it seems, as St. Augustine says, that Christ as man does not give
the Holy Spirit, and hence He does not impart spiritual sense and motion to
those men who are the faithful of His Church. (2) Furthermore, the head of man
receives an inflow of blood from the heart, for just as it could not live
without receiving this influx of blood from the heart, and its re-oxygenation in
the lungs, so the head of man is dependent on the heart, the lungs, and also on
other organs; whereas, on the contrary, Christ does not depend either formally
or efficiently, or finally on the faithful, but they depend on Him. Thus this
article is most appropriate for the discernment of the dissimilarities and
similarities in this analogy.
Reply. Christ as man is head of the Church. The expression "as man"
must not be understood absolutely in its reduplicative sense, as if it meant
solely by reason of Christ's human nature, but it must be taken in its special
sense, namely, as man subsisting by the divine personality, which will be more
clearly explained farther on.
Scriptural proof. The following text is especially cogent: "God...
raising Him up from the dead, and setting Him on His right hand in the heavenly
places... hath made Him head over all the Church."[1012] It is manifest,
however, that St. Paul is here speaking of Christ as man, for he says that He
was raised from the dead.
St. Paul has developed this doctrine at considerable length in his epistles,
from which he proceeds to establish four conclusions.
1) Christ is the head of the regenerated human race raised to the
supernatural and fallen from it. St. Paul says: "For if by the offense of
one many died, much more the grace of God, and the gift, by the grace of one
man, Jesus Christ, hath abounded unto many.... For if by the offense of one many
died, much more the grace of God, and the gift, by the grace of one man, Jesus
Christ, hath abounded unto many.... For if by one man's offense death reigned
through one, much more they who receive abundance of grace, and of the gift and
of justice, shall reign in life through one, Jesus Christ. Therefore, as by the
offense of one, unto all men to condemnation, so also by the justice of one unto
all men to justification of life."[1013]
For God permits evil only for a greater good, and He permitted Adam's sin
only for the greater good of the redemptive Incarnation, as we showed above,
when discussing the motive of the Incarnation.[1014]
St. Paul likewise says: "For as in one body we have many members, but
all the members have not the same office, so we being many, are one body in
Christ, and everyone members one of another."[1015]
2) St. Paul teaches that the influx of Christ as head over all men, even the
angels as His ministers, presupposes the great pre-eminence of Christ. Most
striking is the following text: "You are filled in Him[Christ], who is the
head of all principality and power."[1016]
3) St. Paul says that this influx of Christ as head makes itself felt on
various persons throughout the course of the centuries. Thus he writes:
"The whole body... groweth unto the increase of God."[1017]
4) St. Paul insists on the unity of this mystical body, both as regards the
head, source of this influence, and as regards the end of this unity. In many
texts he speaks of our common participation in the blood of Christ.[1018]
This doctrine of Christ's headship is de fide, not only as contained in
Scripture and the ordinary teaching authority of the Church, but it is also the
teaching of the Council of Trent, which says: "For whereas Jesus Christ
Himself continually infuses His virtue into the said justified, as the head into
the members and the vine into the branches, and this virtue always precedes and
accompanies and follows their good works, which without it could not in any wise
be pleasing and meritorious before God...."[1019] The Council likewise
says: "If anyone denies that Christ whole and entire, the fountain and
author of all graces, is received under the one species of bread, because, as
some falsely assert, He is not received, according to the institution of Christ
Himself, under both species; let him be anathema."[1020]
In the body of the article, St. Thomas gives three reasons why Christ is
fittingly called the head of the Church, according to a metaphorical analogy in
which there is similarity of proportionality and also dissimilarity.
1) Argument from order. The head is the first part of man, that is, the
superior part. But Christ as man, on account of His nearness to God, by grace is
higher than all, for St. Paul says: "For whom He foreknew, He also
predestinated to be made conformable to the image of His Son, that He might be
the first-born among many brethren."[1021]
2) Argument from perfection. In the head flourish all the senses, both
interior and exterior. But Christ has the fullness of all graces, for the
Evangelist says: "We saw Him full of grace and truth."[1022]
3) Argument from power. From the head proceeds the motion and direction of
the members, by reason of the sensitive and motive power that resides in the
head. But Christ has the power of bestowing grace on all members of the Church,
for the Evangelist says: "Of His fullness we have all received."[1023]
Reply to first objection. Christ as God is the principal physical cause of
grace, and as man He is the meritorious or moral cause of grace for us, and
furthermore its physical instrumental or efficient cause, on which more must be
said farther on.[1024]
Therefore this analogy of proportionality is extremely appropriate, though it
is not analogy of proper proportionality, because, according to the strict
meaning of head, it designates the higher part of the animal; but the metaphor
is appropriate because of the above-mentioned similarities. There are also
dissimilarities, as in all analogies, especially in those that are metaphorical.
Reply to second objection. "A natural head depends on the other members
or organs, from which it receives nourishment; but the father of a family is
subject to the civil governor, and Christ as man is subject to God, so that
there is no reason why God cannot be the head of Christ."
In a general reply to the third objection it may be observed that the natural
head is dependent on other members and organs for its nutrition and life, and it
is therefore a member. Contrariwise, the moral head of the Church, Christ, is in
no way dependent on the members and the body for His spiritual life. Thus Christ
cannot be called a member of the Church; although St. Thomas in other passages
conceded that Christ can be called, though not in the strict sense of the term,
a member of the Church, since He is united with the Church as His mystical body,
and receives an influx from God as the principal head of the whole Church.[1025]
Third objection. Why cannot Christ be called the heart of the Church, since
the metaphor would be even more fitting, because the heart influences the head
and other members?
Reply to third objection. The head has a manifest pre-eminence over the other
members; but the heart has a certain hidden influence. And hence the Holy Ghost
is likened to the heart, since He invisibly quickens and unites the Church; but
Christ is likened to the head in His visible nature in which man is set over
man.
Second Article: Whether Christ Is Head Of Men As To Their Bodies Or Only As
To Their Souls
State of the question. The meaning of the title to this article is clear from
the tenor of the third objection, in which it is doubted whether Christ, even as
regards His body, is head over other men even as regards their bodies.
Reply. The answer is in the affirmative, for the whole human nature of Christ
is an instrument united with the divine nature in the operation of our
salvation, which was formerly accomplished in the passion of our Lord, and is
now instrumentally and physically continued in the Holy Eucharist.
Christ not only bestows both habitual and actual grace on the soul, but He
also influences our bodies, inasmuch as in this life He makes them to be
instruments that cooperate in our sanctification by the performance of the
external acts commanded by the virtues. Thus the infused virtues of temperance
and fortitude are in the sensitive appetite, and, after the resurrection of the
dead, Christ will be the instrumental and physical cause as regards the
glorification of the bodies of the saints.
Third Article: Whether Christ Is The Head Of All Men
State of the question. It is apparent from the difficulties posited at the
beginning of this article, for the objections declare: (1) Infidels do not at
all seem to be members of the Church, of which Christ is the head, because they
are in no way related to Christ, whom they do not even know. (2) In fact, many
of the faithful are in the state of mortal sin, and therefore do not seem to
belong to the Church, for St. Paul says: "Christ delivered Himself up for
the Church... that He might present it to Himself a glorious Church, not having
spot or wrinkle or any such thing."[1026] This difficulty as proposed here
was in later times the heretical teaching of John Hus and Quesnel, as will be
stated farther on. (3) It is not clear how Christ can be the head of those who
lived before Him in the Old Testament, for He could not have influenced them.
Reply. Christ is the head of all men, but in different degrees.
1) This doctrine is of faith, it being evidently the teaching of the New
Testament. St. Paul says: "Who[Christ] is the Savior of all men, especially
of the faithful."[1027] The Evangelist likewise says: "He is the
propitiation for our sins, and not for ours only, but also for those of the
whole world."[1028] The Church also condemned John Hus, who maintained that
it consisted only of the elect, and Quesnel, who declared that only the just
belong to the Church.[1029]
2) Theological proof. It is developed in the argumentative part of the
article, and may be expressed by the following syllogism.
Among the members of the mystical body, some are potentially members, and
others are actually members, since they are not all living at the same time or
all in the state of grace. But Christ is the head of all human beings, according
as they are members of His mystical body. Therefore Christ is the head of all
human beings either actually or potentially.
[diagram page 316]
MEMBERS
actually
by glory
by charity in this life
by faith only (these are imperfect members only relatively united with Christ
(ad 2)
potentially
destined to be
in eternity, by glory
in time, by faith and charity
those not destined to be
(this will always be so in adults because of some personal sin; for God does
not deny grace to one who does one's best)
This schema is clear enough in print, but it presupposes the great mystery of
predestination. The entire article should be read.
Corollary. Those who die not in the state of grace, "completely cease to
be Christ's members" because it is no longer potentially possible for them
to be united with Him.
Reply to first objection. "Those who are unbaptized, though not actually
in the Church, are in the Church potentially. And this potentiality is rooted in
two things: first and principally in the power of Christ, which is sufficient
for the salvation of the whole human race; secondly, in free will," for
they can still be converted to God.
Therefore the difference between the mystical head and the natural head is
this, that the former not only can preserve and direct those members it already
has, but it can also unite others to itself, and with reference to these it is
called a potential head.
Reply to second objection. The Church that has neither spot nor wrinkle is
the Church triumphant in heaven. But the Church militant actually consists both
of the just and the faithful in the state of mortal sin, and these are imperfect
members, being only in a qualified sense united with Christ.
This needs some explanation, because of what Quesnel maintained. For those
among the faithful who are in a state of mortal sin actually receive from Christ
an influx, which consists in a certain permanent bond, namely, in infused faith,
and by this bond they are permanently united with the other members of the
Church in one belief. Perfect union with Christ, indeed, requires charity. But
it is already something of great importance to preserve the gift of infused
faith.
This doctrine that was denied by John Hus and Quesnel, is manifestly in
agreement with what Sacred Scripture says. The Gospel compares the Church to a
threshing floor in which along with the wheat there is chaff that must be burnt,
or to a net cast into the sea that contains good and bad fishes;[1030] or it is
compared to ten virgins, five of whom were foolish, not having provided
themselves with the oil of charity.[1031] Thus the Fourth Council of the Lateran
defined the Church as a "congregation of the faithful", saying:
"There is but one universal Church of the faithful outside which absolutely
nobody is saved."[1032]
But if certain Fathers of the Church said that the wicked do not belong to
the Church, this must be understood as meaning that they are not perfect members
of the Church; they are, nevertheless, imperfect members if they have faith.
Those among the faithful who are in the state of mortal sin are called
members of the devil, or of the Babylonian city, inasmuch as they are turned
away from God; but they are called members of the Church, so far as they keep
the faith. So also in our bodies, a member that no longer has the sensitive life
is an imperfect member. Thus the hair and nails are still parts of the body.
Corollary. All who have faith are members of the Church, even if they are
only catechumens or schismatics, although it is true to say that schism easily
drifts into heresy, and there is scarcely any formal schismatic who was not a
heretic.
Reply to third objection. The ancient fathers of the Old Testament, "by
observing the legal sacraments, which were types of future things, were born to
Christ by the faith and love of charity", and so "they belonged to the
same body of the Church as we do." However, Christ, who merited for them
the grace of salvation, did not physically influence them, for a physical
influence presupposes the existence of the influencing cause. On the contrary,
the moral meritorious cause can be as yet non-existent and future, because it
moves not as actually existing, but as known as pertaining either to the future
or the past. Thus, on account of Christ's future merits, God bestowed grace on
the just of the Old Testament. They received medicinal grace and redemption
dependent on Christ's future merits, just as we receive such grace and
redemption dependent on Christ's past merits. But Christ always living now
exerts a physical influence on us, as the instrumental cause of grace.
First doubt. Is Christ actually the head of baptized and occult heretics,
because of the baptismal character that remains in them? The query is concerned
with formal heretics.
Reply. The answer is in the negative, against Cajetan's view, because in
their case not even infused faith remains, which means that they do not belong
to the third class. St. Thomas has in mind in the body of the article, those who
are united with Christ neither by glory nor by charity in this life, but by
faith. The Church is defined as "the congregation of the faithful,"
inasmuch as faith is the foundation and beginning of the supernatural life.
Christ, to be sure, influences these heretics by actual graces, but these
graces only dispose them for the life of grace, and are not anything permanent
in them, which means that they do not constitute a permanent bond uniting the
member with Christ. Thus nobody is said to be a member of a family, merely
because he visits it occasionally. Christ also bestows actual graces on
infidels, of whom certainly He is actually the head.
Cajetan's objection. Christ bestows on baptized infidels something spiritual
and permanent, namely, a baptismal character.
Reply. It is not enough for Christ to bestow on them something spiritual and
permanent, for this something spiritual and permanent must be both vital and
uniting the baptized with the one who is believed or loved. Otherwise Christ
would be the head of the baptized who are damned. Cajetan concedes this last
conclusion, but St. Thomas clearly denies it at the end of the argumentative
part of this article.
It would be an error in the other extreme opposed to that of John Hus and
Quesnel.
Hence the baptized formal heretic is not an actual member of the Church, and
yet the Church has the right of punishing him, inasmuch as he does not maintain
what he promised to believe, just as a king has the right to punish fugitive
soldiers.
St. Robert Bellarmine's objection. The pope who becomes a secret heretic is
still an actual member of the Church, for he is still the head of the Church, as
Cajetan, Cano, Suarez, and others teach.
Reply. This condition is quite abnormal, hence no wonder that something
abnormal results from it, namely, that the pope becoming secretly a heretic
would no longer be an actual member of the Church, according to the teaching as
explained in the body of the article, but would still retain his jurisdiction by
which he would influence the Church in ruling it. Thus he would still be
nominally the head of the Church, which he would still rule as head, though he
would no longer be a member of Christ, because he would not receive that vital
influx of faith from Christ, the invisible and primary head. Thus in quite an
abnormal manner he would be in point of jurisdiction the head of the Church,
though he would not be a member of it.
This condition could not apply to the natural head in its relation to the
body, but such a condition is not repugnant in the case of the moral and
secondary head. The reason is that, whereas the natural head must receive a
vital influx from the soul before it can influence the members of its body, the
moral head, such as the pope is, can exercise his jurisdiction over the Church,
although he receives no influx of interior faith and charity from the soul of
the Church. More briefly, as Billuart says, the pope is constituted a member of
the Church by his personal faith, which he can lose, and his headship of the
visible Church by jurisdiction and power is compatible with private heresy. The
Church will always consist in the visible union of its members with its visible
head, namely, the pope of Rome, although some, who externally seem to be members
of the Church, may be private heretics. Thus the conclusion we must come to is,
that occult heretics are only apparent members of the Church, which they
externally and visibly profess to be the true Church.
Second doubt. Was Christ the head of our first parents in the state of
innocence?
This is a difficult question, and the answer depends on the way we solve the
problem concerning the motive of the Incarnation.
The Scotists and Suarez answer this question in the affirmative, for they
maintain that Christ as man was the head of Adam in the state of innocence, even
as regards essential grace, because Christ is the first of all the predestined.
Many Thomists deny this assertion of the Scotists and Suarez, for they say
that the primary and principal reason of Christ's coming was to redeem the human
race, and Adam in the state of innocence did not need redemption. Nevertheless,
among Thomists, Godoy and Gonet maintain that Christ as man was truly and in the
strict sense the head of our first parents in the state of innocence about as in
the case of the angels, as regards the accidental grace of faith in Christ to
come not as redeemer, but as consummator of glory.[1033]
Let us now see how the more common opinion of the Thomists is explained by
those who hold, as the Salmanticenses do, that God permitted Adam's sins for a
greater good, namely, the redemptive Incarnation, so that the Incarnation is
prior in the genus of final cause, and the fall of the human race is prior in
the genus of material cause to be perfected or repaired, as we explained above
in discussing the motive of the Incarnation.
Thesis. Christ as man was not the head of our first parents in the state of
innocence as regards essential grace.
Authoritative proof. St. Augustine says: "He[Adam] was not in need of
those graces resulting from Christ's death; the blood of the lamb absolved
fallen men from both hereditary sin and personal sins."[1034] He calls the
grace of the state of innocence, God's grace, and the grace bestowed on man
after the Fall, Christ's grace.[1035]
St. Thomas likewise says: "Granted as true the opinion that Christ would
not have become incarnate if man had not sinned, Christ before sin would have
been the head of the Church only as God, but after sin He must be the head of
the Church as man."[1036]
Fundamental theological proof. The more common opinion of the Thomists is
proved by the following syllogistic reasoning.
Christ was willed by God first and principally as the Redeemer, and so the
grace bestowed by Christ is a medicinal and healing grace. But Adam had no grace
in the state of innocence that was a medicinal and healing grace. Therefore Adam
had no grace in the state of innocence that was bestowed on Him by Christ.
In other words, according to the present decree, Christ was willed as a
remedy for the human race because of original sin. Thus the redemptive
Incarnation depends on Adam's sin not indeed in the genus of final cause or of
efficient cause or of formal cause, but in the genus of material cause that must
be perfected or repaired, inasmuch as the alleviation of misery is the reason
for being merciful. Hence every grace coming from Christ as head comes from Him
by reason of His redemption and death for the human race.
Solution Of Objections
First objection. The principal reason for the opposite Scotist opinion is
this. Christ is the first of all the predestined, as St. Thomas himself
says.[1037] But the first of all the predestined is the cause of all the graces
the other predestined receive, among whom are the first parents. Therefore
Christ was the cause of all the graces received by the first parents, even their
essential grace, and so He was their head.
Reply. I distinguish the major: that Christ is the first of all the
predestined by a priority of dignity as regards all, even the angels, this I
concede, because He is predestined to divine and natural sonship, and not to
adoptive sonship; that He is the first of all predestined by a priority of
meritorious causality of all, this I deny; for He is only thus first of all as
regards the redeemed, since He came as redeemer for us men. I contradistinguish
the minor; the first of all the predestined is the meritorious cause of all the
graces of the predestined to be redeemed, as redeemed, this I concede; that He
is the meritorious cause of the essential grace of the others, that is, of the
angels and Adam, not as to be redeemed, but as innocent, this I deny. And I deny
the consequent and consequence, for the notion of head requires causality by way
of merit. Thus farther on we shall state that Christ as man is truly the head of
the angels inasmuch as, if He did not merit for them the essential grace of
justification and glory, at least He merited accidental graces for them to be
ministers in the kingdom of God. Adam in the state of innocence, however, was
not Christ's minister in the kingdom of God.
Third doubt. Was Christ, as man, the end of the essential grace bestowed on
our first parents in the state of innocence? It is not here strictly a question
of Christ's merits, but of Christ as He is the end of creatures.
The Thomists, as also the Salmanticenses, generally agree in saying that
Christ was the end of this essential grace, not in its production but in its
reparation. For Christ was first intended as the Redeemer of the human race, and
therefore this presupposes the destruction of original justice through Adam's
sin.
According to the interpretation of the Salmanticenses and Gonet concerning
the teaching of St. Thomas on the motive of the Incarnation, which we admitted,
the end to which Christ was appointed is the permission of original sin by which
original justice is destroyed, and not the production of this original justice.
Hence Christ is not appointed for the production of this original justice, but
for its reparation. So say the Salmanticenses[1038] and Billuart.[1039]
As regards the essential grace and glory of the good angels, we shall discuss
this farther on. Although this grace is not the result of Christ's merits, yet
it is ordained to Christ as to its end. For this grace was neither destroyed nor
to be repaired, and the decree of the Incarnation did not therefore presuppose
its destruction by some sin permitted by God.
All these statements are consistent with what we previously said about the
motive of the Incarnation,[1040] namely, that God among innumerable possible
worlds saw by His knowledge of simple intelligence the world free from sin,
perfect and glorious not redeemed by the Incarnation, and the world of sin made
perfect and glorious by the redemptive Incarnation, and by one simple and
efficacious decree for the manifestation of His glory chose this second world,
that is, He permitted both Adam's sin destroying original justice and willed the
redemptive Incarnation, as a greater good without which He would not have
permitted the aforesaid sin. Hence the permission of original sin and the
restoration of original justice are ordained to Christ, as to their end; in
fact, as will be stated farther on, the angels themselves and their essential
grace and glory not destined to be destroyed are likewise ordained to Christ, as
to their end, because there is only one decree for all parts of the universe, so
that they may pass from the state of possibility to that of futurity.[1041]
Second objection. Adam's essential grace in the state of innocence is the
effect of his predestination. But Adam's predestination, like ours, is the
effect of Christ's merits. Therefore Adam's essential grace in the state of
innocence is the effect of Christ's merits, who was therefore in the strict
sense his head.
Reply. I distinguish the antecedent: that the grace as first given in the
state of innocence was the effect of Adam's predestination, I deny; that it was
so as destined to be repaired, I concede. For this grace as first given was not
ordained efficaciously to glory, but only as it was repaired after its loss.
Hence in the state of innocence, this grace did not depend either on Adam's
predestination or on Christ's predestination, but on God's general providence in
the supernatural order, just like the sufficient graces that were given, for
example, to the angels who were not predestined.
I insist. But God's general providence is subordinated to the providence of
the hypostatic union as end. Hence there is no solution of the difficulty.
Reply. The Salmanticenses[1042] answer by making the following distinction:
that this subordination to the hypostatic union prevails as regards the
reparation of this original justice, I concede; as regards the state itself of
original justice, I deny. "Although," as they say, "the
providence of the hypostatic union, to which Christ's predestination belongs,
which is the cause of ours, on behalf of the dignity of its object, namely, of
Christ, was sufficient to subordinate to Himself and to that providence the
state of original justice, and God could fittingly enough so decree; yet, on the
present supposition that de facto God intended Christ as a remedy for original
sin, He could by His consequent power extend His decree to the above-mentioned
subordination. The reason is that He could not look upon that first state of
innocence except through the medium of original sin, which is the formal
destruction and non-existence of this state; and therefore He could exert no
influence on this being, as stated above. Consequently the influx of providence
in the hypostatic union de facto consists precisely in those things that concern
or connote original sin; it does not extend to other things, although in another
series of things, considering the sufficiency of this providence, it could be
extended to include them."[1043]
Yet it remains true, as the Salmanticenses furthermore say, that "all
things which God decreed in reparation after the Fall, were directed to Christ
as to their end."[1044] Thus original justice was only mediately and
indirectly the material cause of the Incarnation, since this latter was decreed
in reparation after sin.
Still I insist. But in the other predestined, such as in St. Peter, even the
first of the series of graces interrupted by sin, is the effect of the person's
predestination, according to the Thomist doctrine.[1045] Therefore the same must
be said of Adam's first grace, though the series of graces was interrupted by
sin.
Reply. There is not parity of argument in each case, for in the person
predestined and redeemed, as in St. Peter, the first grace bestowed is given
with the intention of leading him to glory by the recovery of this grace. On the
contrary, grace was not bestowed on Adam in the state of innocence with the
efficacious intention of leading him to glory in that state, but it came from
God's general providence. That state of innocence had to be admitted and the
decree of Christ's coming and His predestination depended on its loss, and
through Christ's merits we are all redeemed. Hence Adam's first grace was the
effect of his predestination, only as recovered, not as first bestowed.
Another difficulty. Is Christ as man Adam's head in the state of innocence as
regards accidental graces, just as, as we shall immediately say, He is of the
angels? Essential grace is habitual grace or sanctifying grace, and accidental
grace is illuminating grace of the intellect, which is not absolutely necessary
for justification.
It is a disputed question among Thomists. Some deny that Christ is Adam's
head, because, so they say, the angels are Christ's ministers in the kingdom of
God, but Adam in the state of innocence was not Christ's minister. So says
Billuart.
Nevertheless Gonet's teaching is probable. He writes: "Christ as man was
head of our first parents even in the state of innocence, for a moral influence
came from Christ on our first parents still in the state of innocence, just as
it was given to the angels, namely, some accidental grace, such as faith in
Christ to come, not indeed as the redeemer, but as the consummator of
glory."[1046]
Other Thomists, such as Billuart, reply with the following distinction: that
Adam in the state of innocence believed in Christ, that is, in Christ
objectively considered, I concede; that he had this belief through Christ, I
deny. But if it is insisted that Adam believed in Christ as the consummator of
glory, and therefore as the head, they reply: as the future head as being the
consummator of glory, let this pass without comment; as the head actually
exerting His influx in the state of innocence, this I deny.
At least it must be granted that Adam's belief in Christ to come as the
consummator of glory was directed to Christ as to the end; and Adam continued in
this belief, since it was not lost as the grace of original justice was, because
Adam, strictly speaking, did not sin against faith, and so he did not lose it.
Final doubt. If we admit the teaching of St. Thomas on the motive of the
Incarnation, is it probable that Adam's essential grace in the state of
innocence rests on a twofold title: namely, (1) on God elevating him to this
grace, independently of Christ; (2) dependent on Christ's merits.
Reply. Certain Thomists, such as Godoy, O. P., and Cipullus, O. P., maintain
this for the angels and also, so it seems, for Adam in the state of innocence.
Their reason is that this contributes to Christ's glory, just as the
glorification of His physical body rests on a twofold title: namely, (1) as
being connatural, since it is the overflow of glory from the soul, and (2) on
the title of merit. Likewise, so they say, the essential grace of the angels and
Adam rested on a twofold title.
This opinion of Godoy and Cipullus is attacked by Billuart and by Gonet, and
to these last-mentioned theologians Contenson replies by saying: "According
to this opinion, God the Father by the first expression of His will freely gave
His grace, and afterward also willed to confer it because of Christ's merits; so
that, if at first He had not decided to give it, by virtue of this second will
it would be bestowed efficaciously. Certainly this way of presenting the case
claims for itself probability, since it by all means safeguards Christ's
dignity."[1047]
Contenson says that this conclusion is only probable, because we do not know
what is positively contained in God's free decree on this point. It has not been
sufficiently revealed.
However, even though this opinion were probable concerning the essential
grace of the angels, it is not so probable as regards the essential grace of
Adam in the state of innocence, because Christ came as the Redeemer on the
supposition that Adam's sin was permitted, by which the grace in the state of
innocence was lost, whereas the first grace of the predestined angels was not
lost.
Fourth Article: Whether Christ Is The Head Of The Angels
State of the question. It concerns Christ as man, for there is not indeed any
doubt that Christ, as God, is the head of the angels even as regards essential
grace and glory, which is a participation of the divine nature.
There are three difficulties presented at the beginning of this article. (1)
It seems that Christ is not the head of the angels, because the head and members
are of the same nature; but Christ, as man, is not of the same nature with the
angels. (2) The angels do not belong to the Church, which is the congregation of
the faithful who are wayfarers exiled from the Lord. (3) Christ as man gives
life to the souls of men, but in this respect He does not give life to the
angels.
Reply. Christ is the head of the angels.
Scriptural proof. St. Paul says: "In Him[Christ] dwelleth all the
fullness of the Godhead Corporeally, and you are filled in Him, who is the head
of all principality and power."[1048] There is a similar text from St. Paul
quoted in the body of this article.[1049] In fact, the words of Jesus, as quoted
by the Evangelist, are evidence of this truth, for He says: "The Son of man
shall send His angels."[1050] And again: "He shall send His angels,
and shall gather together His elect."[1051] "He shall send His angels
with a trumpet, and a great voice."[1052] "All power is given to Me in
heaven and in earth."[1053] Likewise St. Paul declares that Christ has
inherited "a more excellent name than the angels,"[1054] and this for
three reasons, because He is the only Son of God, because He is the Lord of
God's kingdom, whereas the angels are His ministers, and because He is full of
grace, this fullness being absolute and superabundant.
Theological proof. It is proved by two syllogistic reasonings, as follows:
There must be one head to one body. But there is one mystical body of the
Church, which consists of men and angels, who are ordained to the same glory.
Therefore this particular body, which is one because of the unity of its end,
has one head.
But this one and only head is Christ, because He is nearer to God. Therefore
not only men, but angels share in Christ's influence.
The first syllogism has its foundation in the one end of the entire mystical
body, inasmuch as men and angels are ordained to the same ultimate supernatural
end. The source of their spiritual life is derived from the same divine truth
and from the same supreme divine good.
The second syllogism has its foundation in this principle: that Christ is
nearer God by the hypostatic union and more perfectly shares in God's gifts,
according to the absolute fullness of grace.[1055]
Thus the conclusion is that Christ is truly and in the strict sense the head
of the angels, as attested by St. Paul.[1056]
The solution of the difficulties confirms this conclusion.
Reply to first objection. Christ as man is not in agreement with the angels
in their specific nature, but in their generic nature, or in the generic grade
of intellectuality. And though this does not suffice for natural headship, at
least it does so for moral headship, otherwise God Himself would not be the head
of the angels. Moreover, Christ has the same specific nature as the angels in
the supernatural order, namely, the same and only species of habitual grace,
which is the participation of the divine nature.
Reply to second objection. "The church in heaven is the congregation of
comprehensors." But Christ already in this life was both wayfarer and
comprehensor, having grace and glory to the fullest extent.
Reply to third objection. "Christ's humanity, by virtue of the divine
nature, can cause something in the spirits of angels on account of its close
conjunction with God, that is, by personal union."
Several doubts must be examined.
First doubt. Is Christ, as man, truly and strictly speaking, the head of the
angels as regards their external government?
Theologians generally agree that Christ is the head in this sense, and to
deny it would be an error on account of the very clear texts of Sacred
Scripture, as quoted above. Also, just as the pope is called the head of the
Church as regards its eternal government, so Christ as man, by reason of the
hypostatic union, is the prince and lord of the entire Church triumphant, which
consists of men and angels. Manifestly this is so from the very fact that Jesus
said: "The Son of man... shall send His angels,"[1057] and "All
power is given to Me in heaven and in earth."[1058]
Hence St. Thomas shows that Christ ascended above every spiritual
creature,[1059] and that Christ's judiciary power, as man, extends to the
angels, who are His ministers concerning men.
Second doubt. What grace does Christ as man bestow on the angels?
Reply. There is no doubt that He bestows on them accidental grace, which
consists in the illumination of their intellect concerning those things that
pertain to our redemption, especially the mystery of the redemptive Incarnation,
that they may cooperate with Christ as His ministers in the business of man's
salvation. Thus the archangel Gabriel was sent to the Blessed Virgin Mary, St.
Joseph was enlightened by the angel concerning those things that pertain to
Christ and His defense, and Christ sends His angels to be guardians of men.
Thus Christ, as man, bestows on the angels by a physically instrumental
influx, accidental graces that they minister to us, and so He purges them from
error in this ministry, illumines and perfects them. Similarly Christ as man
bestows accidental reward or accidental glory on the angels, on account of this
ministry, and accidental joy in the objective and indirect reparation made for
those seats lost by the fallen angels, through the justification and
glorification of the saints. Thus the angels rejoice in the fact that, because
of Christ's merits, the Blessed Virgin Mary has been exalted above their choirs
and that the soul of St. Joseph is among them.
But Christ formerly merited the accidental graces, which by His physical
instrumentality He bestows on the angels; for He merited whatever He afterward
confers. This is clearly enough expressed by St. Paul in the following text:
"Are they not all ministering spirits, sent to minister for them, who shall
receive the inheritance of salvation?"[1060]
Now indeed, since Christ as man rules over the angels, and merited the
accidental grace and glory He now bestows on them, He is truly and properly
called their head, more than the pope is as regards the faithful; for the pope
only governs the faithful and does not either merit or bestow such accidental
grace and glory on them. In fact, Christ is more the head of the angels than of
infidels, who are not actually subjected to Him as their head; for He does not
impart actual graces to infidels as to actual living members of the Church, but
only to dispose them to receive the life of faith.
It is not necessary for the moral head of the angels to bestow on them
essential grace, for it is not the primary function of the natural head to give
essential life to the members of the body, for this comes from the soul as the
substantial form of the body; but it imparts only some vital motion as its
secondary act. A fortiori, it suffices that the moral head exert its influence
by ruling, as the pope does in the Church and the king in his kingdom.
Third doubt. Does Christ as man bestow on the angels also essential grace and
glory, these being a participation of the divine nature? It is certain that as
God He bestows this grace on them; but the question is whether He bestows this
grace in His human nature, inasmuch as it is personally united with the Word and
because of the fullness of grace possessed by Christ in His human nature.
It is a disputed question among theologians. Some absolutely affirm that He
does, such as Scotus, the Scotists, Suarez, Valentia, and Godoy, among the
Thomists. They give as their principal reason that Christ is the first of all
the predestined, and therefore He is the cause of all graces for others.
On the contrary, some absolutely deny that Christ as man gives this grace to
the angels. Many of these are Thomists, such as Medina, Alvarez, John of St.
Thomas, Gonet, Billuart, and others; outside the school of St. Thomas, we have
Vasquez and de Lugo.
The principal reason advanced by these Thomists is that Christ came as the
Redeemer, to redeem us men, and He did not die for the angels who were not in
need of redemption.
But others try to reconcile the two above-mentioned opinions. Among the
Thomists are Vincent of Asturia and Cipullus, who maintain that the essential
grace of the angels rests on a twofold title: (1) on God's liberality, and (2)
on Christ's merits, just as there were two reasons for the glorification of
Christ's body, namely, the connatural overflow of this glory from His soul, and
the merit He acquired.
Finally, the Salmanticenses seem to solve the question better by saying:
"Christ bestowed this essential grace on the angels, not indeed as
physically efficient cause or as morally meritorious cause or as redemptive
cause, but by way of objective end,"[1061] inasmuch as Christ was first
intended by God above the angels.
Let us first consider the more common opinion among the Thomists, namely,
that Christ as man does not bestow essential grace and glory on the
angels.[1062]
Scriptural proof. In the Gospel we read: "The angel said to them[the
shepherds], "I bring you good tidings of great joy... for this day is born
to you a Savior."[1063] The angel says: "to you," not "to
us." Similarly St. Bernard in one of his homilies, quoting the scriptural
text, "A child is born to us, and a Son is given to us,"[1064] says:
"He was not given also to the angels, who having the great, did not need
the very little. Therefore He was born for us, given to us, because He is
necessary to us."[1065]
But if St. Gregory the Great says, "No man or angel is holy except
through Christ,"[1066] this can be understood of Christ as God.
Moreover, the Church says of the Son of God: "Who for us men and for our
salvation came down from heaven and became incarnate,"[1067] not for the
angels.
Proof from various texts of St. Thomas. Thus he says: "The angels are
not wayfarers as regards their essential reward and therefore in this sense
Christ did not merit anything for them. But they are in some manner wayfarers as
regards their accidental reward; inasmuch as they minister to us, and this is
what Christ merited for them."[1068]
Again he says: "He[Christ] does not exert His influence on the angels by
removing the obstacle either by meriting grace for them or praying for them,
because they are already in a state of bliss; but He exerts His influence in
those things that pertain to hierarchic acts, inasmuch as one angel illumines,
purges, and purifies another."[1069]
St. Thomas likewise says, concerning the extent of Christ's judiciary power
as regards the angels: "They are submitted to Christ's judgment: (1) as
regards the dispensation of those things which are done through them... whereas
they minister to Christ as man; (2) as to other accidental rewards...; (3) as to
the essential reward of the good angels, which is everlasting bliss; and as to
the essential punishment of the wicked angels, which is everlasting damnation.
But this was done by Christ from the beginning of the world inasmuch as He is
the Word of God."[1070]
The principal theological proof for this more common opinion among the
Thomists is about the same as for Adam's essential grace in the state of
innocence and may be expressed by the following syllogistic reasoning.
Christ was willed by God primarily and principally as the Redeemer; and the
grace that comes from Him is medicinal or healing, derived from His death. But
the essential grace of the angels is not at all medicinal or healing, nor did
Christ die for them.
Therefore the essential grace of the angels is not the result of Christ's
merits.
Confirmation. In fact, God's efficacious decree of the Incarnation in
passible flesh presupposes, even for the Scotists, that He permitted and foresaw
Adam's sin; and this permission presupposes that He permitted the devil's sin,
inasmuch as de facto Adam's sin came about from the temptation by the devil, who
was the first to fall. Therefore the Word incarnate, as incarnate, was not the
cause of essential grace in the angels, which had been lost through the devil's
sin.
Solution of objections. The principal reason advanced by the Scotists in
opposition to the Thomist opinion is as follows:
Christ as man is the first of all the predestined. But the first of all the
predestined is the cause of all graces for the others, among whom are the good
angels. Therefore Christ as man was the cause of the essential grace and glory
of the angels.
Reply. As in the case of essential grace for Adam in the state of innocence,
the answer is made by distinguishing the major: that Christ is the first of all
the predestined by a priority of dignity, this I concede, because He was
predestined to natural divine sonship which far transcends adoptive sonship of
the angels;[1071] that He is the first of all the predestined by a priority of
meritorious causality, this I deny, because He is such only as regards those to
be redeemed, since He came as Redeemer for us men and not for the angels. I
contradistinguish the minor: the first of all the predestined is the meritorious
cause of all the graces of the predestined to be redeemed, this I concede; of
the others, namely, of the angels, this I deny. And I deny the consequent and
consequence.
But I insist. The Scotists in confirmation of their thesis add: For Christ to
be truly and in the strict sense the head of the angels, it is not enough for
Him to bestow upon them accidental grace and glory. For Christ is the head only
of those on whom He bestows those gifts by which they are constituted members
either of the Church militant, suffering, or triumphant, and which are grace,
charity, faith, and in heaven the light of glory and the beatific vision.
Reply. The Thomists distinguish the antecedent. That the bestowal of
accidental grace and glory is not enough for Christ to be considered in the
absolutely strict sense the head of the angels just as He is the head of the
just, this I concede; that such is not enough for Him to be truly their head,
this I deny. Indeed, it is not the primary function even of the natural head and
a fortiori of the moral head to bestow essential life on the members. It is not
the primary function of the head to make the members living members, for this
pertains to the soul as the substantial form of the whole body; but the head
imparts to the members a vital motion, which is life in its secondary act. A
fortiori the moral head, such as the pope in the Church or the king in his
kingdom, each exerts influence on the members by external government, and yet
each is truly called the head. But Christ as man, not only governs the angels by
sending them on this or that ministry, but He also bestows on them accidental
graces or illuminations for the correct and devout fulfillment of their
ministry; and because of their having fulfilled their ministry in this way, He
bestows on them an accidental reward. Thus Christ as man is truly and in the
strict sense the head of the angels, although in a way not so perfect as He is
the head of the just, though He is more the head of the angels than the pope is
the head of the faithful.
Finally, the Scotists quote in their favor the following scriptural texts:
"No man cometh to the Father, but by Me"'[1072] and "For if by
the offense of one, many died, much more... the grace of one man, Jesus Christ,
hath abounded unto many."[1073]
The Thomists point out that the scriptural texts and statements of the
Fathers to which the Scotists refer on this subject, either do not certainly
concern the angels but only the just, or if the angels are included, it is not
evident from these texts that Christ as man bestows on them essential grace.
Thus, when St. John quotes our Lord as saying: "No man cometh to the Father
but by Me,"[1074] the meaning is: No one, either angel or man, comes to the
Father, except through the Son, but in a different way; for man comes to the
Father through the Son veiled in the flesh, but the angel through the Son
inasmuch as He is God.
Fourth doubt. If the doctrine of St. Thomas on the motive of the Incarnation
be admitted, is it probable that there are two reasons why the angels have their
essential grace and glory, namely: (1) because of God's liberality independently
of Christ; (2) dependent on Christ's merits?
Reply. Among Thomists, Godoy O. P. and Cipullus O. P., are of this opinion.
Although Gonet and Billuart are against them, yet their opinion, as Contenson
shows,[1075] does not lack probability. Their principal reason for this opinion
is that it contributes to Christ's glory for Him to be the source of all graces;
and in truth, Christ Himself obtained the glorification of His body by a twofold
right: (1) in that it was connatural to Him, as being the overflow of glory from
the soul; (2) by having merited this right.
As Contenson remarks,[1076] this opinion is probable. But if against this
opinion the objection is raised that Christ, however, did not die for the
angels, and therefore He did not merit for them, then the answer is that neither
did Christ die for Himself, and yet He merited for Himself the glorification of
His body, and this by a twofold right.
But this opinion cannot be demonstrated because, if it is an established
fact, then this opinion depends on God's most free decree that has not been
sufficiently revealed; nor can it be deduced with theological certainty from
revealed principles. Hence St. Thomas observes a prudent silence concerning
these things known to God alone. As the Apostle says, it behooves us "to be
wise unto sobriety."[1077]
Fifth doubt. Is Christ as man the final cause of essential grace and glory in
the angels?
Reply. That Christ is the final cause, we affirm along with the
Salmanticenses, who say: "We add that Christ bestowed substantial grace and
first justification on the angels, not indeed that He was either the efficient
physical cause or the moral, meritorious, or redemptive cause, but He was the
cause by way of objective end."[1078] This can most probably be declared in
two ways.[1079]
The first reason, indeed, is that Christ was intended by God as the end of
all things, to whom God ordained all things He decreed to make, as we explicitly
showed.[1080] Now it suffices to say of this particular disposition on God's
part that on the one hand there is nothing derogatory to God, and on the other
that it is most befitting the excellence of Christ, our Lord, who, as He was the
first of the predestined and the exemplary cause of all the predestined, thus it
was becoming for Him to be the quasi-intermediate end for whose sake all things
were created, and to whom God referred and subjected all things, so that they
should serve Him and increase His glory.[1081] Hence, whatever grace and
perfection they had and the angels have, they all participate in Christ's
bestowal of this in the genus of final cause.
The second reason, however, is that the angels in the state of probation, and
also our first parents in the state of innocence, believed in Christ as the
consummator of glory. Thus Christ bestowed faith on the angels, and on our first
parents in the state of innocence objectively.
Hence Christ is the end of essential grace in the angels, but He does not
appear to be the meritorious cause of this grace, unless their grace rests on a
twofold title, which is conjectural but cannot be proved; because, if it is so,
this depends on God's decree that is not sufficiently made manifest.
Conclusion. Therefore Christ is truly and in the strict sense the head of the
angels, although not so completely as He is of the just, whom He redeemed and on
whom He certainly bestows not only accidental grace, but also essential grace
and glory.[1082] The unanimous teaching of theologians is that Christ did not
redeem the angels, and it is the more common opinion among Thomists that He
probably did not merit for them essential grace.
Fifth Article: Whether The Grace Of Christ As Head Of Church Is The Same As
His Habitual Grace, Inasmuch As He Is Man
State of the question. Is Christ's grace as head of the Church really
distinct from His personal habitual grace, or are the two graces identical?
It seems that they are not the same, for the following reasons.
1) The actual or personal sin of Adam differs from original sin which He
transmitted to posterity. Therefore the personal grace of Christ the new Adam is
not the same as His grace of headship.
2) These graces are distinct inasmuch as they are ordained to different acts,
for Christ's personal grace is ordained for His sanctification, whereas His
capital grace is for the sanctification of others.
3) Theologians usually distinguish between three kinds of graces in Christ:
the grace of union, the individual grace of the man, and the capital grace.
Conclusion. Christ's personal habitual grace and His capital grace are
essentially the same, though there is a mental distinction between them.
Very many theologians accept this conclusion, though Vasquez and certain
others teach that Christ's capital grace and His grace of union are really the
same.
Scriptural proof. The Evangelist says: "of His fullness we all have
received."[1083] Hence Christ is our head inasmuch as He had the fullness
of personal habitual grace. Hence there is no real distinction between Christ's
habitual grace and His capital grace; at least, the text quoted above implies
that these two graces are really identical.
Theological proof. There is no difference between the act whereby anything is
in act and whereby it acts, and the agent must be nobler than the patient. But
Christ as man is constituted supernaturally in act by the personal habitual
grace which He received in the highest degree. Therefore Christ as man bestowed
this same grace on others, namely, on those members whose head He is.
The major is evident, for it is founded on the principle that everything acts
inasmuch as it is a being in act. Thus what is hot heats according to the heat
whereby it is hot. For the agent acts, inasmuch as it determines, and the manner
of its determination is in accordance with its own determination.
The minor was explained above: for personal habitual grace intrinsically and
physically informs Christ, as man. Thus this grace is the operative principle
whereby He radically operates supernaturally, performing acts that are
infinitely meritorious and satisfactory. The principium quo of these operations
is habitual grace as it connotes the grace of union, or as it connotes the
principium quod, or the person of the Word, from whom these works derive their
infinite value.[1084]
Therefore this same habitual grace is called capital, inasmuch as by it
Christ can bestow on the members of the Church grace and justification, that is,
by exerting a moral influence on them by means of His infinitely meritorious and
satisfactory works. It is precisely this influence that constitutes Him their
head, although He also exerts a physically instrumental influence on them.
Christ, the head of the faithful of the Old Testament, could not exert a
physically instrumental influence on them, but only a moral influence by His
merit and satisfaction, since they lived before His coming.
St. Thomas often speaks of this physically instrumental causality of Christ's
human nature, inasmuch as it is the instrument united with the divine nature,
whereas the sacraments are separate instruments.[1085] As one who blows a
trumpet emits the sound by this instrument, so God can cause grace by Christ's
human nature; so also our soul makes use of vocal chords as the instrument of
speech. Moreover, it must be observed that, although Christ's body, inasmuch as
it is in heaven as in a place, is locally distant from ours, the higher part of
Christ's soul and of our soul are not of themselves localized, nor is Christ's
mind locally distant from our mind, which is influenced by His mind, inasmuch as
it is the instrument of His divine nature.[1086]
As regards moral causality by way of merit, it is not necessary that the
moral cause already exist for it to exert its influence, since the moral cause
operates inasmuch as it is known, and can be known as coming into existence.
Thus God conferred grace on the faithful of the Old Testament because of
Christ's future merits.
The solution of the objections confirms the conclusion.
Reply to first objection. We must distinguish in Adam between his personal
sin and original sin that had its origin in him, which is a sin of the nature,
"because in him the person, by turning away from God, corrupted the nature;
and by means of this corruption the sin of the first man is transmitted to
posterity.... Now grace is not vouchsafed us by means of human nature, but
solely by the personal action of Christ Himself. Hence we must not distinguish a
twofold grace in Christ, one corresponding to the nature, the other to the
person." This means, as Cajetan observes, that "grace is not
communicated to us by the action of the nature, or by communicating the nature
as Adam would have communicated it, not corrupted, to his children, if he had
not sinned, but by Christ's personal action, by which He merited for us and of
His own will bestowed grace on us."[1087]
Reply to second objection. The eminence of Christ's personal habitual grace
is the reason for the justification of others.
Reply to third objection. "The personal and the capital grace agree in
the essence of the habit"; they are the same habit inasmuch as their more
proximate purpose is for the performance of some meritorious act. On the
contrary, the direct purpose of the grace of union is not for the eliciting of a
meritorious act, and it is not a habit but, as stated above, "the grace of
union is the personal being that is given gratis by God to the human nature in
the person of the Word."[1088]
Objection. But for Vasquez the capital grace and the grace of union are
identical because, so he says, the infinite value of Christ's merits is derived
from this grace of union.
Reply. That the value of Christ's merits is derived remotely from the grace
of union as from the principium quod[1089] that is connotated, this I concede;
that it is derived proximately as from the operative principium quo, this I
deny, although charity is the immediate principle of merit. It pertains to the
notion of capital grace, however, for it to be the root, instrumentally, of
those merits because the head of the Church as such exerts at least a moral
influence on the members by His meritorious works.
But I insist. If Christ did not have habitual grace, He would, nevertheless,
still be our head; for habitual grace is not absolutely necessary so as to
enable Him to elicit meritorious acts. Therefore Christ is not the head because
of habitual grace.
Reply. I distinguish the antecedent: If Christ did not have habitual grace,
He would still be our head because of His divine personality, this I deny, for
His personality does not constitute Him the operative principle of merit;
because of the transient help given by it, this I concede. But then Christ would
not be the connatural operative principle of merit.
Again I insist. Grace that is ordained for the sanctification of others is
not grace gratum faciens, but grace gratis data. Therefore Christ's capital
grace that is ordained for our sanctification is not identical with His personal
habitual grace.
Reply. I distinguish the antecedent: Grace that is primarily ordained for the
sanctification of others is not gratia gratum faciens, this I concede; grace
that is only secondarily so ordained is not such, this I deny. Thus the gift of
wisdom is included in sanctifying grace, although its secondary purpose is for
the direction of souls, which means that it is for the benefit of others. Such
was Christ's habitual grace.
Sixth Article: Whether It Is Proper To Christ To Be The Head Of The Church
In this article, as in the remaining ones of this question, St. Thomas shows
that it is proper for Christ to be the head of the Church by a certain intrinsic
influence of grace and justification, because He has this power from habitual
grace, inasmuch as it presupposes the grace of union, to which is attributed the
infinite value of His merits.[1090] But to be the head of the Church in its
external government for a time befits the pope as regards the Church militant
during the time of his pontificate. In this way, he is the vicar of Christ.
Seventh Article: Whether The Devil Is The Head Of All The Wicked
Lucifer, the prince of devils, is the head of all the wicked not by
interiorly influencing their wills, for God alone can interiorly move the will;
but he is their head by inducing them to commit sin by means of suggestions and
temptations, it being easier to destroy than to build.
Eighth Article: Whether Antichrist May Be Called The Head Of All The Wicked
Antichrist is neither the head of all the wicked as regards those that lived
before his time, since he will come only about the end of the world, nor as
regards his power of influencing them, since he cannot have any influence on
those sinners who lived before his coming; but he is their head only by reason
of the perfection of his wickedness, so that all the wicked who preceded him
are, so to speak, signs of Antichrist.[1091]
CHAPTER XI: QUESTION 9: CHRIST'S KNOWLEDGE IN GENERAL AND
HIS POWER OF CONTEMPLATION
After the consideration of Christ's grace, both personal and capital, we must
discuss the question of His knowledge: (1) What knowledge indeed or what kinds
of knowledge did He have? (2) Then we shall inquire into each particular kind of
knowledge, namely, His beatific knowledge (q. 10), His imprinted or infused
knowledge (q. 11), His acquired knowledge (q. 13), that is, Christ's
intellectual life, even His most sublime contemplation.
It is therefore evident that, as St. Thomas says, "We are here taking
knowledge for any cognition of the human intellect,"[1092] even that which
is not discursive. The most important article of this ninth question is the
second, which inquires whether Christ had already in this life the knowledge
that the blessed or comprehensors have, namely, the beatific vision. The first
article, however, may be considered an introduction to the inquiries about
Christ's created knowledge.
Notice must be taken of the fact that Sacred Scripture, which is a
manifestation of divine truth for the purpose of salvation, insists more on the
moral and religious than on the intellectual aspects of our Lord's life as
Savior. But the idea of Christ as man is not of one who had the most sublime
conception of moral and religious perfection to the exclusion of a proportionate
knowledge of God, the soul, the world, the kingdom of God. It is in this way
that the theologian is induced to treat of Christ's knowledge, and he inquires
what can be known of Him from Sacred Scripture, tradition, and theological
reasoning.[1093]
First Article: Whether Christ Had Any Knowledge Besides The Divine
State of the question. The meaning of the title is whether Christ had any
other knowledge besides the uncreated knowledge. Why is it that any other
knowledge is not superfluous since the uncreated knowledge already includes all
other kinds of knowledge?
Reply. The answer is in the affirmative, namely, that Christ had created
knowledge as well as uncreated knowledge. The conclusion is de fide.
Scriptural proof. That Christ had created knowledge is, indeed, quite clear,
for He says of Himself: "I know Him[My Father] and do keep his Word,
';[1094] but He kept his Father's word by created actions as man. Therefore He
likewise knew His Father by created knowledge. Moreover, Christ prayed, merited,
obeyed, and performed many other human acts, and it is only by acts of the
created intellect and of the created will that these can be performed. It was
not, indeed, as God that He prayed, merited, and obeyed; for these acts
presuppose the subordination of the created will under the guidance of the
created intellect to the uncreated will.
Hence the Monothelites were condemned by the Third Council of Constantinople
for refusing to admit two wills in Christ, namely, the uncreated will and the
created will. This Council defined that Christ "is perfect both in His
divine nature and in His human nature, truly God and truly man, of rational soul
and body... and has two natural wills not contrary to each other..., and His
human nature is in every respect human, sin absolutely excepted."[1095]
Medina maintains that it is manifestly heretical to deny that Christ's soul
had created knowledge, at least in act.
As John of St. Thomas observes, concerning the last sentence in the body of
this article, it was not indeed defined by the Council that Christ has two kinds
of knowledge, but two wills and operations, and that He had a human nature, and
all that belongs to it, except sin. From these definitions, by closer attention
to the meaning than to the words, it follows that the Council condemned the view
of those who deny two kinds of knowledge in Christ.
Theological proof. It is taken from the argumentative part of this article,
and may be expressed in the following syllogistic form.
The human nature is imperfect without its connatural and proper act of
knowledge. But the Son of God assumed a perfect human nature. Therefore the Son
of God had the connatural and proper created act of intellective knowledge.
Major. Three reasons are given for its proof.
1) That the intellective soul is imperfect unless it be reduced to its act of
understanding, for which it is ordained.
2) That everything is on account of its operation, or as Cajetan explains,
operating on account of itself, not that the knowledge is innate, but inasmuch
as, when the terms of the principles have been proposed, the intellect naturally
adheres to them.
Minor. It is revealed, but it is also clearly stated in the previously quoted
canons of the Third Council of Constantinople.[1096] Hence human intelligence
would be for no purpose in Christ unless He could make use of it, and in this
respect His soul would be more imperfect than the souls of the rest of mankind.
Doubt. Could Christ, as man, understand by communication from the uncreated
act of understanding, as the Master of Good Hope thought?[1097]
Reply. This possibility is generally denied by theologians. For the act of
understanding in the soul is a vital act, since it proceeds from an intrinsic
principle, from the soul and its faculty. But the Deity cannot function as the
soul, or a faculty, or a habit, for example, as the light of glory. In such a
case it would not be the form as terminating but as confirming, and hence would
be less perfect than the whole composite of which it is a part. Therefore
Christ's soul could not understand by communication from the uncreated
intellect.
Second Article: Whether Christ Had Knowledge Which The Blessed Or
Comprehensors Have
State of the question. This article must be fully explained. First of all, it
must be noted that Catholic theologians consider as theologically certain the
doctrine that Christ's soul was free from all ignorance, that even from His
conception He knew all things in the Word, which God knows by the knowledge of
vision. This was formerly denied by several heretics and in our times especially
by liberal Protestants and by Modernists.
Let us first consider these denials and their foundation.
The Nestorians, who said there were two persons in Christ, considered Christ
as man to have been subject to ignorance and error. The Apollinarians and
Anomoeans, who maintained that the Word functions as the mind in the Savior,
denied all human knowledge to Christ. Likewise the Monophysites and Monothelites,
who taught that there is only one operation in Christ, denied Him human
knowledge. Finally, in the sixth century, the Agnoetae, under the leadership of
Themistius, deacon of Alexandria, contended that Christ, as other men, was
subject to the corruption of the flesh and was, as a human being,
ignorant.[1098] They quoted two Gospel texts in their defense: (1) "But of
that day or hour[of the judgment], no man knoweth, neither the angels of heaven,
nor the Son."[1099] (2) But of that day and hour no one knoweth, "not
the angels of heaven, but the Father alone."[1100]
In our times, particularly the liberal Protestants hold that Christ was
ignorant of many things from the beginning, and it was only gradually that He
acquired a knowledge of His mission. The disciples of Gunther[1101] and others,
as more recently Dr. Schell, said that Christ's knowledge was subject to the
laws of human progress, and that in the beginning He did not have the beatific
vision, but acquired it by His merits. Finally, the Modernists[1102] boldly
asserted that Christ neither knew all things, nor was always conscious of His
Messianic dignity, and even in some things He erred, for example, concerning the
end of the world.
Against these errors, it is de fide that Christ never erred, that He even
could not err, or in other words, that He was already infallible in this life.
It is at least the commonly accepted and theologically certain doctrine that
Christ's soul was free from ignorance. What follows makes this clear.
It is de fide that Christ, as man, was free from all error in His knowledge,
that Christ, in fact, the founder of the Church, even in this life was
infallible, just as He was impeccable.
1) Sacred Scripture is evidence of this, inasmuch as Christ says of Himself:
"I am the way and the truth and the life."[1103] As God, He is truth
and life; as man He is the way to essential truth, inasmuch as His human nature
and His whole human intellectual life is personally united with essential truth.
Thus, as man, He is presented to us as the master of truth, whom we must hear.
"Neither be ye called masters, for one is your master, Christ,"[1104]
and as the leader, following whom we never walk in darkness;[1105] who, in
establishing His Church, made her infallible in her teaching, saying: "Thou
art Peter, and upon this rock I will build My Church, and the gates of hell
shall not prevail against it."[1106] But if it had been possible for Christ
to err, a fortiori the Church He established could err in her teaching.
2) Christ was not only infallible in the doctrine He delivered to His
apostles, but also in His acts, as is evident from the Gospel narrative, for it
says that Christ, already in this life, saw and knew the thoughts of men, and
had complete knowledge of the free future, foretelling the events long before
the time. Thus He foretold the circumstances of His passion, the destruction of
Jerusalem, the continuance of His Church until the end of time.[1107]
Finally and especially in the Gospel it is recorded that Christ is the Word
of God made flesh, "full of grace and truth."[1108] That Christ was
infallible, as we have seen, not only in the doctrine He delivered, and the
events affirmed by Him, but this also follows as universally established by
reason of the hypostatic union. The Word, indeed, assumed the complete human
nature, but free from error and sin, for as sin is evil of the will, error is
evil of the intellect; and as it is absolutely repugnant, as will be stated
farther on, that the Word incarnate sinned or even was able to sin, so it was
repugnant that He erred or even was able to err. For error would reflect on the
very person of the Word in accordance with the adage: actions are attributed to
the supposita. Hence error and sin cannot be attributed to the Word of God, who
is essentially truth and holiness. Thus it is commonly said to be de fide that
Christ, as man, the founder of the infallible Church, was infallible. To show
the truth of this discursion by the explanatory method suffices, namely, an
explanation of the terms of revelation, for an objectively illative method of
reasoning is not necessary, namely, one by which a new truth is acquired that is
not in itself revealed.
It is at least commonly accepted and theologically certain doctrine, that
Christ's knowledge was absolutely exempt from all ignorance and not only from
error.
St. Thomas proves this, presupposing that Christ had both beatific knowledge
and infused knowledge.[1109] But it is first fitting to manifest the truth of
this assertion from Sacred Scripture and tradition, so that by a quasi a
posterori method it may afterward be clearly seen how it befitted Him to have
this beatific knowledge even in this life.
Sacred Scripture. The texts already quoted state clearly that Christ's
knowledge was absolutely exempt from all ignorance. Thus Christ is declared
"full of grace and truth."[1110] He also knew the secrets of
hearts,[1111] as also distant objects and the free future.[1112] These texts,
however, do not refer to His uncreated knowledge, but to His human knowledge,
which governed His human operation. Therefore Christ as man was exempt from all
ignorance. Thus as man He was, as He Himself said, the way that leads to the
truth and life.
Tradition likewise establishes more clearly that Christ's knowledge was
immune from ignorance, especially from the declaration of St. Gregory the Great
to the patriarch of Alexandria against the Agnoetae. The Pope says: "[But]
concerning what is written: "of that day or hour no man knoweth, neither
the angels of heaven, nor the Son,’[1113] this has been most correctly
understood by your beatitude, since this text most certainly refers not to the
Son, inasmuch as He is the head[of the Church], but to His body which we are.[St.
Augustine] also says... that it can be understood of the Son, because the
omnipotent God does speak at times in a human way, as when He said to Abraham:
"Now I know that thou fearest God.,[1114] It is not because then God
Himself knew that He was feared but because then He made Abraham acknowledge
that he feared God. For just as we declare a day joyful, not that the day itself
is joyful, but because it makes us joyful, so the omnipotent Son says that He
does not know the day which He causes to be unknown, not because He does not
know it, but because He does not at all permit it to be known.... And so the
knowledge He did not have according to His human nature, which made Him, like
the angels, a creature, this knowledge along with the angels who are creatures
He said He did not have. Therefore He who is God and man knows the day and the
hour of judgment; but the reason for this is because God is man. But the issue
is most manifest, for whoever is not a Nestorian can nowise be an Agnoete. For
anyone who confesses the very incarnate wisdom of God, how can he say there is
anything that the wisdom of God does not know? It is also written: "Jesus
knowing that the Father had given Him all things into His hands.’[1115] If He
knows all things, assuredly He knows the day and the hour of the judgment;
therefore who is so foolish as to say that the Son received into His hands what
He was ignorant of?"[1116]
In accordance with this doctrine thus explicitly formulated by Pope St.
Gregory the Great, the common teaching of theologians will always be that Christ
knew the day of judgment in His human nature, but not by reason of His human
nature, which means that He did not know it by the natural light of the created
intellect. Thus the angels, too, know this day only if they are supernaturally
enlightened.[1117]
Before the time of St. Gregory several Fathers spoke in a similar manner,
namely, that Christ knows all things, even the day and hour of the judgment; but
He is silent about this latter event, or He says He does not know because He
does not permit it to be known, and because it is not expedient that men be
informed about it.[1118] St. Augustine teaches that ignorance can in no way be
attributed to that Infant in whom the Word was made flesh.[1119]
Sophronius[1120] is of the same opinion, and St. John Damascene says:
"If the flesh from the moment of conception was immediately united with
God... and the two constituted one identical suppositum, then how can it be that
it was not endowed with absolutely all the gifts of wisdom and
grace?"[1121] It is in this sense that the Fathers interpreted the words
"full of grace and truth,"[1122] concerning the Word incarnate.
In our times there are several Modernist propositions that have been
condemned by the Church concerning Christ's knowledge.[1123] Among these are:
"The natural sense of the Gospel texts cannot be reconciled with what our
theologians teach about the consciousness and infallible knowledge of Jesus
Christ."[1124] "Christ was not always conscious of His Messianic
dignity."[1125]
Also later on the Holy Office declared that the following propositions cannot
be safely taught: (1) "There is no evidence that Christ's soul in this life
possessed that knowledge which the blessed or comprehensors have; (2) That
opinion cannot be called certain that concludes Christ's soul was exempt from
ignorance, but knew everything in the Word, past, present, and future, from the
moment of His conception, or that He knew everything God knows by His knowledge
of vision; (3) The opinion of certain more recent theologians about Christ's
limited knowledge is equally to be accepted in Catholic schools, as the opinion
of the ancient theologians concerning Christ's universal knowledge."[1126]
We shall see later on, in the explanation of the article, the theological
reasons given by St. Thomas for maintaining the universality of Christ's
knowledge.
Modernist objections. On the one hand, the Modernists assert that Christ
erred in announcing that the end of the world was near; on the other hand, He
said that He did not know the judgment day. These two objections are
contradictory.
First objection. It has been examined at length by us in our work on
apologetics,[1127] and there is no need to dwell upon it here. The difficulty
arises from two Gospel texts. After foretelling the destruction of Jerusalem and
the day of judgment, Jesus says: "This generation shall not pass till all
these things be done."[1128] In the other text it is recorded that before
the transfiguration of Jesus, He said: "There are some of them that stand
here, that shall not taste death, till they see the Son of man coming in His
kingdom."[1129]
Reply. This last text more probably alludes to the future and proximate
resurrection of Christ.[1130] But other texts quoted from Sacred Scripture on
this subject are indeed difficult to reconcile, for in this same discourse
Christ spoke of both the end of Jerusalem and the end of the world, and although
the first event is a figure of the second, it is difficult to detect what
belongs to the first event, and what to the second. But what any particularly
learned author has to say on this topic must be understood, if possible, as
showing that there is no contradiction between the texts. However, as Catholic
exegetes show,[1131] and several conservative Protestants, such as Godet and
Sanday, the rationalist and Modernist interpretation is not founded on the
Gospel texts, but is very much in contradiction to it.
1) Christ not only sent His apostles to the people of Israel, but He said to
them: "Go ye into the whole world, and preach the gospel to every
creature,"[1132] and "Going therefore teach ye all
nations."[1133] He expressly says: "And unto all nations the gospel
must first be preached,"[1134] before the second coming. Also: "And...
many shall come from the east and the west...."[1135] But Christ did not
announce these events as taking place in the immediate future.
2) He even distinguished in point of time between the destruction of
Jerusalem and the end of the world, saying: "Jerusalem shall be trodden
down by the Gentiles, till the times of the nations be fulfilled,"[1136]
and de facto it is trodden down. Christ especially refused to state precisely
when the end of the world would be, but He said: "It is not for you to know
the times or moments which the Father hath put in His own power."[1137]
Second objection. Some of the earlier Fathers, such as St. Athanasius, St.
Gregory Nazianzen, St. Cyril of Alexandria, say that Christ was ignorant of the
Judgment Day.[1138]
Reply. These earlier Fathers were refuting the Arians and their only purpose
was to bring out clearly the divinity of Christ in these texts, exempting it of
every defect attributed to it, especially ignorance. Hence they said: If Christ
was ignorant of the Judgment Day, He was ignorant of it not as the Word, but as
man. The question of the perfection of Christ's human knowledge had not as yet
been agitated. Hence no wonder that these earlier Fathers spoke somewhat
inexactly on this subject.
Moreover, we shall see that also the more recent doctors and even Scholastics
say that Christ knew the Judgment Day not from His human nature, that is, not by
the natural light of the created intellect, but only by supernatural
enlightenment.
Third objection. Some, too, have proposed the difficulty that the Gospel
records that Christ often asked questions of men, such as, what they thought of
Him, where the body of Lazarus was laid, and other such questions. They say that
He even expressed amazement, for example, at the faith of the centurion and the
incredulity of the people.
Reply. It is evident from the Gospel narrative that Christ asked questions in
a human way, and likewise expressed admiration, but this was not from lack of
knowledge, for the Evangelist says: "He needed not that any should give
testimony of men; for He knew what was in man."[1139]
It is therefore clearly established from all these texts that Christ was
exempt from all error, which is de fide, and from all ignorance, which is at
least theologically certain. Thus we gain a clearer understanding why the
question is put about whether Christ already in this life enjoyed the beatific
vision.
Did Christ, during His mortal life, enjoy the beatific vision?
Reply. The answer is that Christ did, and ever since the twelfth century it
has been the traditional teaching of all theologians, so that it is at least a
theologically certain truth.[1140]
Hence the Sacred Congregation of the Holy Office declared (June 7, 1918) that
the following proposition cannot be safely taught: "There is no evidence
that Christ, living among men, had in His soul the knowledge the blessed or
comprehensors have."[1141]
Scriptural proof. There are, indeed, several texts in the New Testament from
which it is evident that the Son of God, as God, sees the Father. Thus Jesus
says of Himself: "As the Father knoweth Me, and I know the
Father,"[1142] and "No one knoweth the Son but the Father; neither
doth anyone know the Father, but the Son."[1143]
It is considerably difficult to show from these texts that Christ even as
man, already in this life, saw God immediately in His essence. But there are
texts in the Fourth Gospel which make it sufficiently clear that Christ as man,
already in this life, saw the Father.
For in this Gospel we read: "No man hath seen God at any time; the
only-begotten Son who is in the bosom of the Father, He hath declared
Him."[1144] And again: "He that cometh from above is above all.... And
what He hath seen and heard, that He testifieth."[1145] Also: "I speak
that which I have seen with My Father."[1146] Hence the common method of
argumentation among theologians may be expressed in the following syllogistic
form.
What Christ preached as man, He knew as man, for human speech is the result
of human intellectual knowledge; otherwise the Word would take the place of the
rational soul in Christ, which was the contention of Appollinaris. But as man,
Christ declared what He saw with the Father and in the bosom of the Father.
Therefore Christ saw those things in the bosom of the Father, as man, and it is
also said that He heard them, which properly belongs not to God inasmuch as He
is God, but to man.
Moreover, all knowledge of divine things, exclusive of the beatific vision,
pertains to the order of faith. Hence, if Christ did not see those truths that
are in God, we should have to say He believed them, and thus as man He would not
have known many and most sublime truths. It would have to be said of Him that
concerning God He had known what He is not, instead of what He is. But we have
already seen that Christ, as man, was exempt from ignorance. Nevertheless there
is truly a difference between nescience and ignorance, and it would be possible
for one to say that Christ did not know the secret of God's intimate life, but
not that He was ignorant of it, simply because it was not as yet fitting for Him
to know it. On the contrary, this fittingness will be clarified farther on in
the theological proof from reason.
This argument is confirmed by the following Gospel text: "Not that any
man hath seen the Father, but He who is of God, He hath seen the
Father."[1147]
This means that He not only saw the secrets of the Father in His hidden life,
but He also saw the Father Himself. The word "Vidit" is written as a
quasi-preterite so as to make it clear that this vision transcends time, or, as
the theologians say, it is measured by participated eternity.
There are two other texts from the Gospel which make it manifest that Christ
had consciousness of and not merely faith in His divine nature and personality.
For the Evangelist records Jesus as saying: "Although I give testimony of
Myself, My testimony is true, for I know whence I came and whither I go,[1148] I
know and not only believe." And again He says: "I came out from God. I
came forth from the Father and am come into the world."[1149] When Christ
says, "I know whence I came." He was conscious not only of His
mission, but also of His divine nature and personality. But this clear
consciousness of His divine nature transcends the supernatural knowledge of
faith, for faith is of things not seen, and above the supernatural knowledge of
faith there is only the beatific vision, as will be more clearly seen farther
on.
Finally, there is another Gospel text in which Christ speaks more clearly as
man when He says: "No man hath ascended into heaven, but He that descended
from heaven, the Son of man who is in heaven."[1150] The Son of man is
Christ as man, and it is said of Him that He has already ascended into heaven,
and that He is now in heaven, which means in paradise or in the beatific state.
It cannot be said that He is already in heaven solely by means of the hypostatic
union, for the whole context is concerned with ascent in the order of knowledge;
for in the text that immediately precedes, Jesus had said: "If I have
spoken to you earthly things, and you do not believe; how will you believe if I
shall speak to you of heavenly things."[1151] Christ, in calling others to
the faith, never says that He Himself believes, but that He sees, and knows
whence He came, namely, by the knowledge of vision, and that already "He is
in heaven." This text is confirmed by another, in which Jesus says:
"'Father, I will that where I am, they also whom Thou hast given Me may be
with Me; that they may see My glory, which Thou hast given Me."[1152]
Proof from tradition. The above-mentioned texts of Sacred Scripture are
furthermore declared and explained by tradition. The Second Council of
Constantinople implicitly affirms Christ's beatific vision in this life, when it
says that "He did not increase in holiness as He advanced in the
performance of good works."[1153] If He did not have the beatific vision
from the beginning of His existence, He would have very much increased in
holiness, by passing from the state of faith and of wayfarer to that of vision,
and to the final state of glory in heaven. The Fathers likewise in various ways
affirming that Christ did not increase in holiness, implicitly teach that He was
from the beginning of His existence both comprehensor and wayfarer, which we
find afterward is the common teaching, especially since the twelfth century.
Rouet de Journel[1154] quotes several patristic texts that explicitly affirm
Christ's beatific vision in this life. Thus Eusebius of Caesarea says:
"Then, too, when [Christ] was living among men, He nevertheless
accomplished everything, in the meantime being with the Father and in the
Father, and at the same time He likewise took care of all things, both celestial
and terrestrial, nowhere without that presence, which is in all things, our way
excluded, nor hindered by the divine presence from acting in His accustomed
way."[1155] St. Basil clearly enough affirms that Christ, our Savior,
already had the beatific knowledge in the highest degree.[1156]
This is more clearly asserted by St. Fulgentius, who writes: "How harsh
it is and entirely incompatible with sound faith to say that Christ's soul, even
in this life, did not have complete knowledge of His divine nature, with which
we believe that He naturally constituted one person."[1157] And he adds:
"That soul knew His divine nature completely, yet the soul is not the
divine nature. Therefore that very divine nature is naturally known to it, but
that soul received from the divine nature, which it knew, the power to know
It"[1158]
Finally, St. Augustine maintains that Paul, who was rapt to the third heaven,
saw the divine essence and not merely a certain refulgence of this
brightness.[1159] But if, as St. Augustine says, St. Paul had the beatific
vision transiently, already in this life, then a fortiori Christ Himself must
have had it, and not merely in a transient way.
Theological proof. The first argument is taken from the end of the
Incarnation. It is one of fitness and from this point is most convincing. It may
be expressed by the following syllogism.
What is in potentiality is reduced to act by what is in act. But men are in
potentiality to see God to which they are ordained by God, and to which they
must be brought by Christ's human nature. Therefore Christ as man most fittingly
had the beatific vision.
Major. It is evident, for it enunciates the very principle of causality. Thus
nothing becomes hot except by what is actually hot; and the cause must always be
more efficacious than its effect.[1160]
It is, of course, true that Christ's soul is only the instrumental cause of
glory in the blessed, not by its own power, but by the power of the principal
agent, namely, the Deity. Nevertheless it is a most excellent instrument, which
is capable of being instrumental in producing the form which is beatitude.
Therefore it is fitting for the soul actually to have this beatitude. Hence St.
Thomas does not infer that this was strictly necessary but that it was proper
because it was becoming.[1161]
We thus have from this application of the major to Christ's humanity an
argument of fitness. It must also be said, however, that what is more fitting
and more excellent must be granted to Christ, unless it be incompatible with the
end of the Incarnation, and especially if it manifestly contributes to this end,
as will be explained in the minor. Christ is, of course, the most perfect
Redeemer.
Minor. It is de fide, both as to the ordaining of men to the beatific vision,
and as to Christ's influence as Savior on them, in bringing them to eternal
life. Christ said; "I am the way and the truth and the life."[1162] He
is the way as man, and as God He is the truth and the life. Similarly a text
from St. Paul is quoted in this article, which says: "It became Him, for
whom are all things, and by whom are all things, who had brought many children
into glory, to perfect the author of their salvation, by His
passion."[1163] For Him to bring men into glory, He most fittingly had it
already in this life.
The force of this argument of fitness is more clearly seen when Christ as man
is compared with the apostles, the great doctors of later times, and the higher
contemplatives. The Savior of all, as we said, the head of the Church, both
militant, suffering, and triumphant; He was the supreme doctor in divine
matters, the Master of all masters and contemplatives, from whom we have
received the fullness of the revelation of life. In other words, already on
earth, He was, as man, the supreme witness of divine truth, already transcending
the beatified angels,[1164] so that St. Paul speaking in Christ's name, could
say: "But though we or an angel from heaven preach a gospel to you besides
that which we have preached to you, let him be anathema."[1165] Thus Christ
as the Master of all masters and higher contemplatives is the most perfect
leader to beatitude even to the end of time, which means that He will be
surpassed by no master. Therefore it was most becoming to him, as man, that He
should give testimony as an ocular witness concerning the beatific vision, and
that He should have complete knowledge of the ultimate end to which He must
bring all wayfarers of all times in this life.[1166]
Confirmation. This argument of fitness is all the more convincing when we
consider either the sublime contemplation of St. John the Evangelist concerning
the Word, in the Prologue of his Gospel, or that of St. Paul, the doctor of the
Gentiles, who says: "I know a man in Christ above fourteen years ago
(whether in the body I know not, or out of the body, I know not, God knoweth),
such a one caught up to the third heaven.[1167] And I know such a man, whether
in the body or out of the body, I know not, God knoweth, that he was caught up
into paradise, and heard secret word which it is not granted to man to
utter."[1168] But if St. Paul, that he might be the doctor of the Gentiles,
and might always have more, by his preaching, in his mind and heart than in
utterance, received such a gift of contemplation, so that his preaching came
from the fullness of his contemplation, as St. Thomas says,[1169] what must be
thought of Christ's contemplation, so that He might fittingly be the supreme
Doctor of all generations of men? Christ must have, however, what is most
fitting for Him to have.
Moreover, it must be noted that St. Thomas, following St. Augustine,
maintains that St. Paul, when in rapture, "saw the very essence of God and
not a certain reflection of His clarity";[1170] and so he concludes:
"Therefore it is more becoming to hold that he saw God in His
essence."[1171] St. Thomas considers this view the more probable one. But
if such was the case, then a fortiori, Christ already in this life saw the
Deity.[1172]
St. Thomas, too, because of his sublime contemplation, toward the end of his
life became incapable of dictating any more of his Theological Summa, which
appeared to him as straw, and not wheat; yet Christ's contemplation was far more
sublime. It certainly transcended Adam's contemplation in the state of
innocence, concerning which St. Thomas says: "Adam did not see God in His
essence.... The difference between the vision the blessed enjoy and that granted
to the wayfarer does not consist in this, that the former sees more perfectly
and the other less perfectly, but in this, that the former sees God and the
latter does not see Him."[1173] To believe is not to see, for faith is of
things not seen. Adam's contemplation in the state of innocence remained within
the order of faith, whereas Christ's contemplation in this life transcended this
order.
Thus we understand how Christ's preaching is both most sublime and most
simple and beyond all possibility of contradiction. Moreover, it is adapted to
all minds, to most learned or simple minds; whereas, on the contrary, human
teachers often speak in a terminology that is not accessible to all, because
they do not sufficiently realize the relations that should exist between the
doctrine to be explained and the more profound aspiration of the human heart. On
this subject Bossuet remarks: "Who would not admire the condescension He
shows in adapting the sublimity of His doctrine to His audience? It is milk for
children and entirely bread for the strong. We see Him filled with God's
secrets, but He is not astonished at this, as other mortals are to whom He
communicates Himself. He speaks in a natural way of them, as though born to
these secrets and this glory. What He has beyond measure,[1174] this He imparts
to others by degrees, so that our weakness may be able to bear it."[1175]
He is the supreme Master, of unique and incomparable authority. Thus with the
greatest simplicity He enlightens the mind, fills the heart with holy joy, and
efficaciously moves the will to upright and holy action.[1176] This preaching
must come from the plenitude of most sublime contemplation.
Finally, this argument would find its corroboration by considering what such
mystics as St. John of the Cross and St. Theresa have to say about most sublime
mystic contemplation in this life, and the intellectual vision of the Most Holy
Trinity by means of infused species. This vision, so far as God is not yet seen
directly as He is in His essence, belongs to the order of faith.[1177] There is
not yet intrinsic evidence of the mystery of the Trinity, so that it is quite
evident that God could not be God if He were not the triune God. But Christ
already in this life certainly had a sublimer contemplation of the Trinity than
that of the most sublime contemplative, even, as we shall see farther on, He was
not without it when dying on the cross. Hence St. Paul says that in Christ Jesus
"are hid all the treasures of wisdom and knowledge."[1178]
This argument is derived from the end of the Incarnation. There are other
arguments that have their foundation in the divine personality of Christ, and
His consciousness of this personality.
Second argument. It rests on the consciousness Christ had of His divine
nature and of His divine personality. He said, as we already remarked:
"Although I give testimony of Myself, My testimony is true, for I know
whence I came and whither I go."[1179] And again: "I came out from
God. I came forth from the Father and am come into the world."[1180] From
these texts it is clearly enough established that Christ was conscious of His
divine nature, for He does not say "I believe," but "I know
whence I came." There is also another text in which He says: "I speak
that which I have seen with My Father."[1181] He spoke as man, therefore He
sees as man.
But this consciousness would not transcend the order of faith unless it were
the direct vision of the Deity; for above the order of faith illuminated by the
gifts of the Holy Ghost, such as we find in saints who are still wayfarers,
there is only the beatific vision.[1182] Therefore, if Christ did not have this
beatific vision, then He only believed in His divine nature and divine
personality, just as the saints believe in the indwelling of the most Holy
Trinity in the souls of the just.
Objection. The saints who are still wayfarers have a quasi-experimental
knowledge of this presence of the most Holy Trinity through the filial love God
enkindles in their hearts, as St. Thomas says, for concerning the following text
of St. Paul, "The Spirit Himself giveth testimony to our
spirit."[1183] he remarks: "He gives testimony by means of the filial
love He enkindles in our hearts."[1184]
Reply. This quasi-experimental knowledge does not rise above the order of
faith, for it is the result of faith illumined by the gifts of the Holy Ghost,
especially the gift of wisdom, and so it is faith penetrating and tasting the
mysteries of God in accordance with the text: "Taste and see that the Lord
is sweet."[1185] But these saints who are still wayfarers do not see the
Trinity present in themselves, but they have a certain experimental knowledge
and belief of this presence. On the contrary, Christ said: "I know whence I
came."[1186] "I speak that which I have seen with My
Father."[1187]
Third argument. It has its foundation in the influences of the hypostatic
union. By the very fact of the hypostatic union, which in itself is more exalted
than the beatific vision, Christ's soul was in the state of comprehensor. But
this state of comprehensor pertains to the beatific vision. Therefore it was
fitting for Christ to be both wayfarer and comprehensor, as all theologians
commonly admit, especially after the twelfth century.
This argument is corroborated by considering the overflow from this grace of
union. For the nearer any recipient is to an inflowing cause, the more it
partakes of its influence, as already stated in discussing the fullness of
habitual grace in Christ.[1188] But Christ's human nature was united personally
to the Word of God. Therefore it was supremely fitting for Christ as man, even
in this life, to participate in this most perfect grace, which is the grace that
is consummated by glory.
Fourth argument. It is founded on natural sonship. Christ as man, was
predestined not to divine adoptive sonship, but to divine natural sonship, which
surpasses even glory.[1189] But divine natural filiation implies the right to
divine heirship, even to the immediate attainment of this heirship, which
consists in the intuitive vision of God. Therefore the beatific vision was
befitting to Christ as man, even in this life.
As we have already stated, what was befitting to Christ must be attributed to
Him, especially if this serves, as we have seen, the end of the redemptive
Incarnation, so that Christ may be the ideal Master of all masters even to the
end of the world.
It must be noted that this doctrine is also confirmed from what St. Thomas
teaches concerning the knowledge of the apostles.[1190]
The theologically certain conclusions to be deduced from all these arguments
is that Christ already in this life had the beatific vision, and truly was, as
commonly admitted by theologians since the twelfth century, both wayfarer and
comprehensor. Thus Christ already in this life clearly saw the Trinity and all
mysteries of grace, such as that efficacious grace is not only reconciled with
free will, but is also the reason why the choice is free.
Doubt. Did Christ have the beatific vision from the first moment of His
conception?
Reply. St. Thomas answers this question in the affirmative[1191] because
Christ's human nature from the first moment of its creation was assumed by the
Word, and the beatific vision befitted Christ as man, inasmuch as, by virtue of
the hypostatic union, He was the head of the Church. Hence all the preceding
proofs apply with equal force for the first moment of conception. For this was
in no way repugnant to the end of the Incarnation; it was even befitting to this
end. Moreover, the Council of Constantinople condemned the proposition that
Christ would have become better; but He would have become better if He had
received the beatific vision in the course of the present life.[1192]
Objection. It is more perfect to merit the glory of heaven than to have it
without merit, and Christ's merits were completed only by His death. In fact,
Jesus said, as recorded in the Gospel: "Ought not Christ to have suffered
these things, and so to enter into His glory?"[1193] Therefore Christ
entered into glory only after His death.
Reply. With St. Thomas, I distinguish the antecedent, namely, that it is also
more perfect for Christ to have a thing by merit than without merit "unless
it be of such a nature[for example, a gift] that its want would detract from
Christ's dignity and perfection more than would accrue to Him by merit. Hence He
merited neither grace nor knowledge, nor the beatitude of His soul, nor the
Godhead..., the want of which would have diminished Christ's dignity more than
His merits would have increased it. But the glory of the body and the like are
less than the dignity of meriting which pertains to the virtue of
charity."[1194] Thus Christ merited the glory of His body, which is the
sense of the text quoted above from St. Luke.[1195]
Second objection. Utmost joy is incompatible with utmost sorrow. But Christ
said in the Garden of Gethsemane: "My soul is sorrowful even unto
death."[1196] Therefore at this time He had neither this beatific joy, nor
hence the beatific vision, to which this joy is the necessary sequel.
Reply. In answer to this, we say with St. Thomas:[1197] that utmost joy is
incompatible with utmost sorrow concerning absolutely the same object considered
in the same aspect, I concede; otherwise, I subdistinguish; naturally
incompatible, I concede; supernaturally so, I deny. But Christ was
supernaturally both wayfarer, inasmuch as His human nature was passible, and
comprehensor in the higher part of the mind. Nay, even as we showed in another
work,[1198] His utmost joy and His utmost sorrow were the result of this same
plenitude of grace.
On the one hand, from the plenitude of consummated grace there resulted the
light of glory, the beatific vision, the highest degree of love of God, and
supreme joy. On the other hand, from this same plenitude of Christ's grace as
wayfarer, and from His utmost love for God and for us, there resulted the utmost
of supernatural grief for the sins of men, inasmuch as they are an offense
against God and bring supernatural death to our souls. Moreover, because of His
utmost love for God and for us, Christ willed as priest and voluntary victim to
offer Himself as a most perfect holocaust; and for this reason, in virtue of His
love, He most freely delivered Himself up to grief, by preventing the overflow
of glory from the higher part of His mind into the lower parts and allowed
Himself to be overwhelmed by all manner of grief in His sensitive nature. Herein
is the miracle consequent upon the unique state of Christ as both wayfarer and
comprehensor.
St. Thomas says: "Christ grieved not only over the loss of His own
bodily life, but also over the sins of all others. And this grief in Christ
surpassed all grief of every contrite heart, both because it flowed from a
greater wisdom and charity, by which the pang of contrition is intensified, and
because He grieved at the one time for all sins, according to Isaias 53:4:
"Surely He hath carried our sorrows. "[1199]
St. Thomas says likewise in another treatise about Christ's passion:
"These same things about which[Christ] grieved according to the senses,
imagination, and lower reason, in the higher[reason] were a source of joy,
inasmuch as He referred them to the order of divine wisdom.... He allowed each
of the lower powers to be moved by its own impulse,"[1200] and He
experienced sadness in the highest degree so that He might become a perfect
holocaust. Thus He rejoiced in His passion inasmuch as it contributed to the
redemption of the human race, and it made Him sad inasmuch as it was contrary to
nature. Thus He most freely abandoned Himself to grief, limiting the beatific
joy to the summit of His mind and preventing it from overflowing into the lower
part of His mind and into His sensitive nature. Thus, by most freely abandoning
Himself to grief, as a most generous and voluntary victim, He prevented the
overflow of joy of the higher part of the mind into the lower. But this grief
ceased when Christ was no longer a wayfarer. Hence Christ suffering in His human
nature is like a mountain, the summit of which is poised in the clear sky, the
base of which is made desolate by stormy weather.
Third Article: Whether Christ Had Imprinted Or Infused Knowledge
State of the question. Besides the beatific vision, did Christ have knowledge
infused by God, which is also called imprinted knowledge, inasmuch as it is
given to the soul along with the nature as in the angels? The question concerns
knowledge that is not only per accidens infused, but also per se, namely, that
can be caused only by God, and cannot be acquired by one's own acts.
The difficulty is: (1) It seems that the beatific vision, since it is perfect
knowledge, excludes that which is imperfect, and so it excludes faith; (2) it
seems that infused knowledge is at least superfluous, just as the disposition
for a form is superfluous, when it is already present; (3) finally, just as
matter cannot receive simultaneously two forms, so also the intellect cannot
simultaneously receive these two kinds of knowledge, the beatific and the
infused.
Conclusion. It befitted Christ as man to have infused knowledge besides the
beatific vision.
Scriptural proof. St. Paul says: "In Christ are hid all the treasures of
wisdom and knowledge."[1201] But included in these treasures is infused
knowledge as found in the angels and in disembodied spirits, a knowledge which
several of the saints also received in this life for the perfect exercise of
their mission. Thus the apostles received the gift of tongues, but this
knowledge of languages was in them only per accidens infused, because they could
have learned these languages by their own efforts. Yet some saints also received
knowledge that was at least per se infused concerning certain things, as mystic
theologians show especially when they treat of intellectual visions that take
place through the intermediary of infused species. St. Paul, too, who heard
"the secret words of God,"[1202] received either the beatific vision
as a transient act, which is the opinion of St. Augustine and St. Thomas, or
else a sublime form of infused knowledge, transmitted by means of infused
species. Therefore infused knowledge pertains to these "treasures of wisdom
and knowledge,"[1203] which St. Paul speaks of. The Fathers often speak of
Christ's imprinted knowledge, but they do not as yet explicitly distinguish it
from beatific knowledge. But from the time of Peter Lombard, theologians
commonly admit three kinds of knowledge in Christ, namely, beatific, infused,
and acquired. This common consent of the theologians, however, would have for us
the force of a certain argument from tradition if they were to assert that this
doctrine is de fide; this, however, they do not assert. Hence it is only a
theological conclusion that is commonly admitted by the Scholastics, which does
not appear to be definable by the Church as doctrine that pertains to the faith,
because it is the result of a strictly illative process of reasoning, and is not
merely explicative. This consent of the theologians gives at least great
probability to this opinion about the kinds of knowledge in Christ, as being a
commonly accepted opinion.
Theological proof. It was fitting that the nature assumed by the Word should
not be imperfect. But it would have been imperfect without infused knowledge.
Therefore it was fitting that Christ as man should have infused knowledge.
Major. It expresses a certain moral necessity, which presupposes the
hypostatic union, namely, that what is more worthy and more excellent and is not
repugnant to the end of the Incarnation, must be granted to Christ. In other
words, only corporal defects are to be attributed to Christ, such as
passibility, death, thirst, and such defects that are necessary for our
redemption by the sacrifice on the cross, as will be stated farther on.[1204]
This moral necessity did not lessen, as some said, the divine liberty,
because it depends on the most free decree of the redemptive Incarnation. But
this decree being posited, then the great fitness of the Incarnation follows as
a necessary consequence, and it was necessary because it was fitting. In other
words, it was necessary to grant the Word of God incarnate what manifestly
befits Him. Thus the conclusion is proved and is not merely a persuasive
argument.
Minor. It is proved by the following syllogism. Everything in potentiality is
imperfect unless it be reduced to act. But the possible human intellect is in
potentiality to all intelligible things, and to know them not only in the Word
by the beatific vision, or merely in themselves by acquired knowledge, but in
themselves by infused knowledge, as the angels and disembodied spirits know
them. Therefore the soul of Christ had infused knowledge inasmuch as His
possible human intellect was in potentiality to know intelligible things as the
angels and disembodied spirits know them, which is by infused species.
This knowledge befitted Christ even in this life, before the separation of
His soul from the body, because He was not only wayfarer but also comprehensor.
Hence St. Thomas says: "Since Christ was both comprehensor and wayfarer, He
had each way of considering things, one by which He was like the angels,
inasmuch as He considered things without process of reasoning, the other by
having recourse to phantasms."[1205] Thus anyone who has the gift of
tongues can actually make use of it without having to study the grammar of the
language, but this can also be studied. Hence, as St. Thomas says: "Even as
in the angels, according to Augustine (Gen. ad lit., Bk. IV, chaps. 22, 24, 30),
there is a double knowledge: one the morning knowledge, whereby they know things
in the Word; the other the evening knowledge, whereby they know things in their
proper natures by infused species, so also there was this twofold knowledge in
Christ."[1206] These species were imprinted on the minds of the angels by
the Word of God, and it equally befitted the Word of God to perfect Christ's
soul, which was personally united to the Word. Finally, Christ's soul would have
been made more perfect if it had received these infused species only after its
separation from the body. It was not fitting for Christ in this mortal life to
be lacking in experimental knowledge of the mode of cognition pertaining to
disembodied spirits, for whom He merited and grieved, and for whom He died. When
in the parable of the wicked rich man He spoke of the state of the soul
separated from the body, this shows that He had experimental knowledge of the
mode of cognition of these souls.
This thesis finds its confirmation from the extraordinary events in the lives
of the saints, for example, in the life of St. Catherine of Siena, for our Lord
gave her infused knowledge concerning the hidden lives of several saints, and
marvelous spiritual insight in doctrinal matters, a doctrine which she dictated
when in ecstasy, and which is preserved for us in her Dialogue; she also learned
to read and write not by her own efforts, but our Lord Himself was her teacher;
even the secrets of hearts and distant events she often knew by infused
knowledge.[1207] Similar extraordinary knowledge was granted to other
saints,[1208] and a fortiori this was the prerogative of the most holy soul of
Christ.
Doubt. Is this knowledge only per accidens infused, or is it per se infused?
Reply. It is per accidens infused so far as it concerns things that can be
known by human efforts, and it is per se infused so far as it concerns things
that cannot be acquired by human efforts and are therefore beyond the powers of
our intellect. In fact, we must, in the same way, distinguish in Christ between
two kinds of subordinated infused knowledge, just as in the just there are two
kinds of prudence, one infused and of the supernatural order, specified by a
supernatural object, the other acquired and of the natural order, specified by a
natural object. Thus a musician has in a certain manner the art of music in the
practical intellect, but the ability to play is in the hands. Indeed, Christ
could by His infused knowledge of supernatural things know also by this eminent
knowledge natural things in their relation to supernatural things, but it
befitted Him also to know these things in another way, namely, by knowledge that
is per accidens infused to which His intellect was in potentiality.[1209] Thus
Christ knew the supernatural secrets of hearts by knowledge that is per se
infused, just as in our times He speaks in an exceptional way to certain saints,
who are still wayfarers, in their own language or dialect.
Confirmation of this doctrine from the solution of the objections of this
article.
Reply to first objection. The beatific vision excludes faith, which is of
things not seen, but it does not exclude infused knowledge; for the same
intellect can by two distinct means see things in two ways: first, in the Word,
and secondly in themselves. Thus there are two ways, either by physics or by
mathematics, whereby we can know the same conclusion, for example, the rotundity
of the earth.
Reply to second objection. As he who knew some conclusion by a probable
argument, and afterward knows it by a demonstrative argument, can still consider
the probable argument; although he no longer holds it as an opinion that he
fears may be wrong, that is, he no longer wavers between uncertainty and
certainty, so Christ can have simultaneously both beatific knowledge and infused
knowledge.
Reply to third objection. The beatific vision does not render infused
knowledge superfluous; for the ineffable knowledge of things in the Word does
not make the knowledge of them in themselves superfluous. Moreover, these two
acts can be simultaneous, provided that there is subordination, just as we can
have knowledge of principle and conclusion. The Blessed Virgin Mary also had
infused knowledge on this earth.
Fourth Article: Whether Christ Had Any Acquired Knowledge
State of the question. This article concerns the habit of experimental
knowledge acquired by the intellect through species abstracted from phantasms,
or obtained gradually by individual acts.
The difficulty is: (1) If Christ had this knowledge, then He did not have it
perfectly, because He never studied. (2) This acquired knowledge seems
superfluous if Christ already had directly infused knowledge of created things,
and especially if He already had accidentally infused knowledge of sensible
things.
Conclusion. Christ had knowledge that is essentially capable of being
acquired, and that was also actually acquired by Him.
Scriptural proof. St. Paul says: "Whereas, indeed, He was the Son of
God, He learned obedience by the things which He suffered,"[1210] that is,
by what He experienced. Farther on,[1211] St. Thomas quotes the following Gospel
text: "Jesus advanced in wisdom and age, and grace with God and
men,"[1212] which He explains as resulting from an increase of acquired
knowledge.
St. Thomas himself admits in the present article that he corrects what he
wrote in an earlier work on this subject,[1213] in which he taught that Christ
had knowledge that is essentially acquirable, yet it was not acquired by His own
acts, but was accidentally infused, as in the case of Adam who was created
completely developed. But now St. Thomas maintains that, as it was fitting for
Christ's body to develop gradually, so also it was proper for His soul to
advance gradually in the knowledge of natural things. Hence the Evangelist says:
"Jesus advanced in wisdom and age."[1214]
Theological proof. Nothing that God planted in our nature was wanting to the
human nature of Christ, among which is the active intellect or the connatural
active principle of intellectual knowledge.
But the active intellect would have been useless in Christ, lacking in its
own and special operation, if He did not have knowledge acquired by His own acts
by abstracting intelligible species from phantasms.
Therefore Christ had this knowledge.
Objection. Scotus maintains that the active intellect neither was useless in
Adam, nor is it so in the blessed. The purpose of the active intellect is not
only to abstract species, but it also serves the purpose of illustrating
principles to be made use of in conclusions.
Reply. The Thomists point out that there is a difference between Christ and
Adam, who was created not as a child, but as fully developed, as there is a
difference between Christ and disembodied spirits that no longer have the
connatural mode of understanding by turning to phantasms. If Christ had not
acquired knowledge by repeated acts of the intellect, His active intellect would
have been useless, not absolutely so, but as regards its connatural mode of
operating; for it would be deprived of that act to which it is entitled in such
a state and at such a time.
Moreover, it was no imperfection for Christ that as a child He was deprived
of speech, or that He was unable as yet to acquire perfect knowledge of things.
He already had by the beatific knowledge superabundant cognition for the perfect
knowledge of divine things and of other things in the Word. Therefore Christ in
a certain sense progressed intellectually, but not morally.
The solution of the objections of this article confirms the reply of St.
Thomas.
Reply to first objection. "It was more fitting for Christ to possess a
knowledge acquired by discovery than by being taught", hence He acquired
acquirable knowledge not by learning, but rather by discovery, by a
consideration of nature and men.
Reply to second objection. "It behooved Christ's intellect to be also
perfected with regard to phantasms," although it was already perfected by
infused knowledge. For this is a new and connatural mode of knowing. Someone may
already have certainty of knowledge by the gift of prophecy that death will come
on a certain day; in another way, however, there is experimental knowledge of
the moment of death.
Reply to third objection. There was also a distinction between this acquired
knowledge and infused knowledge concerning sensible things, for this second kind
of knowledge, coming as it does from on high, is not proportioned to phantasms.
Thus he who sings the melody of a musical composition solely from memory, not
having studied music, can afterward in another way know this melody by
distinguishing the various parts and notes of the musical score, reading it even
to the least detail. Previously he knew the musical composition as some general
melody, but now he knows its parts and the way these are distinctly related to
the whole.
Thus, then, it is the common teaching of theologians since the time of Peter
Lombard, that there were three kinds of knowledge in Christ: the beatific,
infused, and acquired knowledge.
Each particular knowledge must now be considered briefly.
CHAPTER XII: QUESTION 10: THE BEATIFIC KNOWLEDGE OF CHRIST'S
SOUL
1) Was it comprehensive? (2) Though not comprehensive, did it extend to all
things; if not to all possible things, at least to all things that God knows by
the knowledge of vision, including even the Judgment Day? (3) Did Christ's soul
know the infinite in the Word? at least those things that are in the
potentiality of the creature, such as the thoughts and affections of immortal
souls, which will never end? (4) Did Christ's soul see the Word clearer than any
other creature did?
First Article: Whether The Soul Of Christ Comprehended The Word
Reply. The answer is in the negative because "the infinite is not
comprehended by the finite."
Reply to second objection. "Christ's soul sees the whole of God's
essence, yet His soul does not see it totally," that is, "not as
perfectly as it is knowable"; for it is infinitely knowable.
The contrary opinion was condemned in the Council of Basel, and this
condemnation was approved by Nicholas V.
Second Article: Whether Christ's Soul Knew All Things In The Word
Reply. Christ's soul did not know in the Word all possible things, but it
knew all present, past, and future things that will be.
Proof of negative part. If Christ's soul knew all possible things, this would
mean that it comprehended all that God can do, which would mean that it
comprehended the divine power, and consequently the divine essence.[1215]
Proof of affirmative part. It may be presented in the following syllogistic
form.
No beatified intellect fails to know in the Word whatever pertains to itself.
But to Christ all things belong, inasmuch as all things are subject to Him, as
the head of the Church, the end of the universe, the Lord of heaven and earth,
the judge of the living and the dead. Therefore Christ's intellect knows in the
Word all things that are subject to Him.
Evidently it belongs to the moral head to know his members and his influence
for them; to one who has knowledge of the end to know the means by which it can
be attained; to the judge to know all things that concern his tribunal, such as
each and every thought of all men; the judge must also know whom to punish, and
whom to reward.
In fact, Christ's soul seems to have not only habitual knowledge but also
actual knowledge of all these things,[1216] like a perfect theologian who not
only could at will successively contemplate all theological conclusions, but who
could simultaneously and actually contemplate all of them. The reason for this
is that the beatific vision, objectively considered, is measured by eternity,
which admits of neither succession nor change. Hence all the thoughts and
actions of angels and men, known by Christ, although as regards their own
duration they are successive, nevertheless are simultaneously present in the
Word, according to the one now of eternity. It is like an intelligible panorama,
just as in the sensible order the visible stars of the firmament are all seen in
one glance. It must be observed that beatific love is likewise measured by
participated eternity, as also Christ's adoration, thanks, and internal offering
of Himself to His Father. Such enduring acts as these constitute, so to speak,
the soul of the sacrifice of the Mass, whose principal priest is Christ as man.
The outstanding difficulty concerns the Judgment Day, inasmuch as we read in
the Gospel that Christ says: "But of that day or hour no man knoweth,
neither the angels of heaven, nor the Son, but the Father."[1217]
Reply to first objection. St. Thomas says: (1) "Arius and Eunomius
understood this saying... of the divine knowledge of the Son, whom they held to
be less than the Father.... But this will not stand, since all things were made
by the Word of God" (John 1:3). Hence, especially inasmuch as Christ is
God, He knew everything. (2) The Son knows also in the human nature the Day of
Judgment, because, as Chrysostom argues (hom. 78 in Matt.); "If it is given
to Christ as man to know how to judge which is greater, much more is it given to
Him to know the less, namely, the time of Judgment" But "He is said
not to know the day and the hour of the Judgment, because He does not make it
known." Pope St. Gregory the Great spoke similarly against the Agnoetae.[1218]
If some of the earlier Fathers spoke less accurately on this subject, this is
because they were disputing with the Arians, to whom they replied: Christ did
not know the Judgment Day, not indeed as God as if they conceded that He did not
know it as man.
The question of the knowledge given to Christ's soul had not yet arisen, and
it had not yet occurred to anyone to distinguish between knowledge acquired
naturally by human efforts, and knowledge not so acquired but received from a
supernatural source, which is not meant to be made known to men.
Reply to second objection. "The soul of Christ knows all things that God
knows in Himself by the knowledge of vision," yet not so clearly and
distinctly.[1219]
Third Article: Whether The Soul Of Christ Can Know The Infinite In The Word
The answer consists of two conclusions.
First conclusion. The soul of Christ does not know the actually infinite;
that is, as is evident from the context, He does not know an actually infinite
multitude of substances, because such a multitude was not created, which was
proved in a previous article,[1220] which stated: Multitude in nature is
created, and everything created is comprehended under some clear intention.
Nevertheless Christ's soul knows in the Word the thoughts and affections of
angels and men. to which there will be no end, that is, they will go on for all
eternity. But this multitude is not actually infinite, since all its parts do
not constitute a simultaneous whole, and it is known, moreover, by Christ's soul
inasmuch as it is represented in a certain unity, namely, in the infinitely
perfect Word.
St. Thomas says: "But as material things can be received by the
intellect immaterially, and many things unitedly, so can infinite things be
received by the intellect, not after the manner of the infinite, but
finitely."[1221] But what is infinite, not materially but in perfection,
can be known, although it cannot be comprehended by Christ's soul, which can
actually and simultaneously know all our thoughts throughout eternity. St.
Thomas, inquiring whether the name "Word" imports relation to
creation, says: "Because God by one act understands Himself and all things,
His one only Word is expressive not only of the Father, but of all
creatures."[1222]
Second conclusion. Christ's soul knows in the Word infinite things that are
in the potentiality of the creature. Thus, as stated in the counter-argument,
"Christ's soul knows all its power and all it can do. It can cleanse,
however, infinite sins."
Fourth Article: Whether Christ's Soul Sees The Word Or The Divine Essence
More Clearly Than Does Any Other Creature
Reply. The answer is in the affirmative. This conclusion is de fide, as His
fullness of grace is.
Scriptural proof. St. Paul says: "God set Christ on His right hand in
the heavenly places, above all Principality and Power and Virtue and Domination,
and every name that is named, not only in this world, but also in that which is
to come."[1223] But this heavenly glory presupposes a more exalted
knowledge of God.
Theological proof. The beatific vision is according to a participation of
light that is derived from the Word of God. But Christ's soul, since it is
united to the Word in person, is more closely associated with the Word than any
other creature, even the angelic. Therefore Christ's soul received a greater
influx of light, and thus sees the divine essence more perfectly.
Reply to second objection. Christ's soul sees the essence of God more clearly
than even the highest of the angels, whose intellect is, nevertheless, naturally
more powerful, because—and of this, Cajetan did not sufficiently take note—"the
vision of the divine essence exceeds the natural power of any creature. And
hence the degrees thereof depend rather on the order of grace, in which Christ
is supreme, than on the order of nature, in which the angelic nature is placed
before the human."[1224] Thus, granted an equal degree of glory, St.
Joseph's soul sees the divine essence just as clearly as the higher angels do.
Hence the beatific vision that belongs to Christ's soul is in the highest
degree, "although, absolutely speaking, there could be a higher and more
sublime degree by the infinity of the divine power."[1225] The highest
possible degree of the light of glory cannot be conceived, because the divine
nature is capable of infinite participation, and there is always an infinite
difference between Christ's beatific vision and the uncreated and comprehensive
vision, not as regards the object, but as regards the mode of cognition or
penetration.
Cajetan seeks to explain the reply to the third objection of St. Thomas by
saying: "If an angel were assumed by the Word of God in unity of person to
an equal degree of glory, the angel would see God more perfectly than Christ's
soul would, and the degree of the beatific vision would be more sublime, not
because of the more sublime light or degree of light, but because of the more
sublime intellect that is equally illumined."[1226] Thus, in Cajetan's
opinion, there can be a more sublime degree of the beatific vision in the angel,
only because the angelic intellect is naturally more powerful than Christ's
human intellect, and therefore transcends it in this order.
A considerable number of the other Thomists do not agree with Cajetan,
especially Alvarez, and they say against Cajetan that St. Thomas in his reply to
the third objection had spoken "of a possibly more sublime degree,"
not in the formal sense, but only materially, which is not his usual way of
speaking. Moreover, they also remark that Cajetan's view would conflict with the
reply to the second objection in which St. Thomas said: "The essentially
supernatural degrees of the vision depend rather on the order of grace... than
on the order of nature."[1227] Therefore, Christ's soul sees God's essence
more clearly than the highest angels do. He received the light of glory in a
degree that was in proportion to the plenitude of His grace, which is derived
from the grace of union.[1228]
CHAPTER XIII: QUESTION II
The Infused Knowledge Of Christ's Soul
It is the knowledge by which Christ's soul knows things outside the Word.
This question considers (1) the object of this knowledge, (2) its acts (a. 2-4),
(3) its habits (a. 5, 6).
First Article: Whether By This Knowledge Christ Knows All Things
State of the question. The word "all" signifies not all possible
things, but all things existing in any period of time, either natural or
supernatural.
The difficulty is that it does not seem to pertain to the perfection of the
human intellect to know things of which there are no phantasms. Therefore it
does not seem that by this infused knowledge Christ knows angels as they are in
themselves, or that He knows all singulars.
Reply. Nevertheless St. Thomas affirms that Christ by infused knowledge knew
all things, both natural and supernatural, namely, all past, present, and future
things; He did not, however, know the divine essence by this knowledge, since
this is the proper object of the beatific vision.
St. Thomas, who is usually both conservative and prudent in his affirmations,
does not fear to make this assertion, although not a few may look upon it as
incredible.
Quasi-scriptural proof. The prophet says of Christ: "The Spirit of
wisdom and understanding, of knowledge and counsel shall fill Him,"[1229]
under which are included all knowable things, both in the speculative and the
practical orders. And Christ had these gifts more perfectly than the angels,
because they were in proportion to the fullness of His grace and charity, and
hence evidently without limitation.
Theological proof. It was fitting that Christ's soul should be entirely
perfect by having all its power reduced to act.
But there is a twofold power in Christ's soul: one is natural for knowing all
natural things, not only by acquired species, but also by infused species;[1230]
the other is obediential for knowing all supernatural things, even by infused
species, as often happens with the saints in this life. Therefore Christ knew
all things by infused knowledge.[1231]
If perfect works of human art are at times most beautiful, how beautiful must
be those of divine art and how sublime must be the spiritual and supernatural
operations of divine goodness, actually in the Blessed Virgin and especially in
Christ Himself !
This article defines most accurately the natural and the obediential powers,
either as regards a natural agent or a supernatural and free agent. Thus the
obediential power is insatiable, that is, it cannot be satisfied, but in Christ
it is reduced to perfect act according to the most fitting purpose of divine
wisdom, as already stated.[1232]
Reply to second objection. As separated souls see themselves and angels by
their essence,[1233] so Christ's soul already in this life saw itself and angels
by His essence, because Christ was both wayfarer and comprehensor. This seems to
us incredible, as if one born blind were told that we have seen by one glance
innumerable stars in the heavens most distant from one another.
Reply to third objection. The knowledge of singulars pertains to the
perfection of practical knowledge. But Christ had fullness of prudence and of
the gift of counsel. This befitted Him, as already stated, because He is judge
of the living and the dead, head of the Church and even of the angels, supreme
Lord of the whole world. It is, indeed, true that He already knew these
singulars because of the beatific vision in the Word, but all comprehensors also
know created things outside the Word.
Confirmation. The angels know all natural things even according to their
individual conditions by means of infused species that are typified in or
derived from the divine essence.[1234] But Christ, by infused knowledge, knows
natural things by means of infused species similarly typified in or derived from
the divine essence, and His cognition is not inferior to angelic cognition. Thus
one who knows a melody merely from memory knows all its notes, although each
successive note has neither been learned nor read, and at times some cannot read
the notes.
These infused species in Christ's soul, although not so universal as the
angelic species since they are proportioned to the vigor of Christ's human
intellect, are not, however, so restricted as those that are abstracted from
sensible things, because they are likenesses derived from the divine essence.
Moreover, the infused light of the gifts of wisdom, understanding, knowledge,
and counsel is of a higher degree in Christ than in the angels, because it is
proportioned to Christ's charity and the fullness of His habitual grace. But
cognition is formally dependent more on light than on species, and thus the
infused faith of angels as wayfarers was of the same species as ours, although
the faith of the angels makes use of species that are infused and not acquired.
First doubt. How does Christ's infused knowledge include future contingent
events and the secrets of hearts?
Reply. It includes these inasmuch as by this knowledge Christ knows the
divine decrees in the terminative sense, not indeed as He knows them by the
beatific knowledge, but through the intermediary of a certain species, which is
a quasi-testimony of God revealing these future contingents and likewise the
secrets of hearts.
Second doubt. Is this infused knowledge of future contingent events
intuitive, just as by the beatific vision they are included in the Word and the
now of eternity, in which futures are already present?
Reply. It is not intuitive. It is, however, called abstractive because it is
measured by discrete time, which is not co-existent with the past and future as
eternity is, which is the measure of beatific knowledge.[1235] Only eternity
comprises all time, and in it future things are known not as future, but as
present.[1236]
Third doubt. Does Christ's soul by means of essentially infused knowledge
have quiddative knowledge of created supernatural gifts, for example, of
sanctifying grace? Expressed more briefly: is it possible, apart from the
beatific vision, to have quiddative knowledge or only analogical knowledge of
sanctifying grace?
This question is of considerable importance, especially in its relation to
the dignity of sanctifying grace.
Reply. The question is disputed among theologians, even among Thomists.
Bannez,[1237] Alvarez,[1238] Lorca, and others deny that the knowledge is
quiddative. They say that Christ's soul by inspired knowledge does not know
sanctifying grace with objective evidence of it but with evidence that rests on
divine testimony, which is objective evidence in the one who testifies. The
reason is that sanctifying grace is intrinsically and essentially supernatural
inasmuch as it is a formal participation of the divine nature as this nature
actually is, and there can be no quiddative knowledge of the formal
participation of any object, unless there is quiddative knowledge of the object
in which there is participation. Thus it is impossible to have quiddative
knowledge of the power of a seed unless there is quiddative knowledge of the
fruit from the seed. The divine essence, however, can be known quiddatively only
by the beatific vision and not by infused knowledge, because no created species
can adequately represent this essence. A fortiori, as these theologians say, the
light of glory cannot be known quiddatively by infused knowledge, because it
transcends any other created light whatever. Therefore, as these theologians
say, this light of glory can be known quiddatively only in the Word, and not
outside the Word. Still more so, according to these theologians, it is
impossible for the soul of Christ by infused knowledge to know quiddatively the
hypostatic union, for this union transcends the order of grace. Thus it was only
by the beatific vision that Christ could have quiddative knowledge of the
hypostatic union. This first opinion, proposed by Bannez, Alvarez, and others,
if not certain, merits a degree of probability, in fact, it is the far more
probable opinion.
Other theologians, however, such as Suarez, and several Thomists, such as the
Salmanticenses, Gonet, John of St. Thomas, and Billuart, maintain that it is
possible for Christ's soul by means of essentially infused knowledge to have
quiddative knowledge of essentially supernatural created gifts. They give as
their reason that these gifts are of limited entity and therefore representable
by a limited infused species, such as the infused species of the angels. This
opinion seems to me not so probable as the first, which is evident from the
following objection.
Objection. These gifts, such as habitual grace and the light of glory,
although they are created and limited, nevertheless are essentially supernatural
and essentially refer to God as He is in Himself. But God cannot, by infused
knowledge, be quiddatively known as He is in Himself. Therefore these gifts
cannot be quiddatively known by infused knowledge.
Reply. These theologians deny the consequence, saying that grace is not a
universal participation, but an analogical participation of the divine nature,
and it suffices to know the existence of the divine essence. This reason does
not appear convincing. They say: "Because the hypostatic union, a property
of which is infused knowledge, is the radical principle of cognition of Christ's
infused knowledge, it suffices that this union be of the same degree of
immateriality and perfection as the above-mentioned supernatural objects."
This confirmation seems insufficient because the radical principle of infused
knowledge does not change the nature of this knowledge, which is specified by
its object, even though the infused light by which Christ's infused knowledge
judges be substantially supernatural, as our faith is, which nevertheless does
not give us quiddative knowledge of sanctifying grace. Hence it does not seem
possible for infused knowledge, which makes use of created species, to have
quiddative knowledge of sanctifying grace as it actually is. Thus the angels in
the state of probation did not have quiddative knowledge of their grace, whereas
on the contrary they already had quiddative knowledge of their angelic nature.
This argument confirms us in saying that Christ already in this life had the
beatific vision for the clear knowledge of His divine nature and personality.
Fourth doubt. Did Christ's soul by means of infused knowledge have evident
cognition of the mystery of the Trinity as to its existence, it being supposed
that only by the beatific vision is there quiddative knowledge of the Deity and
the Trinity?
Reply. Alvarez and Lorca, as also Vasquez, answer in the negative, saying
that the only way such knowledge is evident is from the evidence that is in the
one testifying, inasmuch as the mystery of the Trinity was revealed to Christ's
soul, yet it was not believed but seen by Him, by reason of the beatific vision
He enjoyed, which is above infused knowledge, and this applies equally to the
mystery of the Incarnation. This opinion, if not certain, is most probable.
But other Thomists, such as Gonet, John of St. Thomas, and Billuart, answer
in the affirmative, because, so they say, by means of infused species Christ's
soul outside the Word has knowledge of His beatific vision, the terminus of
which is the Trinity. Thus He had by infused knowledge evidence concerning the
existence of the Trinity, which is of a higher order that that enjoyed by the
one who testifies to it.
It is difficult to prove the truth of this second opinion, since, as we saw
in the solution of the preceding opinion, there is no certainty for its
foundation, inasmuch as it is not certain and is even not probable, that by
infused knowledge Christ's soul could have evident and quiddative knowledge of
sanctifying grace and the light of glory. The possession of the beatific vision
and a quiddative knowledge of the divine essence, of which grace is a formal
participation, are indispensable for a quiddative knowledge of sanctifying
grace, which is the seed of glory.
Second Article: Whether Christ Could Use This Knowledge Without Turning To
Phantasms
Reply. Christ could use this infused knowledge without having to turn to
phantasms. The reason is (1) that by this knowledge He could know separate
substances, such as angels, that cannot be known by means of phantasms; (2) that
Christ was both wayfarer and comprehensor, and the condition of a comprehensor's
soul is for it to be nowise subject to its body, or dependent on it, but
completely to dominate it. Thus Christ could merit even during sleep.
Reply to third objection. "Although the soul of Christ could understand
without turning to phantasms, yet it could also understand by turning to
phantasms," also by means of infused knowledge. This means that Christ
could, as He chose, use this knowledge either by not turning to phantasms or by
turning to them, forming or not forming in the imagination pictures of the same
object as is known by this infused knowledge. Thus in the sensible order one may
be inspired to sing the melody of a musical composition, writing or not writing
the score at one's choice. Similarly one is free to think in one language, and
possibly express one's thoughts in another language.
Corollary. We must take care to distinguish between infused contemplation and
essentially infused knowledge, for this normally functions without having
recourse to the imagination, as in the case of angels and separated souls, as
also by very special favor with certain wayfarers. But infused contemplation,
which is the result of living faith illumined by the gifts of wisdom and
understanding, normally functions with the concurrence of the imagination, which
is the normal manner of sanctification, but it is not infused knowledge.
Third Article: Whether This Knowledge Was Collative Or Discursive
St. Thomas replies that this knowledge was not collative or discursive in its
acquisition, because it was divinely infused and not acquired by a process of
reasoning. But Christ could use this knowledge in a discursive way, like
wayfarers, though He was independent of this discursive process. This means that
He could, like wayfarers, by divers acts of reasoning deduce conclusions from
principles, effects from causes, properties from essences, as men at times who
already know the effects conclude them from their causes, not that they may
learn them anew, but wishing to use the knowledge they have; or as theologians
who at times deduce from some revealed truth another which is otherwise
revealed, and which prior to its deduction is already a certainty of faith. The
reason given by St. Thomas as stated in this article,[1239] is that the
collative and discursive process is connatural to the rational soul, and also to
the souls of the blessed, but not to the angels.
Fourth Article: Whether In Christ This Infused Knowledge Was Greater Than
That Of The Angels
St. Thomas replies that this knowledge in Christ was far more excellent
because of its influencing cause, which is the Word; for the light divinely
infused in the soul of Christ is much more excellent than the natural light of
the angels. So this infused knowledge in Christ was absolutely more certain than
was the infused knowledge of the angels, and extended to many more things,
namely, to all things, even Judgment Day, including everything that pertains to
the supreme judge of the living and the dead, and to the king of the angels.
Nevertheless, in a qualified sense Christ's infused knowledge was inferior to
that of the angels, namely, on the part of the recipient, which is the rational
soul, or as regards the mode of its reception, for, as we stated, Christ could
use this knowledge by turning to phantasms and by having recourse to the
discursive process of reasoning.
Moreover, as stated farther on[1240] it was connatural for Christ's soul to
receive species not so universal in scope as those of the angels. This means
that the species are in proportion to the human intellect which is not so
perfect as the angelic intellect. But if St. Thomas taught the contrary,[1241]
namely, that the infused species in Christ's soul were not so universal in scope
as those of the angels, he clearly reversed his opinion in the sixth article of
this question.
But although the infused knowledge of Christ as regards the mode of its
reception is inferior to the angelic knowledge, this does not prevent it from
being absolutely more exalted. Thus St. Thomas teaches that "faith is
simply more certain than wisdom, the understanding of first principles, and
knowledge; but these three, as denoting evidence, are more certain relatively,
that is, for us."[1242] Similarly it is certain that the faith of the
Blessed Virgin Mary was simply more exalted than the faith of the angels as
wayfarers although she made use of species not so universal in scope; for the
perfection of knowledge depends more on the light than on the species since the
light is the more formal principle.[1243] For the light or the habit adapts
itself to the faculty in the exercise of its act and especially in passing
judgment.
Fifth Article: Whether Christ's Infused Knowledge Was Habitual Or Actual;
That Is, Whether It Was Always In Act
The answer of St. Thomas: "The knowledge imprinted on the soul of Christ
was habitual, for He could use it when He pleased." The reason is that this
knowledge was in Him according to the connatural mode of the human soul, which
is to receive knowledge as a habit that can be used at will. Thus Christ's
infused knowledge was univocal to our knowledge, as stated in the argument and
counter-argument of this article, though it was not univocal in species but in
the genus of knowledge.
Reply to first objection. This infused knowledge of Christ was inferior to
that of the beatific vision, for this latter was always actual with respect to
everything He knew in this way; nevertheless it seems that Christ's infused
knowledge always actually knew certain objects even when He was asleep, during
which times He could merit. Thus Christ's soul in this way always knew itself.
Sixth Article: Whether This Infused Knowledge Of Christ Was Distinguished By
Diverse Habits
St. Thomas affirms that Christ's infused knowledge was distinguished by
different habits, because He made use of species not so universal in scope as
those of the angels, and thus His knowledge was distinguished according to the
different kinds of knowable things.
Downloaded from St. Michael's Depot http://abbey.apana.org.au/Home_Pages/St_Michaels_Depot.htm
|